Which part of this theorem and corresponding proof about relations is incorrect?

The name of the pictureThe name of the pictureThe name of the pictureClash Royale CLAN TAG#URR8PPP











up vote
0
down vote

favorite












I have a theorem and corresponding proof whose correctness I need to verify. The theorem is:



For any sets $A$, $B$, $C$, and $D$: $A$ x $B subseteq C$ x $D$ $implies$ $A subseteq C$ $land$ $B subseteq D$



The proof is:



Suppose $A$ x $B subseteq C$ x $D$. Let $a$ be an arbitrary element of $A$ and let $b$ be an aribtrary element of $B$. Then $(a, b) in A$ x $B$. So since $A$ x $B subseteq C$ x $D$, $(a, b) in C$ x $D$. Therefore $a in C$ and $b in D$. Since $a$ and $b$ were arbitrary elements of $A$ and $B$, respectively, this shows that $A subseteq C$ and $B subseteq D$.



The above proof is demonstratably wrong with the case where $A = 1$, and $B = C = D = emptyset$, but I cannot find the flaw in the logic.



Following my own reasoning gives me:



$1)$ Assuming the 'P' of the conditional: $Givens = $$A$ x $B subseteq C$ x $D$, $Goals = A subseteq C, B subseteq D$



$2)$ Assuming arbitrary $a$ and $b$, assuming $a in A$ and $b in B$: $Givens = $$A$ x $B subseteq C$ x $D, a in A, b in B$, $Goals = a in C, b in D$



$3)$ Note that $(a, b) in A$ x $B implies (a, b) in C$ x $D implies a in C land b in D$



$4)$ Since $a in A land b in B$, we can create an ordered pair, $(a, b)$ such that $(a, b) in A$ x $B$, which appears to lead to the conclusion noted in $3)$, thus satisfying our goals.



Which is just a rambling version of the original proof.







share|cite|improve this question















  • 2




    "Assuming $ain A$ and $bin B$" assumes that you can choose such an $a$ and $b$. In the case that $B$ is empty, of course such a choice is invalid.
    – JMoravitz
    Jul 25 at 22:22










  • Thank you, so a corrected form of the theorem would be: $A$ x $B subseteq C$ x $D land A neq emptyset land B neq emptyset ...$ $implies$ $A subseteq C$ $land$ $B subseteq D$?
    – user2780519
    Jul 25 at 22:37











  • Yes, alternatively to keep the statement cleaner you should include the restrictions on $A$ and $B$ when you define the variables: "For any non-empty sets $A,B,C,D$..."
    – JMoravitz
    Jul 25 at 22:40










  • Cheers, I always end up missing an edge case or two..
    – user2780519
    Jul 25 at 22:47














up vote
0
down vote

favorite












I have a theorem and corresponding proof whose correctness I need to verify. The theorem is:



For any sets $A$, $B$, $C$, and $D$: $A$ x $B subseteq C$ x $D$ $implies$ $A subseteq C$ $land$ $B subseteq D$



The proof is:



Suppose $A$ x $B subseteq C$ x $D$. Let $a$ be an arbitrary element of $A$ and let $b$ be an aribtrary element of $B$. Then $(a, b) in A$ x $B$. So since $A$ x $B subseteq C$ x $D$, $(a, b) in C$ x $D$. Therefore $a in C$ and $b in D$. Since $a$ and $b$ were arbitrary elements of $A$ and $B$, respectively, this shows that $A subseteq C$ and $B subseteq D$.



The above proof is demonstratably wrong with the case where $A = 1$, and $B = C = D = emptyset$, but I cannot find the flaw in the logic.



Following my own reasoning gives me:



$1)$ Assuming the 'P' of the conditional: $Givens = $$A$ x $B subseteq C$ x $D$, $Goals = A subseteq C, B subseteq D$



$2)$ Assuming arbitrary $a$ and $b$, assuming $a in A$ and $b in B$: $Givens = $$A$ x $B subseteq C$ x $D, a in A, b in B$, $Goals = a in C, b in D$



$3)$ Note that $(a, b) in A$ x $B implies (a, b) in C$ x $D implies a in C land b in D$



$4)$ Since $a in A land b in B$, we can create an ordered pair, $(a, b)$ such that $(a, b) in A$ x $B$, which appears to lead to the conclusion noted in $3)$, thus satisfying our goals.



