How can we identify a set is infinite when proving Bolzano–Weierstrass theorem?

The name of the pictureThe name of the pictureThe name of the pictureClash Royale CLAN TAG#URR8PPP











up vote
7
down vote

favorite












I'm proving the Bolzano–Weierstrass theorem. It says



$$
textIf A text : bounded and infinite set, text then A text has at least one limit point.
$$



So the proof goes like the following.



Since $A subset mathbbR^N$ is bounded, it can be a subset of a box $B_1 = I_1 times cdots times I_N$, where $I_i$ is an interval in $mathbbR$. Let's divide the $B_1$ into $2^N$ sub-boxes. Then, at least one sub-box has the infinite elements of $A$. Let's say that sub-box as $B_2$. Let's say we can repeat this procedure for $B_3, B_4, ldots$



Well, so proof ends as we prove some $x$ exists in $cap_n=1^inftyB_n$ and it is a limit point of $A$.



But what I'm wondering is, how can we identify the $B_2$? (and $B_3$, and so on)



Yes, it's clear to me that such set exists, but the existence itself does not guarantee us to identify the set (that is, to select and label it as $B_2$), since we don't have any tools to discern if $B_2$ is infinite or not.



It sounds a little bit philosophical, but is there anyone to help?







share|cite|improve this question





















  • You say at least one sub-box has. Also there is a missing step somewhere, the highest $B_k$ mentioned is $B_2$ but you then write $xin cap_nB_n$ we don't know what any $B_k, k>2$ is at this point.
    – mathreadler
    Jul 28 at 7:53







  • 3




    What do you mean exactly by "identify"? And why do we need to do so?
    – Anguepa
    Jul 28 at 7:53










  • @Angeupa What I mean by "identify" is, what we need to do before "Let's say that sub-box as $B_2$". I can prove at least one such set exists, but how can we actually pick that set out and label it as $B_2$?
    – moreblue
    Jul 28 at 8:01







  • 4




    It is an existence proof not a construction proof. It only shows that such a point must exist, not that there must be only one or how to find it (if it is only one). The points must sum up and the only way to sum to infinity is if one or more of the subboxes sums to infinity since if none of them did then it would be finite number of points which would violate the assumption.
    – mathreadler
    Jul 28 at 8:04











  • Since there are finitely many sub-boxes ($2^N$), one can (in principle) check each box until we find one that contains infinitely many elements.
    – Brahadeesh
    Jul 28 at 8:04














up vote
7
down vote

favorite












I'm proving the Bolzano–Weierstrass theorem. It says



$$
textIf A text : bounded and infinite set, text then A text has at least one limit point.
$$



So the proof goes like the following.



Since $A subset mathbbR^N$ is bounded, it can be a subset of a box $B_1 = I_1 times cdots times I_N$, where $I_i$ is an interval in $mathbbR$. Let's divide the $B_1$ into $2^N$ sub-boxes. Then, at least one sub-box has the infinite elements of $A$. Let's say that sub-box as $B_2$. Let's say we can repeat this procedure for $B_3, B_4, ldots$



Well, so proof ends as we prove some $x$ exists in $cap_n=1^inftyB_n$ and it is a limit point of $A$.



But what I'm wondering is, how can we identify the $B_2$? (and $B_3$, and so on)



Yes, it's clear to me that such set exists, but the existence itself does not guarantee us to identify the set (that is, to select and label it as $B_2$), since we don't have any tools to discern if $B_2$ is infinite or not.



It sounds a little bit philosophical, but is there anyone to help?







share|cite|improve this question





















  • You say at least one sub-box has. Also there is a missing step somewhere, the highest $B_k$ mentioned is $B_2$ but you then write $xin cap_nB_n$ we don't know what any $B_k, k>2$ is at this point.
    – mathreadler
    Jul 28 at 7:53







  • 3




    What do you mean exactly by "identify"? And why do we need to do so?
    – Anguepa
    Jul 28 at 7:53










  • @Angeupa What I mean by "identify" is, what we need to do before "Let's say that sub-box as $B_2$". I can prove at least one such set exists, but how can we actually pick that set out and label it as $B_2$?
    – moreblue
    Jul 28 at 8:01







