Prove that if $A$ and $B$ are Dedekind finite then so is their union, without using natural numbers or Axiom of Choice

The name of the pictureThe name of the pictureThe name of the pictureClash Royale CLAN TAG#URR8PPP











up vote
3
down vote

favorite
1












Note admins: THIS IS NOT A DUPLICATE to other posts (see the last sentence).




Prove that if $A$ and $B$ are Dedekind finite then so is their union, without using the concept of natural numbers or Axiom of Choice.




Of course, the result is trivial with the natural numbers, but the book from which this question is derived said this can be proven without the aid of natural numbers and Axiom of Choice (I am using Moschovakis' Notes on Set Theory, 1st edition, chapter 4, x4.25)



We are allowed to use $ZF$ Axioms.



Suppose on the contrary thay there are Dedekind finite sets $A,B$ such that $A cup B$ is Dedekind infinite. If either $f(A) subset A$ or $f(B) subset B$ then we can easily create a proper injection from one set to itself (just take restriction of $f$), so assume that that is not the case.



I am not sure what to do here. A hint would be more appreciated then a full answer.



I realize that there already are many questions and answers regarding how a union of two Dedekind finite sets are still Dedekind finite, but my question is different: the difficulty here is that (1) since I am not allowed to use natural numbers, we cannot talk about a set being finite or infinte, much less list some elements or sets, and (2) we cannot use Axiom of Choice.







share|cite|improve this question





















  • Since being Dedekind finite is defined without a reference to the natural numbers, your last comment is irrelevant.
    – Asaf Karagila
    Jul 26 at 6:49






  • 1




    If A $cup$B is Dedekind infinite, there is an injective function f : N → A $cup$ B, but he can't make use of that. So it could be relevant.
    – Steve B
    Jul 26 at 7:00










  • @Steve: And that does not use the natural numbers, how? :)
    – Asaf Karagila
    Jul 26 at 9:10










  • BlueRoss: Unless you are allowed to use the axiom of choice, which you explicitly said you can't, that is a false statement.
    – Asaf Karagila
    Jul 27 at 8:38














up vote
3
down vote

favorite
1












Note admins: THIS IS NOT A DUPLICATE to other posts (see the last sentence).




Prove that if $A$ and $B$ are Dedekind finite then so is their union, without using the concept of natural numbers or Axiom of Choice.




Of course, the result is trivial with the natural numbers, but the book from which this question is derived said this can be proven without the aid of natural numbers and Axiom of Choice (I am using Moschovakis' Notes on Set Theory, 1st edition, chapter 4, x4.25)



We are allowed to use $ZF$ Axioms.



Suppose on the contrary thay there are Dedekind finite sets $A,B$ such that $A cup B$ is Dedekind infinite. If either $f(A) subset A$ or $f(B) subset B$ then we can easily create a proper injection from one set to itself (just take restriction of $f$), so assume that that is not the case.



I am not sure what to do here. A hint would be more appreciated then a full answer.



I realize that there already are many questions and answers regarding how a union of two Dedekind finite sets are still Dedekind finite, but my question is different: the difficulty here is that (1) since I am not allowed to use natural numbers, we cannot talk about a set being finite or infinte, much less list some elements or sets, and (2) we cannot use Axiom of Choice.







share|cite|improve this question





















  • Since being Dedekind finite is defined without a reference to the natural numbers, your last comment is irrelevant.
    – Asaf Karagila
    Jul 26 at 6:49






  • 1




    If A $cup$B is Dedekind infinite, there is an injective function f : N → A $cup$ B, but he can't make use of that. So it could be relevant.
    – Steve B
    Jul 26 at 7:00










  • @Steve: And that does not use the natural numbers, how? :)
    – Asaf Karagila
    Jul 26 at 9:10










  • BlueRoss: Unless you are allowed to use the axiom of choice, which you explicitly said you can't, that is a false statement.
    – Asaf Karagila
    Jul 27 at 8:38












up vote
3
down vote

favorite
1









up vote
3
down vote

favorite
1






1





Note admins: THIS IS NOT A DUPLICATE to other posts (see the last sentence).