Which is just a rambling version of the original proof.







share|cite|improve this question















  • 2




    "Assuming $ain A$ and $bin B$" assumes that you can choose such an $a$ and $b$. In the case that $B$ is empty, of course such a choice is invalid.
    – JMoravitz
    Jul 25 at 22:22










  • Thank you, so a corrected form of the theorem would be: $A$ x $B subseteq C$ x $D land A neq emptyset land B neq emptyset ...$ $implies$ $A subseteq C$ $land$ $B subseteq D$?
    – user2780519
    Jul 25 at 22:37











  • Yes, alternatively to keep the statement cleaner you should include the restrictions on $A$ and $B$ when you define the variables: "For any non-empty sets $A,B,C,D$..."
    – JMoravitz
    Jul 25 at 22:40










  • Cheers, I always end up missing an edge case or two..
    – user2780519
    Jul 25 at 22:47












up vote
0
down vote

favorite









up vote
0
down vote

favorite











I have a theorem and corresponding proof whose correctness I need to verify. The theorem is:



For any sets $A$, $B$, $C$, and $D$: $A$ x $B subseteq C$ x $D$ $implies$ $A subseteq C$ $land$ $B subseteq D$



The proof is:



Suppose $A$ x $B subseteq C$ x $D$. Let $a$ be an arbitrary element of $A$ and let $b$ be an aribtrary element of $B$. Then $(a, b) in A$ x $B$. So since $A$ x $B subseteq C$ x $D$, $(a, b) in C$ x $D$. Therefore $a in C$ and $b in D$. Since $a$ and $b$ were arbitrary elements of $A$ and $B$, respectively, this shows that $A subseteq C$ and $B subseteq D$.



The above proof is demonstratably wrong with the case where $A = 1$, and $B = C = D = emptyset$, but I cannot find the flaw in the logic.



Following my own reasoning gives me:



$1)$ Assuming the 'P' of the conditional: $Givens = $$A$ x $B subseteq C$ x $D$, $Goals = A subseteq C, B subseteq D$



$2)$ Assuming arbitrary $a$ and $b$, assuming $a in A$ and $b in B$: $Givens = $$A$ x $B subseteq C$ x $D, a in A, b in B$, $Goals = a in C, b in D$



$3)$ Note that $(a, b) in A$ x $B implies (a, b) in C$ x $D implies a in C land b in D$



$4)$ Since $a in A land b in B$, we can create an ordered pair, $(a, b)$ such that $(a, b) in A$ x $B$, which appears to lead to the conclusion noted in $3)$, thus satisfying our goals.



Which is just a rambling version of the original proof.







share|cite|improve this question











I have a theorem and corresponding proof whose correctness I need to verify. The theorem is:



For any sets $A$, $B$, $C$, and $D$: $A$ x $B subseteq C$ x $D$ $implies$ $A subseteq C$ $land$ $B subseteq D$



The proof is:



Suppose $A$ x $B subseteq C$ x $D$. Let $a$ be an arbitrary element of $A$ and let $b$ be an aribtrary element of $B$. Then $(a, b) in A$ x $B$. So since $A$ x $B subseteq C$ x $D$, $(a, b) in C$ x $D$. Therefore $a in C$ and $b in D$. Since $a$ and $b$ were arbitrary elements of $A$ and $B$, respectively, this shows that $A subseteq C$ and $B subseteq D$.



The above proof is demonstratably wrong with the case where $A = 1$, and $B = C = D = emptyset$, but I cannot find the flaw in the logic.



