algebraic geometry for specific fields means no axiom of choice?

The name of the pictureThe name of the pictureThe name of the pictureClash Royale CLAN TAG#URR8PPP











up vote
3
down vote

favorite












I'm beginning to study commutative algebra and algebraic geometry, and something confuses me.



Many proofs, e.g. of the Nullstellensatz, require the axiom of choice (to get the right results about ideals, I suppose). Is there any way to avoid that axiom, if you start with an algebraically closed field that is countable? What about the complex field?



I've been looking for something on this topic on the Internet, with no luck. Thanks for any help!







share|cite|improve this question















  • 1




    If your field is countable, you can probably get away with most things. Do note, however, that it is consistent that $Bbb Q$ has two non-isomorphic algebraic closures (but only one of them is countable). So even that's to be taken with a pinch of salt.
    – Asaf Karagila
    Aug 3 at 17:16














up vote
3
down vote

favorite












I'm beginning to study commutative algebra and algebraic geometry, and something confuses me.



Many proofs, e.g. of the Nullstellensatz, require the axiom of choice (to get the right results about ideals, I suppose). Is there any way to avoid that axiom, if you start with an algebraically closed field that is countable? What about the complex field?



I've been looking for something on this topic on the Internet, with no luck. Thanks for any help!







share|cite|improve this question















  • 1




    If your field is countable, you can probably get away with most things. Do note, however, that it is consistent that $Bbb Q$ has two non-isomorphic algebraic closures (but only one of them is countable). So even that's to be taken with a pinch of salt.
    – Asaf Karagila
    Aug 3 at 17:16












up vote
3
down vote

favorite









up vote
3
down vote

favorite











I'm beginning to study commutative algebra and algebraic geometry, and something confuses me.



Many proofs, e.g. of the Nullstellensatz, require the axiom of choice (to get the right results about ideals, I suppose). Is there any way to avoid that axiom, if you start with an algebraically closed field that is countable? What about the complex field?



I've been looking for something on this topic on the Internet, with no luck. Thanks for any help!







share|cite|improve this question











I'm beginning to study commutative algebra and algebraic geometry, and something confuses me.



Many proofs, e.g. of the Nullstellensatz, require the axiom of choice (to get the right results about ideals, I suppose). Is there any way to avoid that axiom, if you start with an algebraically closed field that is countable? What about the complex field?



I've been looking for something on this topic on the Internet, with no luck. Thanks for any help!









share|cite|improve this question










share|cite|improve this question




share|cite|improve this question









asked Aug 3 at 17:08









Chris Sanders

1,138216




1,138216







  • 1




    If your field is countable, you can probably get away with most things. Do note, however, that it is consistent that $Bbb Q$ has two non-isomorphic algebraic closures (but only one of them is countable). So even that's to be taken with a pinch of salt.
    – Asaf Karagila
    Aug 3 at 17:16












  • 1




    If your field is countable, you can probably get away with most things. Do note, however, that it is consistent that $Bbb Q$ has two non-isomorphic algebraic closures (but only one of them is countable). So even that's to be taken with a pinch of salt.
    – Asaf Karagila
    Aug 3 at 17:16







1




1




If your field is countable, you can probably get away with most things. Do note, however, that it is consistent that $Bbb Q$ has two non-isomorphic algebraic closures (but only one of them is countable). So even that's to be taken with a pinch of salt.
– Asaf Karagila
Aug 3 at 17:16




If your field is countable, you can probably get away with most things. Do note, however, that it is consistent that $Bbb Q$ has two non-isomorphic algebraic closures (but only one of them is countable). So even that's to be taken with a pinch of salt.
– Asaf Karagila
Aug 3 at 17:16










2 Answers
2






active

oldest

votes

















up vote
3
down vote



accepted










The axiom of choice is pretty much never necessary for doing any sort of commutative algebra or algebraic geometry which involves only finitely generated algebras over a field. In particular, any arguments that involve the existence of maximal ideals (or ideals which are maximal with a given property) can be carried out in these rings without invoking the axiom of choice, since they are Noetherian.



To be more precise, without assuming the axiom of choice, you can prove that any polynomial ring in finitely many variables over a field (and therefore also any quotient of such a ring) is Noetherian in the strong sense that any set of ideals contains a maximal element. The proof is a minor modification of the usual proof of the Hilbert basis theorem; you can find it written out in full detail at Existence of a prime ideal in an integral domain of finite type over a field without Axiom of Choice.






share|cite|improve this answer





















  • Hrm... define Noetherian without choice. :-)
    – Asaf Karagila
    Aug 3 at 22:20










  • Right, there are multiple inequivalent definitions. That's why I clarified which definition I was using (namely, the strongest one).
    – Eric Wofsey
    Aug 3 at 22:24










  • Right, yeah, I should have finished reading the answer before I posted the comment. :-P
    – Asaf Karagila
    Aug 3 at 22:24

















up vote
2
down vote













Many applications of choice can be removed when we restrict attention to well-orderable - or even better, countable - fields and other objects. As Asaf says, however, there are nonetheless some facts which really do require the axiom of choice. At the same time, these often have slight weakenings that (a) don't require choice and (b) do everything we really need (e.g. that there is only one countable algebraic closure of $mathbbQ$ up to isomorphism).