Prove that if $A$ and $B$ are Dedekind finite then so is their union, without using the concept of natural numbers or Axiom of Choice.




Of course, the result is trivial with the natural numbers, but the book from which this question is derived said this can be proven without the aid of natural numbers and Axiom of Choice (I am using Moschovakis' Notes on Set Theory, 1st edition, chapter 4, x4.25)



We are allowed to use $ZF$ Axioms.



Suppose on the contrary thay there are Dedekind finite sets $A,B$ such that $A cup B$ is Dedekind infinite. If either $f(A) subset A$ or $f(B) subset B$ then we can easily create a proper injection from one set to itself (just take restriction of $f$), so assume that that is not the case.



I am not sure what to do here. A hint would be more appreciated then a full answer.



I realize that there already are many questions and answers regarding how a union of two Dedekind finite sets are still Dedekind finite, but my question is different: the difficulty here is that (1) since I am not allowed to use natural numbers, we cannot talk about a set being finite or infinte, much less list some elements or sets, and (2) we cannot use Axiom of Choice.







share|cite|improve this question













Note admins: THIS IS NOT A DUPLICATE to other posts (see the last sentence).




Prove that if $A$ and $B$ are Dedekind finite then so is their union, without using the concept of natural numbers or Axiom of Choice.




Of course, the result is trivial with the natural numbers, but the book from which this question is derived said this can be proven without the aid of natural numbers and Axiom of Choice (I am using Moschovakis' Notes on Set Theory, 1st edition, chapter 4, x4.25)



We are allowed to use $ZF$ Axioms.



Suppose on the contrary thay there are Dedekind finite sets $A,B$ such that $A cup B$ is Dedekind infinite. If either $f(A) subset A$ or $f(B) subset B$ then we can easily create a proper injection from one set to itself (just take restriction of $f$), so assume that that is not the case.



I am not sure what to do here. A hint would be more appreciated then a full answer.



I realize that there already are many questions and answers regarding how a union of two Dedekind finite sets are still Dedekind finite, but my question is different: the difficulty here is that (1) since I am not allowed to use natural numbers, we cannot talk about a set being finite or infinte, much less list some elements or sets, and (2) we cannot use Axiom of Choice.









share|cite|improve this question












share|cite|improve this question




share|cite|improve this question








edited Jul 27 at 3:17
























asked Jul 26 at 6:12









BlueRoses

833314




833314











  • Since being Dedekind finite is defined without a reference to the natural numbers, your last comment is irrelevant.
    – Asaf Karagila
    Jul 26 at 6:49






  • 1




    If A $cup$B is Dedekind infinite, there is an injective function f : N → A $cup$ B, but he can't make use of that. So it could be relevant.
    – Steve B
    Jul 26 at 7:00










  • @Steve: And that does not use the natural numbers, how? :)
    – Asaf Karagila
    Jul 26 at 9:10










  • BlueRoss: Unless you are allowed to use the axiom of choice, which you explicitly said you can't, that is a false statement.
    – Asaf Karagila
    Jul 27 at 8:38
















  • Since being Dedekind finite is defined without a reference to the natural numbers, your last comment is irrelevant.
    – Asaf Karagila
    Jul 26 at 6:49






  • 1




    If A $cup$B is Dedekind infinite, there is an injective function f : N → A $cup$ B, but he can't make use of that. So it could be relevant.
    – Steve B
    Jul 26 at 7:00










  • @Steve: And that does not use the natural numbers, how? :)
    – Asaf Karagila
    Jul 26 at 9:10










  • BlueRoss: Unless you are allowed to use the axiom of choice, which you explicitly said you can't, that is a false statement.
    – Asaf Karagila
    Jul 27 at 8:38















Since being Dedekind finite is defined without a reference to the natural numbers, your last comment is irrelevant.
– Asaf Karagila
Jul 26 at 6:49