Following my own reasoning gives me:



$1)$ Assuming the 'P' of the conditional: $Givens = $$A$ x $B subseteq C$ x $D$, $Goals = A subseteq C, B subseteq D$



$2)$ Assuming arbitrary $a$ and $b$, assuming $a in A$ and $b in B$: $Givens = $$A$ x $B subseteq C$ x $D, a in A, b in B$, $Goals = a in C, b in D$



$3)$ Note that $(a, b) in A$ x $B implies (a, b) in C$ x $D implies a in C land b in D$



$4)$ Since $a in A land b in B$, we can create an ordered pair, $(a, b)$ such that $(a, b) in A$ x $B$, which appears to lead to the conclusion noted in $3)$, thus satisfying our goals.



Which is just a rambling version of the original proof.









share|cite|improve this question










share|cite|improve this question




share|cite|improve this question









asked Jul 25 at 22:19









user2780519

133




133







  • 2




    "Assuming $ain A$ and $bin B$" assumes that you can choose such an $a$ and $b$. In the case that $B$ is empty, of course such a choice is invalid.
    – JMoravitz
    Jul 25 at 22:22










  • Thank you, so a corrected form of the theorem would be: $A$ x $B subseteq C$ x $D land A neq emptyset land B neq emptyset ...$ $implies$ $A subseteq C$ $land$ $B subseteq D$?
    – user2780519
    Jul 25 at 22:37











  • Yes, alternatively to keep the statement cleaner you should include the restrictions on $A$ and $B$ when you define the variables: "For any non-empty sets $A,B,C,D$..."
    – JMoravitz
    Jul 25 at 22:40










  • Cheers, I always end up missing an edge case or two..
    – user2780519
    Jul 25 at 22:47












  • 2




    "Assuming $ain A$ and $bin B$" assumes that you can choose such an $a$ and $b$. In the case that $B$ is empty, of course such a choice is invalid.
    – JMoravitz
    Jul 25 at 22:22










  • Thank you, so a corrected form of the theorem would be: $A$ x $B subseteq C$ x $D land A neq emptyset land B neq emptyset ...$ $implies$ $A subseteq C$ $land$ $B subseteq D$?
    – user2780519
    Jul 25 at 22:37











  • Yes, alternatively to keep the statement cleaner you should include the restrictions on $A$ and $B$ when you define the variables: "For any non-empty sets $A,B,C,D$..."
    – JMoravitz
    Jul 25 at 22:40










  • Cheers, I always end up missing an edge case or two..
    – user2780519
    Jul 25 at 22:47







2




2




"Assuming $ain A$ and $bin B$" assumes that you can choose such an $a$ and $b$. In the case that $B$ is empty, of course such a choice is invalid.
– JMoravitz
Jul 25 at 22:22




"Assuming $ain A$ and $bin B$" assumes that you can choose such an $a$ and $b$. In the case that $B$ is empty, of course such a choice is invalid.
– JMoravitz
Jul 25 at 22:22












Thank you, so a corrected form of the theorem would be: $A$ x $B subseteq C$ x $D land A neq emptyset land B neq emptyset ...$ $implies$ $A subseteq C$ $land$ $B subseteq D$?
– user2780519
Jul 25 at 22:37





Thank you, so a corrected form of the theorem would be: $A$ x $B subseteq C$ x $D land A neq emptyset land B neq emptyset ...$ $implies$ $A subseteq C$ $land$ $B subseteq D$?
– user2780519
Jul 25 at 22:37













Yes, alternatively to keep the statement cleaner you should include the restrictions on $A$ and $B$ when you define the variables: "For any non-empty sets $A,B,C,D$..."
– JMoravitz
Jul 25 at 22:40




Yes, alternatively to keep the statement cleaner you should include the restrictions on $A$ and $B$ when you define the variables: "For any non-empty sets $A,B,C,D$..."
– JMoravitz
Jul 25 at 22:40












Cheers, I always end up missing an edge case or two..
– user2780519
Jul 25 at 22:47




Cheers, I always end up missing an edge case or two..
– user2780519
Jul 25 at 22:47










1 Answer
1






active

oldest

votes

















up vote
0
down vote



accepted










If we rewrite the proof, the flaw becomes more apparent:




Given arbitrary element $a$ of $A$, $a$ we can form an ordered pair $(a,b)$ where $b$ is in $B$. Since $(a,b)$ would then be in $AxB$, it follows that it is $CxD$, and thus $a$ is in $C$. A similar argument shows that $b$ is in $D$.