You might be concerned at this point about results in "concrete" mathematics which go through principles with no apparent choice-free proof. E.g. is it possible that the Riemann hypothesis could be proved, but only using choice due to its reliance on some "choicey" piece of algebraic geometry? It turns out that there is a very powerful metatheorem which says that the answer is "no:" Shoenfield absoluteness. In particular, this implies that if ZFC proves the Riemann hypothesis, or Goldbach, or Fermat's last theorem, or basically any fact from number theory or "low-level" algebraic geometry, then so does ZF. In fact it says much more: it says e.g. that we can also through arithmetic axioms like GCH onto the pile while still not changing the provability of the Riemann hypothesis. The motto I would give here is that Shoenfield absoluteness shows that number theory doesn't rely on choice.






share|cite|improve this answer





















    Your Answer




    StackExchange.ifUsing("editor", function ()
    return StackExchange.using("mathjaxEditing", function ()
    StackExchange.MarkdownEditor.creationCallbacks.add(function (editor, postfix)
    StackExchange.mathjaxEditing.prepareWmdForMathJax(editor, postfix, [["$", "$"], ["\\(","\\)"]]);
    );
    );
    , "mathjax-editing");

    StackExchange.ready(function()
    var channelOptions =
    tags: "".split(" "),
    id: "69"
    ;
    initTagRenderer("".split(" "), "".split(" "), channelOptions);

    StackExchange.using("externalEditor", function()
    // Have to fire editor after snippets, if snippets enabled
    if (StackExchange.settings.snippets.snippetsEnabled)
    StackExchange.using("snippets", function()
    createEditor();
    );

    else
    createEditor();

    );

    function createEditor()
    StackExchange.prepareEditor(
    heartbeatType: 'answer',
    convertImagesToLinks: true,
    noModals: false,
    showLowRepImageUploadWarning: true,
    reputationToPostImages: 10,
    bindNavPrevention: true,
    postfix: "",
    noCode: true, onDemand: true,
    discardSelector: ".discard-answer"
    ,immediatelyShowMarkdownHelp:true
    );



    );








     

    draft saved


    draft discarded


















    StackExchange.ready(
    function ()
    StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmath.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f2871301%2falgebraic-geometry-for-specific-fields-means-no-axiom-of-choice%23new-answer', 'question_page');

    );

    Post as a guest






























    2 Answers
    2






    active

    oldest

    votes








    2 Answers
    2






    active

    oldest

    votes









    active

    oldest

    votes






    active

    oldest

    votes








    up vote
    3
    down vote



    accepted










    The axiom of choice is pretty much never necessary for doing any sort of commutative algebra or algebraic geometry which involves only finitely generated algebras over a field. In particular, any arguments that involve the existence of maximal ideals (or ideals which are maximal with a given property) can be carried out in these rings without invoking the axiom of choice, since they are Noetherian.



    To be more precise, without assuming the axiom of choice, you can prove that any polynomial ring in finitely many variables over a field (and therefore also any quotient of such a ring) is Noetherian in the strong sense that any set of ideals contains a maximal element. The proof is a minor modification of the usual proof of the Hilbert basis theorem; you can find it written out in full detail at Existence of a prime ideal in an integral domain of finite type over a field without Axiom of Choice.






    share|cite|improve this answer





















    • Hrm... define Noetherian without choice. :-)
      – Asaf Karagila
      Aug 3 at 22:20










    • Right, there are multiple inequivalent definitions. That's why I clarified which definition I was using (namely, the strongest one).
      – Eric Wofsey
      Aug 3 at 22:24










    • Right, yeah, I should have finished reading the answer before I posted the comment. :-P
      – Asaf Karagila
      Aug 3 at 22:24














    up vote
    3
    down vote



    accepted










    The axiom of choice is pretty much never necessary for doing any sort of commutative algebra or algebraic geometry which involves only finitely generated algebras over a field. In particular, any arguments that involve the existence of maximal ideals (or ideals which are maximal with a given property) can be carried out in these rings without invoking the axiom of choice, since they are Noetherian.