Since being Dedekind finite is defined without a reference to the natural numbers, your last comment is irrelevant.
– Asaf Karagila
Jul 26 at 6:49




1




1




If A $cup$B is Dedekind infinite, there is an injective function f : N → A $cup$ B, but he can't make use of that. So it could be relevant.
– Steve B
Jul 26 at 7:00




If A $cup$B is Dedekind infinite, there is an injective function f : N → A $cup$ B, but he can't make use of that. So it could be relevant.
– Steve B
Jul 26 at 7:00












@Steve: And that does not use the natural numbers, how? :)
– Asaf Karagila
Jul 26 at 9:10




@Steve: And that does not use the natural numbers, how? :)
– Asaf Karagila
Jul 26 at 9:10












BlueRoss: Unless you are allowed to use the axiom of choice, which you explicitly said you can't, that is a false statement.
– Asaf Karagila
Jul 27 at 8:38




BlueRoss: Unless you are allowed to use the axiom of choice, which you explicitly said you can't, that is a false statement.
– Asaf Karagila
Jul 27 at 8:38










1 Answer
1






active

oldest

votes

















up vote
4
down vote













Here's a hint.
Suppose f is an injection from $A cup
B$ to a proper subset.



Define $D(x) = bigcap S subset A cup B : x in S, f(S) subseteq S$.



Choose $c in (A cup B) setminus f(A cup B)$. Let $C = D(c)$.



Show that $x prec y$ iff $D(y) subsetneq D(x)$ is a well-ordering of C and attempt to construct injections on $A cap C$ and $B cap C$ taking members of each to the next member under the well-ordering. Show that at least one of these must exist. It is onto a proper subset and so one of A and B is Dedekind-infinite.



(You might get away without fully proving the well-ordering. Showing that if $X subset C$ is non-empty then $exists! x in X, X subseteq D(x)$ may be enough.)



ETA more details.



Let's call a set $S$ f-closed if $f(S) subseteq S subseteq A cup B$



Note that for any such $S$, $x in S$ implies $D(x) subseteq S$.



In particular, $D(x)$, $f(D(x))$, $D(f(x))$, $D(f(x)) cup x $ and $f(D(x)) cup x $ are all f-closed, for any x, which can be used to show $D(f(x)) = f(D(x))$ and $D(x) = D(f(x)) cup x = f(D(x)) cup x $. And also, for any $y in D(x)$, $D(y) subseteq D(x)$.



Next we need to prove: If $S$ is f-closed, non-empty and $S subseteq D(x)$ for some x, then there exists $y in D(x)$ such that $S=D(y)$



Suppose this fails for a particular $S$. Let $T = y in D(x) : S subsetneq D(y) $. If $y in T$ then $S subseteq D(f(y))$ (as $y notin S$) but we can't have $S = D(f(y))$ so we must have $S subsetneq D(f(y))$ and so $f(y) in T$. Thus $T$ is f-closed. But $x in T$ and so $T = D(x)$, which implies S is empty - a contradiction.



A similar argument shows that if $D(x) neq D(f(x))$ then for any $y$,$z in D(x)$, $D(y) = D(z)$ iff $y = z$. In particular this applies in C.



So now if $X subseteq C$ is non-empty, let $W = bigcup D(x) : x in X $. This f-closed so there is a unique $m in C$ such that $W = D(m)$. Clearly $m in X$. Define $min(X) = m$. (This can be used to construct the full well-ordering, but it is all we need to complete the proof.)



