Confusion about countability [closed]

The name of the pictureThe name of the pictureThe name of the pictureClash Royale CLAN TAG#URR8PPP











up vote
1
down vote

favorite












$(0, 1)$ can be proved uncountable by using Cantor's diagonalization argument. It shows there are real numbers not in the list $(x_1, x_2...)$, where $x_n=0.a_n1a_n2...$, a decimal expansion of $x_n$. I think I do not quite understand the proof since I'm not very convinced by it and it's clearly a right proof. I feel it somehow not explicitly showed that there don't exist any bijection function from $(0,1)$ to $mathbbN$. I feel the proof is showing that since every natural number is already corresponding to a $x_n$, there are not place for anything else. And since both $mathbbZ$ and $mathbbQ$ are countable, then all the natural numbers are already corresponding to $mathbbZ$, but we can still insert the rational numbers that are not integer to corresponding to some natural numbers.What's the difference here? Can someone help me clear my mind? Thank ahead.







share|cite|improve this question













closed as off-topic by Andrés E. Caicedo, Lord Shark the Unknown, Xander Henderson, Shailesh, José Carlos Santos Jul 27 at 16:45


This question appears to be off-topic. The users who voted to close gave this specific reason:


  • "This question is missing context or other details: Please improve the question by providing additional context, which ideally includes your thoughts on the problem and any attempts you have made to solve it. This information helps others identify where you have difficulties and helps them write answers appropriate to your experience level." – Xander Henderson, Shailesh
If this question can be reworded to fit the rules in the help center, please edit the question.








  • 1




    The proof is definitely not direct. One assumes there is a bijection from $mathbfN$ to $(0,1)$ and writes $x_n$ for the image of the natural number $n$ under this function. Then a contradiction is derived using decimal expansions of the numbers $x_n$, $ngeq 1$.
    – Keenan Kidwell
    Jul 27 at 3:38










  • I think this exact same point of confusion has been covered in earlier posts about Canto's diagonalization argument. Did you search the site?
    – Jyrki Lahtonen
    Jul 27 at 6:07














up vote
1
down vote

favorite












$(0, 1)$ can be proved uncountable by using Cantor's diagonalization argument. It shows there are real numbers not in the list $(x_1, x_2...)$, where $x_n=0.a_n1a_n2...$, a decimal expansion of $x_n$. I think I do not quite understand the proof since I'm not very convinced by it and it's clearly a right proof. I feel it somehow not explicitly showed that there don't exist any bijection function from $(0,1)$ to $mathbbN$. I feel the proof is showing that since every natural number is already corresponding to a $x_n$, there are not place for anything else. And since both $mathbbZ$ and $mathbbQ$ are countable, then all the natural numbers are already corresponding to $mathbbZ$, but we can still insert the rational numbers that are not integer to corresponding to some natural numbers.What's the difference here? Can someone help me clear my mind? Thank ahead.







share|cite|improve this question













closed as off-topic by Andrés E. Caicedo, Lord Shark the Unknown, Xander Henderson, Shailesh, José Carlos Santos Jul 27 at 16:45


This question appears to be off-topic. The users who voted to close gave this specific reason:


  • "This question is missing context or other details: Please improve the question by providing additional context, which ideally includes your thoughts on the problem and any attempts you have made to solve it. This information helps others identify where you have difficulties and helps them write answers appropriate to your experience level." – Xander Henderson, Shailesh
If this question can be reworded to fit the rules in the help center, please edit the question.








  • 1




    The proof is definitely not direct. One assumes there is a bijection from $mathbfN$ to $(0,1)$ and writes $x_n$ for the image of the natural number $n$ under this function. Then a contradiction is derived using decimal expansions of the numbers $x_n$, $ngeq 1$.
    – Keenan Kidwell
    Jul 27 at 3:38