  • 4




    It is an existence proof not a construction proof. It only shows that such a point must exist, not that there must be only one or how to find it (if it is only one). The points must sum up and the only way to sum to infinity is if one or more of the subboxes sums to infinity since if none of them did then it would be finite number of points which would violate the assumption.
    – mathreadler
    Jul 28 at 8:04











  • Since there are finitely many sub-boxes ($2^N$), one can (in principle) check each box until we find one that contains infinitely many elements.
    – Brahadeesh
    Jul 28 at 8:04












up vote
7
down vote

favorite









up vote
7
down vote

favorite











I'm proving the Bolzano–Weierstrass theorem. It says



$$
textIf A text : bounded and infinite set, text then A text has at least one limit point.
$$



So the proof goes like the following.



Since $A subset mathbbR^N$ is bounded, it can be a subset of a box $B_1 = I_1 times cdots times I_N$, where $I_i$ is an interval in $mathbbR$. Let's divide the $B_1$ into $2^N$ sub-boxes. Then, at least one sub-box has the infinite elements of $A$. Let's say that sub-box as $B_2$. Let's say we can repeat this procedure for $B_3, B_4, ldots$



Well, so proof ends as we prove some $x$ exists in $cap_n=1^inftyB_n$ and it is a limit point of $A$.



But what I'm wondering is, how can we identify the $B_2$? (and $B_3$, and so on)



Yes, it's clear to me that such set exists, but the existence itself does not guarantee us to identify the set (that is, to select and label it as $B_2$), since we don't have any tools to discern if $B_2$ is infinite or not.



It sounds a little bit philosophical, but is there anyone to help?







share|cite|improve this question













I'm proving the Bolzano–Weierstrass theorem. It says



$$
textIf A text : bounded and infinite set, text then A text has at least one limit point.
$$



So the proof goes like the following.



Since $A subset mathbbR^N$ is bounded, it can be a subset of a box $B_1 = I_1 times cdots times I_N$, where $I_i$ is an interval in $mathbbR$. Let's divide the $B_1$ into $2^N$ sub-boxes. Then, at least one sub-box has the infinite elements of $A$. Let's say that sub-box as $B_2$. Let's say we can repeat this procedure for $B_3, B_4, ldots$



Well, so proof ends as we prove some $x$ exists in $cap_n=1^inftyB_n$ and it is a limit point of $A$.



But what I'm wondering is, how can we identify the $B_2$? (and $B_3$, and so on)



Yes, it's clear to me that such set exists, but the existence itself does not guarantee us to identify the set (that is, to select and label it as $B_2$), since we don't have any tools to discern if $B_2$ is infinite or not.



It sounds a little bit philosophical, but is there anyone to help?









share|cite|improve this question












share|cite|improve this question




share|cite|improve this question








edited Jul 28 at 8:35
























asked Jul 28 at 7:47









moreblue

1738




1738











  • You say at least one sub-box has. Also there is a missing step somewhere, the highest $B_k$ mentioned is $B_2$ but you then write $xin cap_nB_n$ we don't know what any $B_k, k>2$ is at this point.
    – mathreadler
    Jul 28 at 7:53







  • 3




    What do you mean exactly by "identify"? And why do we need to do so?
    – Anguepa
    Jul 28 at 7:53










  • @Angeupa What I mean by "identify" is, what we need to do before "Let's say that sub-box as $B_2$". I can prove at least one such set exists, but how can we actually pick that set out and label it as $B_2$?
    – moreblue
    Jul 28 at 8:01







  • 4




    It is an existence proof not a construction proof. It only shows that such a point must exist, not that there must be only one or how to find it (if it is only one). The points must sum up and the only way to sum to infinity is if one or more of the subboxes sums to infinity since if none of them did then it would be finite number of points which would violate the assumption.
    – mathreadler
    Jul 28 at 8:04











  • Since there are finitely many sub-boxes ($2^N$), one can (in principle) check each box until we find one that contains infinitely many elements.
    – Brahadeesh
    Jul 28 at 8:04
