Now try to define a function on $A cap C$ by $g(x) = min(D(f(x) cap A)$. If this is possible $g$ is an injection from $A cap C$ to a proper subset. If it is not possible then for some $y in C$, $(D(y) cap A = emptyset$. Then $D(y) subseteq B cap C$ and f restricted to $D(y)$ is an injection onto a proper subset. At least one of $A cap C$ and $B cap C$ must be Dedekind-infinite.






share|cite|improve this answer























  • Very good, very good!
    – Asaf Karagila
    Jul 27 at 11:52










  • Could you give another hint, either about showing that the order on C is well, or about constructing the next-member injections?
    – Kyle MacDonald
    Aug 5 at 1:12










  • @Kyle MacDonald I've added some more details now. Sorry it's taken so long, I've been rather busy.
    – David Hartley
    Aug 8 at 23:33










Your Answer




StackExchange.ifUsing("editor", function ()
return StackExchange.using("mathjaxEditing", function ()
StackExchange.MarkdownEditor.creationCallbacks.add(function (editor, postfix)
StackExchange.mathjaxEditing.prepareWmdForMathJax(editor, postfix, [["$", "$"], ["\\(","\\)"]]);
);
);
, "mathjax-editing");

StackExchange.ready(function()
var channelOptions =
tags: "".split(" "),
id: "69"
;
initTagRenderer("".split(" "), "".split(" "), channelOptions);

StackExchange.using("externalEditor", function()
// Have to fire editor after snippets, if snippets enabled
if (StackExchange.settings.snippets.snippetsEnabled)
StackExchange.using("snippets", function()
createEditor();
);

else
createEditor();

);

function createEditor()
StackExchange.prepareEditor(
heartbeatType: 'answer',
convertImagesToLinks: true,
noModals: false,
showLowRepImageUploadWarning: true,
reputationToPostImages: 10,
bindNavPrevention: true,
postfix: "",
noCode: true, onDemand: true,
discardSelector: ".discard-answer"
,immediatelyShowMarkdownHelp:true
);



);








 

draft saved


draft discarded


















StackExchange.ready(
function ()
StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmath.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f2863114%2fprove-that-if-a-and-b-are-dedekind-finite-then-so-is-their-union-without-us%23new-answer', 'question_page');

);

Post as a guest






























1 Answer
1






active

oldest

votes








1 Answer
1






active

oldest

votes









active

oldest

votes






active

oldest

votes








up vote
4
down vote













Here's a hint.
Suppose f is an injection from $A cup
B$ to a proper subset.



Define $D(x) = bigcap S subset A cup B : x in S, f(S) subseteq S$.



Choose $c in (A cup B) setminus f(A cup B)$. Let $C = D(c)$.



Show that $x prec y$ iff $D(y) subsetneq D(x)$ is a well-ordering of C and attempt to construct injections on $A cap C$ and $B cap C$ taking members of each to the next member under the well-ordering. Show that at least one of these must exist. It is onto a proper subset and so one of A and B is Dedekind-infinite.



(You might get away without fully proving the well-ordering. Showing that if $X subset C$ is non-empty then $exists! x in X, X subseteq D(x)$ may be enough.)



ETA more details.



Let's call a set $S$ f-closed if $f(S) subseteq S subseteq A cup B$



Note that for any such $S$, $x in S$ implies $D(x) subseteq S$.



In particular, $D(x)$, $f(D(x))$, $D(f(x))$, $D(f(x)) cup x $ and $f(D(x)) cup x $ are all f-closed, for any x, which can be used to show $D(f(x)) = f(D(x))$ and $D(x) = D(f(x)) cup x = f(D(x)) cup x $. And also, for any $y in D(x)$, $D(y) subseteq D(x)$.



Next we need to prove: If $S$ is f-closed, non-empty and $S subseteq D(x)$ for some x, then there exists $y in D(x)$ such that $S=D(y)$



Suppose this fails for a particular $S$. Let $T = y in D(x) : S subsetneq D(y) $. If $y in T$ then $S subseteq D(f(y))$ (as $y notin S$) but we can't have $S = D(f(y))$ so we must have $S subsetneq D(f(y))$ and so $f(y) in T$. Thus $T$ is f-closed. But $x in T$ and so $T = D(x)$, which implies S is empty - a contradiction.



A similar argument shows that if $D(x) neq D(f(x))$ then for any $y$,$z in D(x)$, $D(y) = D(z)$ iff $y = z$. In particular this applies in C.