    To be more precise, without assuming the axiom of choice, you can prove that any polynomial ring in finitely many variables over a field (and therefore also any quotient of such a ring) is Noetherian in the strong sense that any set of ideals contains a maximal element. The proof is a minor modification of the usual proof of the Hilbert basis theorem; you can find it written out in full detail at Existence of a prime ideal in an integral domain of finite type over a field without Axiom of Choice.






    share|cite|improve this answer





















    • Hrm... define Noetherian without choice. :-)
      – Asaf Karagila
      Aug 3 at 22:20










    • Right, there are multiple inequivalent definitions. That's why I clarified which definition I was using (namely, the strongest one).
      – Eric Wofsey
      Aug 3 at 22:24










    • Right, yeah, I should have finished reading the answer before I posted the comment. :-P
      – Asaf Karagila
      Aug 3 at 22:24












    up vote
    3
    down vote



    accepted







    up vote
    3
    down vote



    accepted






    The axiom of choice is pretty much never necessary for doing any sort of commutative algebra or algebraic geometry which involves only finitely generated algebras over a field. In particular, any arguments that involve the existence of maximal ideals (or ideals which are maximal with a given property) can be carried out in these rings without invoking the axiom of choice, since they are Noetherian.



    To be more precise, without assuming the axiom of choice, you can prove that any polynomial ring in finitely many variables over a field (and therefore also any quotient of such a ring) is Noetherian in the strong sense that any set of ideals contains a maximal element. The proof is a minor modification of the usual proof of the Hilbert basis theorem; you can find it written out in full detail at Existence of a prime ideal in an integral domain of finite type over a field without Axiom of Choice.






    share|cite|improve this answer













    The axiom of choice is pretty much never necessary for doing any sort of commutative algebra or algebraic geometry which involves only finitely generated algebras over a field. In particular, any arguments that involve the existence of maximal ideals (or ideals which are maximal with a given property) can be carried out in these rings without invoking the axiom of choice, since they are Noetherian.



    To be more precise, without assuming the axiom of choice, you can prove that any polynomial ring in finitely many variables over a field (and therefore also any quotient of such a ring) is Noetherian in the strong sense that any set of ideals contains a maximal element. The proof is a minor modification of the usual proof of the Hilbert basis theorem; you can find it written out in full detail at Existence of a prime ideal in an integral domain of finite type over a field without Axiom of Choice.







    share|cite|improve this answer













    share|cite|improve this answer



    share|cite|improve this answer











    answered Aug 3 at 21:30









    Eric Wofsey

    161k12188297




    161k12188297











    • Hrm... define Noetherian without choice. :-)
      – Asaf Karagila
      Aug 3 at 22:20










    • Right, there are multiple inequivalent definitions. That's why I clarified which definition I was using (namely, the strongest one).
      – Eric Wofsey
      Aug 3 at 22:24










    • Right, yeah, I should have finished reading the answer before I posted the comment. :-P
      – Asaf Karagila
      Aug 3 at 22:24
















    • Hrm... define Noetherian without choice. :-)
      – Asaf Karagila
      Aug 3 at 22:20










    • Right, there are multiple inequivalent definitions. That's why I clarified which definition I was using (namely, the strongest one).
      – Eric Wofsey
      Aug 3 at 22:24










    • Right, yeah, I should have finished reading the answer before I posted the comment. :-P
      – Asaf Karagila
      Aug 3 at 22:24















    Hrm... define Noetherian without choice. :-)
    – Asaf Karagila
    Aug 3 at 22:20




    Hrm... define Noetherian without choice. :-)
    – Asaf Karagila
    Aug 3 at 22:20












    Right, there are multiple inequivalent definitions. That's why I clarified which definition I was using (namely, the strongest one).
    – Eric Wofsey
    Aug 3 at 22:24




    Right, there are multiple inequivalent definitions. That's why I clarified which definition I was using (namely, the strongest one).
    – Eric Wofsey
    Aug 3 at 22:24












    Right, yeah, I should have finished reading the answer before I posted the comment. :-P
    – Asaf Karagila
    Aug 3 at 22:24




    Right, yeah, I should have finished reading the answer before I posted the comment. :-P
    – Asaf Karagila
    Aug 3 at 22:24










    up vote
    2
    down vote













    Many applications of choice can be removed when we restrict attention to well-orderable - or even better, countable - fields and other objects. As Asaf says, however, there are nonetheless some facts which really do require the axiom of choice. At the same time, these often have slight weakenings that (a) don't require choice and (b) do everything we really need (e.g. that there is only one countable algebraic closure of $mathbbQ$ up to isomorphism).