  • You say at least one sub-box has. Also there is a missing step somewhere, the highest $B_k$ mentioned is $B_2$ but you then write $xin cap_nB_n$ we don't know what any $B_k, k>2$ is at this point.
    – mathreadler
    Jul 28 at 7:53







  • 3




    What do you mean exactly by "identify"? And why do we need to do so?
    – Anguepa
    Jul 28 at 7:53










  • @Angeupa What I mean by "identify" is, what we need to do before "Let's say that sub-box as $B_2$". I can prove at least one such set exists, but how can we actually pick that set out and label it as $B_2$?
    – moreblue
    Jul 28 at 8:01







  • 4




    It is an existence proof not a construction proof. It only shows that such a point must exist, not that there must be only one or how to find it (if it is only one). The points must sum up and the only way to sum to infinity is if one or more of the subboxes sums to infinity since if none of them did then it would be finite number of points which would violate the assumption.
    – mathreadler
    Jul 28 at 8:04











  • Since there are finitely many sub-boxes ($2^N$), one can (in principle) check each box until we find one that contains infinitely many elements.
    – Brahadeesh
    Jul 28 at 8:04















You say at least one sub-box has. Also there is a missing step somewhere, the highest $B_k$ mentioned is $B_2$ but you then write $xin cap_nB_n$ we don't know what any $B_k, k>2$ is at this point.
– mathreadler
Jul 28 at 7:53





You say at least one sub-box has. Also there is a missing step somewhere, the highest $B_k$ mentioned is $B_2$ but you then write $xin cap_nB_n$ we don't know what any $B_k, k>2$ is at this point.
– mathreadler
Jul 28 at 7:53





3




3




What do you mean exactly by "identify"? And why do we need to do so?
– Anguepa
Jul 28 at 7:53




What do you mean exactly by "identify"? And why do we need to do so?
– Anguepa
Jul 28 at 7:53












@Angeupa What I mean by "identify" is, what we need to do before "Let's say that sub-box as $B_2$". I can prove at least one such set exists, but how can we actually pick that set out and label it as $B_2$?
– moreblue
Jul 28 at 8:01





@Angeupa What I mean by "identify" is, what we need to do before "Let's say that sub-box as $B_2$". I can prove at least one such set exists, but how can we actually pick that set out and label it as $B_2$?
– moreblue
Jul 28 at 8:01





4




4




It is an existence proof not a construction proof. It only shows that such a point must exist, not that there must be only one or how to find it (if it is only one). The points must sum up and the only way to sum to infinity is if one or more of the subboxes sums to infinity since if none of them did then it would be finite number of points which would violate the assumption.
– mathreadler
Jul 28 at 8:04





It is an existence proof not a construction proof. It only shows that such a point must exist, not that there must be only one or how to find it (if it is only one). The points must sum up and the only way to sum to infinity is if one or more of the subboxes sums to infinity since if none of them did then it would be finite number of points which would violate the assumption.
– mathreadler
Jul 28 at 8:04













Since there are finitely many sub-boxes ($2^N$), one can (in principle) check each box until we find one that contains infinitely many elements.
– Brahadeesh
Jul 28 at 8:04




Since there are finitely many sub-boxes ($2^N$), one can (in principle) check each box until we find one that contains infinitely many elements.
– Brahadeesh
Jul 28 at 8:04










3 Answers
3






active

oldest

votes

















up vote
7
down vote



accepted










It is not surprising that there is no constructive way to identify, at each stage, which of the $2^n$ boxes holds infinitely many points—because, from the outset, the premiss of the theorem assumes nothing about where the points are: we know only that there are infinitely many of them. There are thus at least continuum-many possibilities for how the points might be distributed. All we can do is make the logical observation that, at every stage, the boxes cannot all hold a finite number of points, and therefore at least one of them holds an infinite number. If we need to identify just which such a box might be, we might be able to do so if we were given a precise construction of $A$; but we are given no such information.






share|cite|improve this answer




























    up vote
    7
    down vote













    It seems that you understand why at least one box contains infinitely many elements of $A$, and your difficulty is only in finding which box that is (or finding one such box if there are several of them). That is, it's a question of existence versus finding. Notice, though, that the theorem you're proving says only that there exists a limit point. It doesn't claim anything about finding a limit point.