  • I think this exact same point of confusion has been covered in earlier posts about Canto's diagonalization argument. Did you search the site?
    – Jyrki Lahtonen
    Jul 27 at 6:07












up vote
1
down vote

favorite









up vote
1
down vote

favorite











$(0, 1)$ can be proved uncountable by using Cantor's diagonalization argument. It shows there are real numbers not in the list $(x_1, x_2...)$, where $x_n=0.a_n1a_n2...$, a decimal expansion of $x_n$. I think I do not quite understand the proof since I'm not very convinced by it and it's clearly a right proof. I feel it somehow not explicitly showed that there don't exist any bijection function from $(0,1)$ to $mathbbN$. I feel the proof is showing that since every natural number is already corresponding to a $x_n$, there are not place for anything else. And since both $mathbbZ$ and $mathbbQ$ are countable, then all the natural numbers are already corresponding to $mathbbZ$, but we can still insert the rational numbers that are not integer to corresponding to some natural numbers.What's the difference here? Can someone help me clear my mind? Thank ahead.







share|cite|improve this question













$(0, 1)$ can be proved uncountable by using Cantor's diagonalization argument. It shows there are real numbers not in the list $(x_1, x_2...)$, where $x_n=0.a_n1a_n2...$, a decimal expansion of $x_n$. I think I do not quite understand the proof since I'm not very convinced by it and it's clearly a right proof. I feel it somehow not explicitly showed that there don't exist any bijection function from $(0,1)$ to $mathbbN$. I feel the proof is showing that since every natural number is already corresponding to a $x_n$, there are not place for anything else. And since both $mathbbZ$ and $mathbbQ$ are countable, then all the natural numbers are already corresponding to $mathbbZ$, but we can still insert the rational numbers that are not integer to corresponding to some natural numbers.What's the difference here? Can someone help me clear my mind? Thank ahead.









share|cite|improve this question












share|cite|improve this question




share|cite|improve this question








edited Jul 27 at 3:44
























asked Jul 27 at 3:30









Cathy

1067




1067




closed as off-topic by Andrés E. Caicedo, Lord Shark the Unknown, Xander Henderson, Shailesh, José Carlos Santos Jul 27 at 16:45


This question appears to be off-topic. The users who voted to close gave this specific reason:


  • "This question is missing context or other details: Please improve the question by providing additional context, which ideally includes your thoughts on the problem and any attempts you have made to solve it. This information helps others identify where you have difficulties and helps them write answers appropriate to your experience level." – Xander Henderson, Shailesh
If this question can be reworded to fit the rules in the help center, please edit the question.




closed as off-topic by Andrés E. Caicedo, Lord Shark the Unknown, Xander Henderson, Shailesh, José Carlos Santos Jul 27 at 16:45


This question appears to be off-topic. The users who voted to close gave this specific reason:


  • "This question is missing context or other details: Please improve the question by providing additional context, which ideally includes your thoughts on the problem and any attempts you have made to solve it. This information helps others identify where you have difficulties and helps them write answers appropriate to your experience level." – Xander Henderson, Shailesh
If this question can be reworded to fit the rules in the help center, please edit the question.







  • 1




    The proof is definitely not direct. One assumes there is a bijection from $mathbfN$ to $(0,1)$ and writes $x_n$ for the image of the natural number $n$ under this function. Then a contradiction is derived using decimal expansions of the numbers $x_n$, $ngeq 1$.
    – Keenan Kidwell
    Jul 27 at 3:38










  • I think this exact same point of confusion has been covered in earlier posts about Canto's diagonalization argument. Did you search the site?
    – Jyrki Lahtonen
    Jul 27 at 6:07












  • 1




    The proof is definitely not direct. One assumes there is a bijection from $mathbfN$ to $(0,1)$ and writes $x_n$ for the image of the natural number $n$ under this function. Then a contradiction is derived using decimal expansions of the numbers $x_n$, $ngeq 1$.
    – Keenan Kidwell
    Jul 27 at 3:38










  • I think this exact same point of confusion has been covered in earlier posts about Canto's diagonalization argument. Did you search the site?
    – Jyrki Lahtonen
    Jul 27 at 6:07







1




1




The proof is definitely not direct. One assumes there is a bijection from $mathbfN$ to $(0,1)$ and writes $x_n$ for the image of the natural number $n$ under this function. Then a contradiction is derived using decimal expansions of the numbers $x_n$, $ngeq 1$.
– Keenan Kidwell
Jul 27 at 3:38




The proof is definitely not direct. One assumes there is a bijection from $mathbfN$ to $(0,1)$ and writes $x_n$ for the image of the natural number $n$ under this function. Then a contradiction is derived using decimal expansions of the numbers $x_n$, $ngeq 1$.
– Keenan Kidwell
Jul 27 at 3:38