    You might be concerned at this point about results in "concrete" mathematics which go through principles with no apparent choice-free proof. E.g. is it possible that the Riemann hypothesis could be proved, but only using choice due to its reliance on some "choicey" piece of algebraic geometry? It turns out that there is a very powerful metatheorem which says that the answer is "no:" Shoenfield absoluteness. In particular, this implies that if ZFC proves the Riemann hypothesis, or Goldbach, or Fermat's last theorem, or basically any fact from number theory or "low-level" algebraic geometry, then so does ZF. In fact it says much more: it says e.g. that we can also through arithmetic axioms like GCH onto the pile while still not changing the provability of the Riemann hypothesis. The motto I would give here is that Shoenfield absoluteness shows that number theory doesn't rely on choice.






    share|cite|improve this answer

























      up vote
      2
      down vote













      Many applications of choice can be removed when we restrict attention to well-orderable - or even better, countable - fields and other objects. As Asaf says, however, there are nonetheless some facts which really do require the axiom of choice. At the same time, these often have slight weakenings that (a) don't require choice and (b) do everything we really need (e.g. that there is only one countable algebraic closure of $mathbbQ$ up to isomorphism).



      You might be concerned at this point about results in "concrete" mathematics which go through principles with no apparent choice-free proof. E.g. is it possible that the Riemann hypothesis could be proved, but only using choice due to its reliance on some "choicey" piece of algebraic geometry? It turns out that there is a very powerful metatheorem which says that the answer is "no:" Shoenfield absoluteness. In particular, this implies that if ZFC proves the Riemann hypothesis, or Goldbach, or Fermat's last theorem, or basically any fact from number theory or "low-level" algebraic geometry, then so does ZF. In fact it says much more: it says e.g. that we can also through arithmetic axioms like GCH onto the pile while still not changing the provability of the Riemann hypothesis. The motto I would give here is that Shoenfield absoluteness shows that number theory doesn't rely on choice.






      share|cite|improve this answer























        up vote
        2
        down vote










        up vote
        2
        down vote









        Many applications of choice can be removed when we restrict attention to well-orderable - or even better, countable - fields and other objects. As Asaf says, however, there are nonetheless some facts which really do require the axiom of choice. At the same time, these often have slight weakenings that (a) don't require choice and (b) do everything we really need (e.g. that there is only one countable algebraic closure of $mathbbQ$ up to isomorphism).



        You might be concerned at this point about results in "concrete" mathematics which go through principles with no apparent choice-free proof. E.g. is it possible that the Riemann hypothesis could be proved, but only using choice due to its reliance on some "choicey" piece of algebraic geometry? It turns out that there is a very powerful metatheorem which says that the answer is "no:" Shoenfield absoluteness. In particular, this implies that if ZFC proves the Riemann hypothesis, or Goldbach, or Fermat's last theorem, or basically any fact from number theory or "low-level" algebraic geometry, then so does ZF. In fact it says much more: it says e.g. that we can also through arithmetic axioms like GCH onto the pile while still not changing the provability of the Riemann hypothesis. The motto I would give here is that Shoenfield absoluteness shows that number theory doesn't rely on choice.






        share|cite|improve this answer













        Many applications of choice can be removed when we restrict attention to well-orderable - or even better, countable - fields and other objects. As Asaf says, however, there are nonetheless some facts which really do require the axiom of choice. At the same time, these often have slight weakenings that (a) don't require choice and (b) do everything we really need (e.g. that there is only one countable algebraic closure of $mathbbQ$ up to isomorphism).



        You might be concerned at this point about results in "concrete" mathematics which go through principles with no apparent choice-free proof. E.g. is it possible that the Riemann hypothesis could be proved, but only using choice due to its reliance on some "choicey" piece of algebraic geometry? It turns out that there is a very powerful metatheorem which says that the answer is "no:" Shoenfield absoluteness. In particular, this implies that if ZFC proves the Riemann hypothesis, or Goldbach, or Fermat's last theorem, or basically any fact from number theory or "low-level" algebraic geometry, then so does ZF. In fact it says much more: it says e.g. that we can also through arithmetic axioms like GCH onto the pile while still not changing the provability of the Riemann hypothesis. The motto I would give here is that Shoenfield absoluteness shows that number theory doesn't rely on choice.







        share|cite|improve this answer













        share|cite|improve this answer



        share|cite|improve this answer











        answered Aug 3 at 18:02









        Noah Schweber

        110k9138259




        110k9138259






















             

            draft saved


            draft discarded


























             


            draft saved


            draft discarded














            StackExchange.ready(
            function ()
            StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmath.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f2871301%2falgebraic-geometry-for-specific-fields-means-no-axiom-of-choice%23new-answer', 'question_page');

            );

            Post as a guest













































































            Comments

            Popular posts from this blog

            What is the equation of a 3D cone with generalised tilt?

            Color the edges and diagonals of a regular polygon

            Relationship between determinant of matrix and determinant of adjoint?