So now if $X subseteq C$ is non-empty, let $W = bigcup D(x) : x in X $. This f-closed so there is a unique $m in C$ such that $W = D(m)$. Clearly $m in X$. Define $min(X) = m$. (This can be used to construct the full well-ordering, but it is all we need to complete the proof.)



Now try to define a function on $A cap C$ by $g(x) = min(D(f(x) cap A)$. If this is possible $g$ is an injection from $A cap C$ to a proper subset. If it is not possible then for some $y in C$, $(D(y) cap A = emptyset$. Then $D(y) subseteq B cap C$ and f restricted to $D(y)$ is an injection onto a proper subset. At least one of $A cap C$ and $B cap C$ must be Dedekind-infinite.






share|cite|improve this answer























  • Very good, very good!
    – Asaf Karagila
    Jul 27 at 11:52










  • Could you give another hint, either about showing that the order on C is well, or about constructing the next-member injections?
    – Kyle MacDonald
    Aug 5 at 1:12










  • @Kyle MacDonald I've added some more details now. Sorry it's taken so long, I've been rather busy.
    – David Hartley
    Aug 8 at 23:33














up vote
4
down vote













Here's a hint.
Suppose f is an injection from $A cup
B$ to a proper subset.



Define $D(x) = bigcap S subset A cup B : x in S, f(S) subseteq S$.



Choose $c in (A cup B) setminus f(A cup B)$. Let $C = D(c)$.



Show that $x prec y$ iff $D(y) subsetneq D(x)$ is a well-ordering of C and attempt to construct injections on $A cap C$ and $B cap C$ taking members of each to the next member under the well-ordering. Show that at least one of these must exist. It is onto a proper subset and so one of A and B is Dedekind-infinite.



(You might get away without fully proving the well-ordering. Showing that if $X subset C$ is non-empty then $exists! x in X, X subseteq D(x)$ may be enough.)



ETA more details.



Let's call a set $S$ f-closed if $f(S) subseteq S subseteq A cup B$



Note that for any such $S$, $x in S$ implies $D(x) subseteq S$.



In particular, $D(x)$, $f(D(x))$, $D(f(x))$, $D(f(x)) cup x $ and $f(D(x)) cup x $ are all f-closed, for any x, which can be used to show $D(f(x)) = f(D(x))$ and $D(x) = D(f(x)) cup x = f(D(x)) cup x $. And also, for any $y in D(x)$, $D(y) subseteq D(x)$.



Next we need to prove: If $S$ is f-closed, non-empty and $S subseteq D(x)$ for some x, then there exists $y in D(x)$ such that $S=D(y)$



Suppose this fails for a particular $S$. Let $T = y in D(x) : S subsetneq D(y) $. If $y in T$ then $S subseteq D(f(y))$ (as $y notin S$) but we can't have $S = D(f(y))$ so we must have $S subsetneq D(f(y))$ and so $f(y) in T$. Thus $T$ is f-closed. But $x in T$ and so $T = D(x)$, which implies S is empty - a contradiction.



A similar argument shows that if $D(x) neq D(f(x))$ then for any $y$,$z in D(x)$, $D(y) = D(z)$ iff $y = z$. In particular this applies in C.



So now if $X subseteq C$ is non-empty, let $W = bigcup D(x) : x in X $. This f-closed so there is a unique $m in C$ such that $W = D(m)$. Clearly $m in X$. Define $min(X) = m$. (This can be used to construct the full well-ordering, but it is all we need to complete the proof.)



Now try to define a function on $A cap C$ by $g(x) = min(D(f(x) cap A)$. If this is possible $g$ is an injection from $A cap C$ to a proper subset. If it is not possible then for some $y in C$, $(D(y) cap A = emptyset$. Then $D(y) subseteq B cap C$ and f restricted to $D(y)$ is an injection onto a proper subset. At least one of $A cap C$ and $B cap C$ must be Dedekind-infinite.






share|cite|improve this answer























  • Very good, very good!
    – Asaf Karagila
    Jul 27 at 11:52










  • Could you give another hint, either about showing that the order on C is well, or about constructing the next-member injections?
    – Kyle MacDonald
    Aug 5 at 1:12










  • @Kyle MacDonald I've added some more details now. Sorry it's taken so long, I've been rather busy.
    – David Hartley
    Aug 8 at 23:33












up vote
4
down vote










up vote
4
down vote









Here's a hint.
Suppose f is an injection from $A cup
B$ to a proper subset.