I think this exact same point of confusion has been covered in earlier posts about Canto's diagonalization argument. Did you search the site?
– Jyrki Lahtonen
Jul 27 at 6:07




I think this exact same point of confusion has been covered in earlier posts about Canto's diagonalization argument. Did you search the site?
– Jyrki Lahtonen
Jul 27 at 6:07










2 Answers
2






active

oldest

votes

















up vote
3
down vote



accepted










In a nutshell, Cantor's argument was to show there cannot be a surjection from $mathbbN$ to $(0,1)$. E.g. no matter what map you give me, there is always some real number that your map from the naturals does not hit. However, for the naturals to the rationals there are many surjective and bijective maps from $mathbbN rightarrow mathbbQ$.



In addition, cardinality is an equivalence relation e.g. if $|A| = |B|$ and $|B| = |C|$, we see $|A| = |C|$. By using this we see by Cantor's argument that there is no map from ANY countable set to $(0,1)$, which bisects to $mathbbR$.



Here's the intuition of why there is at least one real number not in the range of any map from $mathbbN rightarrow (0,1)$.



Assume $(0,1)$ is countable, then we can list every element out, which is the hallmark of countable sets. E.g. for every $x in (0,1)$ there is some $n$ such that $x=$ $x_n = 0.k_1k_2k_3.....$.



Now on our "$n^th$" digit of $x_n$ set $m_n = k_n + 1$ (with $9+1$ being sent to $0$). Then consider $gamma = 0.m_1m_2m_3...m_n....$, clearly $gamma$ is a real number. At the same time $gamma$ is different from every $x_n$ because it differs by every $x_n$ by at least one digit. Therefore, $gamma$ is not in $(0,1)$ as we assumed every $x in (0,1)$, we can write out as $x_n$ for some $n$, but we showed $
gamma$ is not on that list! But it clearly is also in $(0,1)$. Hence, we found a real number on $(0,1)$ that is not in our list, so we see no matter for what mapping we give, we cannot have a surjection from $mathbbN rightarrow (0,1)$. Therefore, it cannot be a bijection. Then by the equivalence class as $|(0,1)| = |mathbbR|$, we see the result follows.






share|cite|improve this answer























  • Thanks, but I still didn't quite understand how Cantor's argument shows there cannot be a surjection from N to (0, 1). I know how the proof goes, but not know how the process in the proof proved there cannot be such a surjection.
    – Cathy
    Jul 27 at 5:48










  • It's somehow seems to me that it denied one kind of mapping not all kinds of mapping from N to (0, 1). Where I am wrong?
    – Cathy
    Jul 27 at 5:59






  • 1




    Well, I guess another way of looking at this proof is that no matter what countable subset of $(0,1)$ that you give me, I can always find a number not in your countable subset (in particular the $gamma$). Therefore, $(0,1)$ is not countable; otherwise, there would be a countable subset that contained the entire interval.
    – Raymond Chu
    Jul 27 at 6:16

















up vote
0
down vote













You're right, it does show that there is not a "place" for the number created from diagonalization. So this conclusion is stating the bijection we assumed we had was not really a bijection since it missed a number. They are logically equivalent statements.



I don't quite understand the second half of your question.






share|cite|improve this answer




























    2 Answers
    2






    active

    oldest

    votes








    2 Answers
    2






    active

    oldest

    votes









    active

    oldest

    votes






    active

    oldest

    votes








    up vote
    3
    down vote



    accepted










    In a nutshell, Cantor's argument was to show there cannot be a surjection from $mathbbN$ to $(0,1)$. E.g. no matter what map you give me, there is always some real number that your map from the naturals does not hit. However, for the naturals to the rationals there are many surjective and bijective maps from $mathbbN rightarrow mathbbQ$.



    In addition, cardinality is an equivalence relation e.g. if $|A| = |B|$ and $|B| = |C|$, we see $|A| = |C|$. By using this we see by Cantor's argument that there is no map from ANY countable set to $(0,1)$, which bisects to $mathbbR$.



    Here's the intuition of why there is at least one real number not in the range of any map from $mathbbN rightarrow (0,1)$.