    To prove the existence of a limit point, it's enough to have the existence of an appropriate box at every stage of the process.



    If you wanted to prove a stronger theorem saying that one can find a limit point, then you'd have to worry about finding an appropriate box at every stage. Any alleged theorem of that sort would have to be preceded by information about (1) exactly how the set $A$ is presented and (2) exactly what it means to "find" a point. So such a theorem would not only be harder to prove but considerably more complicated to state than the Bolzano-Weierstrass theorem.






    share|cite|improve this answer




























      up vote
      4
      down vote













      It is in fact a philosophical question. The "paradoxes of infinity" have puzzled people since ancient times. In 1851 Bolzano himself has written a book with the title "Paradoxien des Unendlichen" (in English "Paradoxes of the Infinite").



      In your proof you start with an infinite set $A$. But how can you know that is infinite? Is it explicitly given by listing its elements? In broad terms let us understand by "listing" any rule that allows you to decide whether a given element $x$ belongs to $A$ or not.



      If you have such a listing, then you will be able to identify $B_2, B_3, ...$. If not, you are not even able to identify $A$. In that case it is only possible to argue on an abstract level: If you put infinitely many things into finitely many boxes, than at least one box must contain infinitely many things. Imagine a "person" has put the things into the boxes, but you didn't watch the process. Then you will not know which box contains infinitely many things, but you will know that at least one box must contain infinitely many things. If you don't like to consider "infinitely many things", you can also consider $10$ things in $2$ boxes: You know that at least one must contain $5$ things or more, but you don't know which box. It is similar to the shell game: You know that the ball is placed beneath one the shells, but would you bet beneath which?






      share|cite|improve this answer























      • Regarding his book about infinities... It really is great that some of Bolzano's texts are available to our day :D They are quite inspirational.
        – mathreadler
        Jul 28 at 18:16











      Your Answer




      StackExchange.ifUsing("editor", function ()
      return StackExchange.using("mathjaxEditing", function ()
      StackExchange.MarkdownEditor.creationCallbacks.add(function (editor, postfix)
      StackExchange.mathjaxEditing.prepareWmdForMathJax(editor, postfix, [["$", "$"], ["\\(","\\)"]]);
      );
      );
      , "mathjax-editing");

      StackExchange.ready(function()
      var channelOptions =
      tags: "".split(" "),
      id: "69"
      ;
      initTagRenderer("".split(" "), "".split(" "), channelOptions);

      StackExchange.using("externalEditor", function()
      // Have to fire editor after snippets, if snippets enabled
      if (StackExchange.settings.snippets.snippetsEnabled)
      StackExchange.using("snippets", function()
      createEditor();
      );

      else
      createEditor();

      );

      function createEditor()
      StackExchange.prepareEditor(
      heartbeatType: 'answer',
      convertImagesToLinks: true,
      noModals: false,
      showLowRepImageUploadWarning: true,
      reputationToPostImages: 10,
      bindNavPrevention: true,
      postfix: "",
      noCode: true, onDemand: true,
      discardSelector: ".discard-answer"
      ,immediatelyShowMarkdownHelp:true
      );



      );








       

      draft saved


      draft discarded


















      StackExchange.ready(
      function ()
      StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmath.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f2865077%2fhow-can-we-identify-a-set-is-infinite-when-proving-bolzano-weierstrass-theorem%23new-answer', 'question_page');

      );

      Post as a guest






























      3 Answers
      3






      active

      oldest

      votes








      3 Answers
      3






      active

      oldest

      votes









      active

      oldest

      votes






      active

      oldest

      votes








      up vote
      7
      down vote



      accepted










      It is not surprising that there is no constructive way to identify, at each stage, which of the $2^n$ boxes holds infinitely many points—because, from the outset, the premiss of the theorem assumes nothing about where the points are: we know only that there are infinitely many of them. There are thus at least continuum-many possibilities for how the points might be distributed. All we can do is make the logical observation that, at every stage, the boxes cannot all hold a finite number of points, and therefore at least one of them holds an infinite number. If we need to identify just which such a box might be, we might be able to do so if we were given a precise construction of $A$; but we are given no such information.