Define $D(x) = bigcap S subset A cup B : x in S, f(S) subseteq S$.



Choose $c in (A cup B) setminus f(A cup B)$. Let $C = D(c)$.



Show that $x prec y$ iff $D(y) subsetneq D(x)$ is a well-ordering of C and attempt to construct injections on $A cap C$ and $B cap C$ taking members of each to the next member under the well-ordering. Show that at least one of these must exist. It is onto a proper subset and so one of A and B is Dedekind-infinite.



(You might get away without fully proving the well-ordering. Showing that if $X subset C$ is non-empty then $exists! x in X, X subseteq D(x)$ may be enough.)



ETA more details.



Let's call a set $S$ f-closed if $f(S) subseteq S subseteq A cup B$



Note that for any such $S$, $x in S$ implies $D(x) subseteq S$.



In particular, $D(x)$, $f(D(x))$, $D(f(x))$, $D(f(x)) cup x $ and $f(D(x)) cup x $ are all f-closed, for any x, which can be used to show $D(f(x)) = f(D(x))$ and $D(x) = D(f(x)) cup x = f(D(x)) cup x $. And also, for any $y in D(x)$, $D(y) subseteq D(x)$.



Next we need to prove: If $S$ is f-closed, non-empty and $S subseteq D(x)$ for some x, then there exists $y in D(x)$ such that $S=D(y)$



Suppose this fails for a particular $S$. Let $T = y in D(x) : S subsetneq D(y) $. If $y in T$ then $S subseteq D(f(y))$ (as $y notin S$) but we can't have $S = D(f(y))$ so we must have $S subsetneq D(f(y))$ and so $f(y) in T$. Thus $T$ is f-closed. But $x in T$ and so $T = D(x)$, which implies S is empty - a contradiction.



A similar argument shows that if $D(x) neq D(f(x))$ then for any $y$,$z in D(x)$, $D(y) = D(z)$ iff $y = z$. In particular this applies in C.



So now if $X subseteq C$ is non-empty, let $W = bigcup D(x) : x in X $. This f-closed so there is a unique $m in C$ such that $W = D(m)$. Clearly $m in X$. Define $min(X) = m$. (This can be used to construct the full well-ordering, but it is all we need to complete the proof.)



Now try to define a function on $A cap C$ by $g(x) = min(D(f(x) cap A)$. If this is possible $g$ is an injection from $A cap C$ to a proper subset. If it is not possible then for some $y in C$, $(D(y) cap A = emptyset$. Then $D(y) subseteq B cap C$ and f restricted to $D(y)$ is an injection onto a proper subset. At least one of $A cap C$ and $B cap C$ must be Dedekind-infinite.






share|cite|improve this answer















Here's a hint.
Suppose f is an injection from $A cup
B$ to a proper subset.



Define $D(x) = bigcap S subset A cup B : x in S, f(S) subseteq S$.



Choose $c in (A cup B) setminus f(A cup B)$. Let $C = D(c)$.



Show that $x prec y$ iff $D(y) subsetneq D(x)$ is a well-ordering of C and attempt to construct injections on $A cap C$ and $B cap C$ taking members of each to the next member under the well-ordering. Show that at least one of these must exist. It is onto a proper subset and so one of A and B is Dedekind-infinite.



(You might get away without fully proving the well-ordering. Showing that if $X subset C$ is non-empty then $exists! x in X, X subseteq D(x)$ may be enough.)



ETA more details.



Let's call a set $S$ f-closed if $f(S) subseteq S subseteq A cup B$



Note that for any such $S$, $x in S$ implies $D(x) subseteq S$.