    Assume $(0,1)$ is countable, then we can list every element out, which is the hallmark of countable sets. E.g. for every $x in (0,1)$ there is some $n$ such that $x=$ $x_n = 0.k_1k_2k_3.....$.



    Now on our "$n^th$" digit of $x_n$ set $m_n = k_n + 1$ (with $9+1$ being sent to $0$). Then consider $gamma = 0.m_1m_2m_3...m_n....$, clearly $gamma$ is a real number. At the same time $gamma$ is different from every $x_n$ because it differs by every $x_n$ by at least one digit. Therefore, $gamma$ is not in $(0,1)$ as we assumed every $x in (0,1)$, we can write out as $x_n$ for some $n$, but we showed $
    gamma$ is not on that list! But it clearly is also in $(0,1)$. Hence, we found a real number on $(0,1)$ that is not in our list, so we see no matter for what mapping we give, we cannot have a surjection from $mathbbN rightarrow (0,1)$. Therefore, it cannot be a bijection. Then by the equivalence class as $|(0,1)| = |mathbbR|$, we see the result follows.






    share|cite|improve this answer























    • Thanks, but I still didn't quite understand how Cantor's argument shows there cannot be a surjection from N to (0, 1). I know how the proof goes, but not know how the process in the proof proved there cannot be such a surjection.
      – Cathy
      Jul 27 at 5:48










    • It's somehow seems to me that it denied one kind of mapping not all kinds of mapping from N to (0, 1). Where I am wrong?
      – Cathy
      Jul 27 at 5:59






    • 1




      Well, I guess another way of looking at this proof is that no matter what countable subset of $(0,1)$ that you give me, I can always find a number not in your countable subset (in particular the $gamma$). Therefore, $(0,1)$ is not countable; otherwise, there would be a countable subset that contained the entire interval.
      – Raymond Chu
      Jul 27 at 6:16














    up vote
    3
    down vote



    accepted










    In a nutshell, Cantor's argument was to show there cannot be a surjection from $mathbbN$ to $(0,1)$. E.g. no matter what map you give me, there is always some real number that your map from the naturals does not hit. However, for the naturals to the rationals there are many surjective and bijective maps from $mathbbN rightarrow mathbbQ$.



    In addition, cardinality is an equivalence relation e.g. if $|A| = |B|$ and $|B| = |C|$, we see $|A| = |C|$. By using this we see by Cantor's argument that there is no map from ANY countable set to $(0,1)$, which bisects to $mathbbR$.



    Here's the intuition of why there is at least one real number not in the range of any map from $mathbbN rightarrow (0,1)$.



    Assume $(0,1)$ is countable, then we can list every element out, which is the hallmark of countable sets. E.g. for every $x in (0,1)$ there is some $n$ such that $x=$ $x_n = 0.k_1k_2k_3.....$.



    Now on our "$n^th$" digit of $x_n$ set $m_n = k_n + 1$ (with $9+1$ being sent to $0$). Then consider $gamma = 0.m_1m_2m_3...m_n....$, clearly $gamma$ is a real number. At the same time $gamma$ is different from every $x_n$ because it differs by every $x_n$ by at least one digit. Therefore, $gamma$ is not in $(0,1)$ as we assumed every $x in (0,1)$, we can write out as $x_n$ for some $n$, but we showed $
    gamma$ is not on that list! But it clearly is also in $(0,1)$. Hence, we found a real number on $(0,1)$ that is not in our list, so we see no matter for what mapping we give, we cannot have a surjection from $mathbbN rightarrow (0,1)$. Therefore, it cannot be a bijection. Then by the equivalence class as $|(0,1)| = |mathbbR|$, we see the result follows.






    share|cite|improve this answer























    • Thanks, but I still didn't quite understand how Cantor's argument shows there cannot be a surjection from N to (0, 1). I know how the proof goes, but not know how the process in the proof proved there cannot be such a surjection.
      – Cathy
      Jul 27 at 5:48










    • It's somehow seems to me that it denied one kind of mapping not all kinds of mapping from N to (0, 1). Where I am wrong?
      – Cathy
      Jul 27 at 5:59






    • 1




      Well, I guess another way of looking at this proof is that no matter what countable subset of $(0,1)$ that you give me, I can always find a number not in your countable subset (in particular the $gamma$). Therefore, $(0,1)$ is not countable; otherwise, there would be a countable subset that contained the entire interval.
      – Raymond Chu
      Jul 27 at 6:16












    up vote
    3
    down vote



    accepted







    up vote
    3
    down vote



    accepted






    In a nutshell, Cantor's argument was to show there cannot be a surjection from $mathbbN$ to $(0,1)$. E.g. no matter what map you give me, there is always some real number that your map from the naturals does not hit. However, for the naturals to the rationals there are many surjective and bijective maps from $mathbbN rightarrow mathbbQ$.