      share|cite|improve this answer

























        up vote
        7
        down vote



        accepted










        It is not surprising that there is no constructive way to identify, at each stage, which of the $2^n$ boxes holds infinitely many points—because, from the outset, the premiss of the theorem assumes nothing about where the points are: we know only that there are infinitely many of them. There are thus at least continuum-many possibilities for how the points might be distributed. All we can do is make the logical observation that, at every stage, the boxes cannot all hold a finite number of points, and therefore at least one of them holds an infinite number. If we need to identify just which such a box might be, we might be able to do so if we were given a precise construction of $A$; but we are given no such information.






        share|cite|improve this answer























          up vote
          7
          down vote



          accepted







          up vote
          7
          down vote



          accepted






          It is not surprising that there is no constructive way to identify, at each stage, which of the $2^n$ boxes holds infinitely many points—because, from the outset, the premiss of the theorem assumes nothing about where the points are: we know only that there are infinitely many of them. There are thus at least continuum-many possibilities for how the points might be distributed. All we can do is make the logical observation that, at every stage, the boxes cannot all hold a finite number of points, and therefore at least one of them holds an infinite number. If we need to identify just which such a box might be, we might be able to do so if we were given a precise construction of $A$; but we are given no such information.






          share|cite|improve this answer













          It is not surprising that there is no constructive way to identify, at each stage, which of the $2^n$ boxes holds infinitely many points—because, from the outset, the premiss of the theorem assumes nothing about where the points are: we know only that there are infinitely many of them. There are thus at least continuum-many possibilities for how the points might be distributed. All we can do is make the logical observation that, at every stage, the boxes cannot all hold a finite number of points, and therefore at least one of them holds an infinite number. If we need to identify just which such a box might be, we might be able to do so if we were given a precise construction of $A$; but we are given no such information.







          share|cite|improve this answer













          share|cite|improve this answer



          share|cite|improve this answer











          answered Jul 28 at 8:45









          John Bentin

          10.8k22350




          10.8k22350




















              up vote
              7
              down vote













              It seems that you understand why at least one box contains infinitely many elements of $A$, and your difficulty is only in finding which box that is (or finding one such box if there are several of them). That is, it's a question of existence versus finding. Notice, though, that the theorem you're proving says only that there exists a limit point. It doesn't claim anything about finding a limit point.



              To prove the existence of a limit point, it's enough to have the existence of an appropriate box at every stage of the process.



              If you wanted to prove a stronger theorem saying that one can find a limit point, then you'd have to worry about finding an appropriate box at every stage. Any alleged theorem of that sort would have to be preceded by information about (1) exactly how the set $A$ is presented and (2) exactly what it means to "find" a point. So such a theorem would not only be harder to prove but considerably more complicated to state than the Bolzano-Weierstrass theorem.






              share|cite|improve this answer

























                up vote
                7
                down vote













                It seems that you understand why at least one box contains infinitely many elements of $A$, and your difficulty is only in finding which box that is (or finding one such box if there are several of them). That is, it's a question of existence versus finding. Notice, though, that the theorem you're proving says only that there exists a limit point. It doesn't claim anything about finding a limit point.



                To prove the existence of a limit point, it's enough to have the existence of an appropriate box at every stage of the process.



                If you wanted to prove a stronger theorem saying that one can find a limit point, then you'd have to worry about finding an appropriate box at every stage. Any alleged theorem of that sort would have to be preceded by information about (1) exactly how the set $A$ is presented and (2) exactly what it means to "find" a point. So such a theorem would not only be harder to prove but considerably more complicated to state than the Bolzano-Weierstrass theorem.






                share|cite|improve this answer























                  up vote
                  7
                  down vote










                  up vote
                  7
                  down vote









                  It seems that you understand why at least one box contains infinitely many elements of $A$, and your difficulty is only in finding which box that is (or finding one such box if there are several of them). That is, it's a question of existence versus finding. Notice, though, that the theorem you're proving says only that there exists a limit point. It doesn't claim anything about finding a limit point.