In particular, $D(x)$, $f(D(x))$, $D(f(x))$, $D(f(x)) cup x $ and $f(D(x)) cup x $ are all f-closed, for any x, which can be used to show $D(f(x)) = f(D(x))$ and $D(x) = D(f(x)) cup x = f(D(x)) cup x $. And also, for any $y in D(x)$, $D(y) subseteq D(x)$.



Next we need to prove: If $S$ is f-closed, non-empty and $S subseteq D(x)$ for some x, then there exists $y in D(x)$ such that $S=D(y)$



Suppose this fails for a particular $S$. Let $T = y in D(x) : S subsetneq D(y) $. If $y in T$ then $S subseteq D(f(y))$ (as $y notin S$) but we can't have $S = D(f(y))$ so we must have $S subsetneq D(f(y))$ and so $f(y) in T$. Thus $T$ is f-closed. But $x in T$ and so $T = D(x)$, which implies S is empty - a contradiction.



A similar argument shows that if $D(x) neq D(f(x))$ then for any $y$,$z in D(x)$, $D(y) = D(z)$ iff $y = z$. In particular this applies in C.



So now if $X subseteq C$ is non-empty, let $W = bigcup D(x) : x in X $. This f-closed so there is a unique $m in C$ such that $W = D(m)$. Clearly $m in X$. Define $min(X) = m$. (This can be used to construct the full well-ordering, but it is all we need to complete the proof.)



Now try to define a function on $A cap C$ by $g(x) = min(D(f(x) cap A)$. If this is possible $g$ is an injection from $A cap C$ to a proper subset. If it is not possible then for some $y in C$, $(D(y) cap A = emptyset$. Then $D(y) subseteq B cap C$ and f restricted to $D(y)$ is an injection onto a proper subset. At least one of $A cap C$ and $B cap C$ must be Dedekind-infinite.







share|cite|improve this answer















share|cite|improve this answer



share|cite|improve this answer








edited Aug 8 at 23:28


























answered Jul 27 at 11:15









David Hartley

550148




550148











  • Very good, very good!
    – Asaf Karagila
    Jul 27 at 11:52










  • Could you give another hint, either about showing that the order on C is well, or about constructing the next-member injections?
    – Kyle MacDonald
    Aug 5 at 1:12










  • @Kyle MacDonald I've added some more details now. Sorry it's taken so long, I've been rather busy.
    – David Hartley
    Aug 8 at 23:33
















  • Very good, very good!
    – Asaf Karagila
    Jul 27 at 11:52










  • Could you give another hint, either about showing that the order on C is well, or about constructing the next-member injections?
    – Kyle MacDonald
    Aug 5 at 1:12










  • @Kyle MacDonald I've added some more details now. Sorry it's taken so long, I've been rather busy.
    – David Hartley
    Aug 8 at 23:33















Very good, very good!
– Asaf Karagila
Jul 27 at 11:52




Very good, very good!
– Asaf Karagila
Jul 27 at 11:52












Could you give another hint, either about showing that the order on C is well, or about constructing the next-member injections?
– Kyle MacDonald
Aug 5 at 1:12




Could you give another hint, either about showing that the order on C is well, or about constructing the next-member injections?
– Kyle MacDonald
Aug 5 at 1:12












@Kyle MacDonald I've added some more details now. Sorry it's taken so long, I've been rather busy.
– David Hartley
Aug 8 at 23:33




@Kyle MacDonald I've added some more details now. Sorry it's taken so long, I've been rather busy.
– David Hartley
Aug 8 at 23:33












 

draft saved


draft discarded


























 


draft saved


draft discarded














StackExchange.ready(
function ()
StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmath.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f2863114%2fprove-that-if-a-and-b-are-dedekind-finite-then-so-is-their-union-without-us%23new-answer', 'question_page');

);

Post as a guest













































































Comments

Popular posts from this blog

What is the equation of a 3D cone with generalised tilt?

Color the edges and diagonals of a regular polygon

Relationship between determinant of matrix and determinant of adjoint?