    In addition, cardinality is an equivalence relation e.g. if $|A| = |B|$ and $|B| = |C|$, we see $|A| = |C|$. By using this we see by Cantor's argument that there is no map from ANY countable set to $(0,1)$, which bisects to $mathbbR$.



    Here's the intuition of why there is at least one real number not in the range of any map from $mathbbN rightarrow (0,1)$.



    Assume $(0,1)$ is countable, then we can list every element out, which is the hallmark of countable sets. E.g. for every $x in (0,1)$ there is some $n$ such that $x=$ $x_n = 0.k_1k_2k_3.....$.



    Now on our "$n^th$" digit of $x_n$ set $m_n = k_n + 1$ (with $9+1$ being sent to $0$). Then consider $gamma = 0.m_1m_2m_3...m_n....$, clearly $gamma$ is a real number. At the same time $gamma$ is different from every $x_n$ because it differs by every $x_n$ by at least one digit. Therefore, $gamma$ is not in $(0,1)$ as we assumed every $x in (0,1)$, we can write out as $x_n$ for some $n$, but we showed $
    gamma$ is not on that list! But it clearly is also in $(0,1)$. Hence, we found a real number on $(0,1)$ that is not in our list, so we see no matter for what mapping we give, we cannot have a surjection from $mathbbN rightarrow (0,1)$. Therefore, it cannot be a bijection. Then by the equivalence class as $|(0,1)| = |mathbbR|$, we see the result follows.






    share|cite|improve this answer















    In a nutshell, Cantor's argument was to show there cannot be a surjection from $mathbbN$ to $(0,1)$. E.g. no matter what map you give me, there is always some real number that your map from the naturals does not hit. However, for the naturals to the rationals there are many surjective and bijective maps from $mathbbN rightarrow mathbbQ$.



    In addition, cardinality is an equivalence relation e.g. if $|A| = |B|$ and $|B| = |C|$, we see $|A| = |C|$. By using this we see by Cantor's argument that there is no map from ANY countable set to $(0,1)$, which bisects to $mathbbR$.



    Here's the intuition of why there is at least one real number not in the range of any map from $mathbbN rightarrow (0,1)$.



    Assume $(0,1)$ is countable, then we can list every element out, which is the hallmark of countable sets. E.g. for every $x in (0,1)$ there is some $n$ such that $x=$ $x_n = 0.k_1k_2k_3.....$.



    Now on our "$n^th$" digit of $x_n$ set $m_n = k_n + 1$ (with $9+1$ being sent to $0$). Then consider $gamma = 0.m_1m_2m_3...m_n....$, clearly $gamma$ is a real number. At the same time $gamma$ is different from every $x_n$ because it differs by every $x_n$ by at least one digit. Therefore, $gamma$ is not in $(0,1)$ as we assumed every $x in (0,1)$, we can write out as $x_n$ for some $n$, but we showed $
    gamma$ is not on that list! But it clearly is also in $(0,1)$. Hence, we found a real number on $(0,1)$ that is not in our list, so we see no matter for what mapping we give, we cannot have a surjection from $mathbbN rightarrow (0,1)$. Therefore, it cannot be a bijection. Then by the equivalence class as $|(0,1)| = |mathbbR|$, we see the result follows.







    share|cite|improve this answer















    share|cite|improve this answer



    share|cite|improve this answer








    edited Jul 27 at 3:46


























    answered Jul 27 at 3:39









    Raymond Chu

    1,02219




    1,02219











    • Thanks, but I still didn't quite understand how Cantor's argument shows there cannot be a surjection from N to (0, 1). I know how the proof goes, but not know how the process in the proof proved there cannot be such a surjection.
      – Cathy
      Jul 27 at 5:48