                  To prove the existence of a limit point, it's enough to have the existence of an appropriate box at every stage of the process.



                  If you wanted to prove a stronger theorem saying that one can find a limit point, then you'd have to worry about finding an appropriate box at every stage. Any alleged theorem of that sort would have to be preceded by information about (1) exactly how the set $A$ is presented and (2) exactly what it means to "find" a point. So such a theorem would not only be harder to prove but considerably more complicated to state than the Bolzano-Weierstrass theorem.






                  share|cite|improve this answer













                  It seems that you understand why at least one box contains infinitely many elements of $A$, and your difficulty is only in finding which box that is (or finding one such box if there are several of them). That is, it's a question of existence versus finding. Notice, though, that the theorem you're proving says only that there exists a limit point. It doesn't claim anything about finding a limit point.



                  To prove the existence of a limit point, it's enough to have the existence of an appropriate box at every stage of the process.



                  If you wanted to prove a stronger theorem saying that one can find a limit point, then you'd have to worry about finding an appropriate box at every stage. Any alleged theorem of that sort would have to be preceded by information about (1) exactly how the set $A$ is presented and (2) exactly what it means to "find" a point. So such a theorem would not only be harder to prove but considerably more complicated to state than the Bolzano-Weierstrass theorem.







                  share|cite|improve this answer













                  share|cite|improve this answer



                  share|cite|improve this answer











                  answered Jul 28 at 12:51









                  Andreas Blass

                  47.5k348104




                  47.5k348104




















                      up vote
                      4
                      down vote













                      It is in fact a philosophical question. The "paradoxes of infinity" have puzzled people since ancient times. In 1851 Bolzano himself has written a book with the title "Paradoxien des Unendlichen" (in English "Paradoxes of the Infinite").



                      In your proof you start with an infinite set $A$. But how can you know that is infinite? Is it explicitly given by listing its elements? In broad terms let us understand by "listing" any rule that allows you to decide whether a given element $x$ belongs to $A$ or not.



                      If you have such a listing, then you will be able to identify $B_2, B_3, ...$. If not, you are not even able to identify $A$. In that case it is only possible to argue on an abstract level: If you put infinitely many things into finitely many boxes, than at least one box must contain infinitely many things. Imagine a "person" has put the things into the boxes, but you didn't watch the process. Then you will not know which box contains infinitely many things, but you will know that at least one box must contain infinitely many things. If you don't like to consider "infinitely many things", you can also consider $10$ things in $2$ boxes: You know that at least one must contain $5$ things or more, but you don't know which box. It is similar to the shell game: You know that the ball is placed beneath one the shells, but would you bet beneath which?






                      share|cite|improve this answer























                      • Regarding his book about infinities... It really is great that some of Bolzano's texts are available to our day :D They are quite inspirational.
                        – mathreadler
                        Jul 28 at 18:16















                      up vote
                      4
                      down vote













                      It is in fact a philosophical question. The "paradoxes of infinity" have puzzled people since ancient times. In 1851 Bolzano himself has written a book with the title "Paradoxien des Unendlichen" (in English "Paradoxes of the Infinite").



                      In your proof you start with an infinite set $A$. But how can you know that is infinite? Is it explicitly given by listing its elements? In broad terms let us understand by "listing" any rule that allows you to decide whether a given element $x$ belongs to $A$ or not.



                      If you have such a listing, then you will be able to identify $B_2, B_3, ...$. If not, you are not even able to identify $A$. In that case it is only possible to argue on an abstract level: If you put infinitely many things into finitely many boxes, than at least one box must contain infinitely many things. Imagine a "person" has put the things into the boxes, but you didn't watch the process. Then you will not know which box contains infinitely many things, but you will know that at least one box must contain infinitely many things. If you don't like to consider "infinitely many things", you can also consider $10$ things in $2$ boxes: You know that at least one must contain $5$ things or more, but you don't know which box. It is similar to the shell game: You know that the ball is placed beneath one the shells, but would you bet beneath which?






                      share|cite|improve this answer























                      • Regarding his book about infinities... It really is great that some of Bolzano's texts are available to our day :D They are quite inspirational.
                        – mathreadler
                        Jul 28 at 18:16













                      up vote
                      4
                      down vote










                      up vote
                      4
                      down vote









                      It is in fact a philosophical question. The "paradoxes of infinity" have puzzled people since ancient times. In 1851 Bolzano himself has written a book with the title "Paradoxien des Unendlichen" (in English "Paradoxes of the Infinite").



                      In your proof you start with an infinite set $A$. But how can you know that is infinite? Is it explicitly given by listing its elements? In broad terms let us understand by "listing" any rule that allows you to decide whether a given element $x$ belongs to $A$ or not.



                      If you have such a listing, then you will be able to identify $B_2, B_3, ...$. If not, you are not even able to identify $A$. In that case it is only possible to argue on an abstract level: If you put infinitely many things into finitely many boxes, than at least one box must contain infinitely many things. Imagine a "person" has put the things into the boxes, but you didn't watch the process. Then you will not know which box contains infinitely many things, but you will know that at least one box must contain infinitely many things. If you don't like to consider "infinitely many things", you can also consider $10$ things in $2$ boxes: You know that at least one must contain $5$ things or more, but you don't know which box. It is similar to the shell game: You know that the ball is placed beneath one the shells, but would you bet beneath which?






                      share|cite|improve this answer















                      It is in fact a philosophical question. The "paradoxes of infinity" have puzzled people since ancient times. In 1851 Bolzano himself has written a book with the title "Paradoxien des Unendlichen" (in English "Paradoxes of the Infinite").



                      In your proof you start with an infinite set $A$. But how can you know that is infinite? Is it explicitly given by listing its elements? In broad terms let us understand by "listing" any rule that allows you to decide whether a given element $x$ belongs to $A$ or not.



                      If you have such a listing, then you will be able to identify $B_2, B_3, ...$. If not, you are not even able to identify $A$. In that case it is only possible to argue on an abstract level: If you put infinitely many things into finitely many boxes, than at least one box must contain infinitely many things. Imagine a "person" has put the things into the boxes, but you didn't watch the process. Then you will not know which box contains infinitely many things, but you will know that at least one box must contain infinitely many things. If you don't like to consider "infinitely many things", you can also consider $10$ things in $2$ boxes: You know that at least one must contain $5$ things or more, but you don't know which box. It is similar to the shell game: You know that the ball is placed beneath one the shells, but would you bet beneath which?







                      share|cite|improve this answer















                      share|cite|improve this answer



                      share|cite|improve this answer








                      edited Jul 28 at 10:56


























                      answered Jul 28 at 8:55









                      Paul Frost

                      3,603420




                      3,603420











                      • Regarding his book about infinities... It really is great that some of Bolzano's texts are available to our day :D They are quite inspirational.
                        – mathreadler
                        Jul 28 at 18:16

















                      • Regarding his book about infinities... It really is great that some of Bolzano's texts are available to our day :D They are quite inspirational.
                        – mathreadler
                        Jul 28 at 18:16
















                      Regarding his book about infinities... It really is great that some of Bolzano's texts are available to our day :D They are quite inspirational.
                      – mathreadler
                      Jul 28 at 18:16





                      Regarding his book about infinities... It really is great that some of Bolzano's texts are available to our day :D They are quite inspirational.
                      – mathreadler
                      Jul 28 at 18:16













                       

                      draft saved


                      draft discarded


























                       


                      draft saved


                      draft discarded














                      StackExchange.ready(
                      function ()
                      StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmath.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f2865077%2fhow-can-we-identify-a-set-is-infinite-when-proving-bolzano-weierstrass-theorem%23new-answer', 'question_page');

                      );

                      Post as a guest













































































                      Comments

                      Popular posts from this blog

                      What is the equation of a 3D cone with generalised tilt?

                      Color the edges and diagonals of a regular polygon

                      Relationship between determinant of matrix and determinant of adjoint?