    • It's somehow seems to me that it denied one kind of mapping not all kinds of mapping from N to (0, 1). Where I am wrong?
      – Cathy
      Jul 27 at 5:59






    • 1




      Well, I guess another way of looking at this proof is that no matter what countable subset of $(0,1)$ that you give me, I can always find a number not in your countable subset (in particular the $gamma$). Therefore, $(0,1)$ is not countable; otherwise, there would be a countable subset that contained the entire interval.
      – Raymond Chu
      Jul 27 at 6:16
















    • Thanks, but I still didn't quite understand how Cantor's argument shows there cannot be a surjection from N to (0, 1). I know how the proof goes, but not know how the process in the proof proved there cannot be such a surjection.
      – Cathy
      Jul 27 at 5:48










    • It's somehow seems to me that it denied one kind of mapping not all kinds of mapping from N to (0, 1). Where I am wrong?
      – Cathy
      Jul 27 at 5:59






    • 1




      Well, I guess another way of looking at this proof is that no matter what countable subset of $(0,1)$ that you give me, I can always find a number not in your countable subset (in particular the $gamma$). Therefore, $(0,1)$ is not countable; otherwise, there would be a countable subset that contained the entire interval.
      – Raymond Chu
      Jul 27 at 6:16















    Thanks, but I still didn't quite understand how Cantor's argument shows there cannot be a surjection from N to (0, 1). I know how the proof goes, but not know how the process in the proof proved there cannot be such a surjection.
    – Cathy
    Jul 27 at 5:48




    Thanks, but I still didn't quite understand how Cantor's argument shows there cannot be a surjection from N to (0, 1). I know how the proof goes, but not know how the process in the proof proved there cannot be such a surjection.
    – Cathy
    Jul 27 at 5:48












    It's somehow seems to me that it denied one kind of mapping not all kinds of mapping from N to (0, 1). Where I am wrong?
    – Cathy
    Jul 27 at 5:59




    It's somehow seems to me that it denied one kind of mapping not all kinds of mapping from N to (0, 1). Where I am wrong?
    – Cathy
    Jul 27 at 5:59




    1




    1




    Well, I guess another way of looking at this proof is that no matter what countable subset of $(0,1)$ that you give me, I can always find a number not in your countable subset (in particular the $gamma$). Therefore, $(0,1)$ is not countable; otherwise, there would be a countable subset that contained the entire interval.
    – Raymond Chu
    Jul 27 at 6:16




    Well, I guess another way of looking at this proof is that no matter what countable subset of $(0,1)$ that you give me, I can always find a number not in your countable subset (in particular the $gamma$). Therefore, $(0,1)$ is not countable; otherwise, there would be a countable subset that contained the entire interval.
    – Raymond Chu
    Jul 27 at 6:16










    up vote
    0
    down vote













    You're right, it does show that there is not a "place" for the number created from diagonalization. So this conclusion is stating the bijection we assumed we had was not really a bijection since it missed a number. They are logically equivalent statements.



    I don't quite understand the second half of your question.






    share|cite|improve this answer

























      up vote
      0
      down vote













      You're right, it does show that there is not a "place" for the number created from diagonalization. So this conclusion is stating the bijection we assumed we had was not really a bijection since it missed a number. They are logically equivalent statements.



      I don't quite understand the second half of your question.






      share|cite|improve this answer























        up vote
        0
        down vote










        up vote
        0
        down vote









        You're right, it does show that there is not a "place" for the number created from diagonalization. So this conclusion is stating the bijection we assumed we had was not really a bijection since it missed a number. They are logically equivalent statements.



        I don't quite understand the second half of your question.






        share|cite|improve this answer













        You're right, it does show that there is not a "place" for the number created from diagonalization. So this conclusion is stating the bijection we assumed we had was not really a bijection since it missed a number. They are logically equivalent statements.



        I don't quite understand the second half of your question.







        share|cite|improve this answer













        share|cite|improve this answer



        share|cite|improve this answer











        answered Jul 27 at 3:39









        El Gallo Negro

        233




        233












            Comments

            Popular posts from this blog

            What is the equation of a 3D cone with generalised tilt?

            Color the edges and diagonals of a regular polygon

            Relationship between determinant of matrix and determinant of adjoint?