The flaw is in the "we can form an ordered pair $(a,b)$" part. If B is empty, then we can't form any ordered pairs containing $a$, and thus the proof that $a$ is in $C$ fails.






share|cite|improve this answer





















    Your Answer




    StackExchange.ifUsing("editor", function ()
    return StackExchange.using("mathjaxEditing", function ()
    StackExchange.MarkdownEditor.creationCallbacks.add(function (editor, postfix)
    StackExchange.mathjaxEditing.prepareWmdForMathJax(editor, postfix, [["$", "$"], ["\\(","\\)"]]);
    );
    );
    , "mathjax-editing");

    StackExchange.ready(function()
    var channelOptions =
    tags: "".split(" "),
    id: "69"
    ;
    initTagRenderer("".split(" "), "".split(" "), channelOptions);

    StackExchange.using("externalEditor", function()
    // Have to fire editor after snippets, if snippets enabled
    if (StackExchange.settings.snippets.snippetsEnabled)
    StackExchange.using("snippets", function()
    createEditor();
    );

    else
    createEditor();

    );

    function createEditor()
    StackExchange.prepareEditor(
    heartbeatType: 'answer',
    convertImagesToLinks: true,
    noModals: false,
    showLowRepImageUploadWarning: true,
    reputationToPostImages: 10,
    bindNavPrevention: true,
    postfix: "",
    noCode: true, onDemand: true,
    discardSelector: ".discard-answer"
    ,immediatelyShowMarkdownHelp:true
    );



    );








     

    draft saved


    draft discarded


















    StackExchange.ready(
    function ()
    StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmath.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f2862882%2fwhich-part-of-this-theorem-and-corresponding-proof-about-relations-is-incorrect%23new-answer', 'question_page');

    );

    Post as a guest






























    1 Answer
    1






    active

    oldest

    votes








    1 Answer
    1






    active

    oldest

    votes









    active

    oldest

    votes






    active

    oldest

    votes








    up vote
    0
    down vote



    accepted










    If we rewrite the proof, the flaw becomes more apparent:




    Given arbitrary element $a$ of $A$, $a$ we can form an ordered pair $(a,b)$ where $b$ is in $B$. Since $(a,b)$ would then be in $AxB$, it follows that it is $CxD$, and thus $a$ is in $C$. A similar argument shows that $b$ is in $D$.




    The flaw is in the "we can form an ordered pair $(a,b)$" part. If B is empty, then we can't form any ordered pairs containing $a$, and thus the proof that $a$ is in $C$ fails.






    share|cite|improve this answer

























      up vote
      0
      down vote



      accepted










      If we rewrite the proof, the flaw becomes more apparent:




      Given arbitrary element $a$ of $A$, $a$ we can form an ordered pair $(a,b)$ where $b$ is in $B$. Since $(a,b)$ would then be in $AxB$, it follows that it is $CxD$, and thus $a$ is in $C$. A similar argument shows that $b$ is in $D$.




      The flaw is in the "we can form an ordered pair $(a,b)$" part. If B is empty, then we can't form any ordered pairs containing $a$, and thus the proof that $a$ is in $C$ fails.






      share|cite|improve this answer























        up vote
        0
        down vote



        accepted







        up vote
        0
        down vote



        accepted






        If we rewrite the proof, the flaw becomes more apparent:




        Given arbitrary element $a$ of $A$, $a$ we can form an ordered pair $(a,b)$ where $b$ is in $B$. Since $(a,b)$ would then be in $AxB$, it follows that it is $CxD$, and thus $a$ is in $C$. A similar argument shows that $b$ is in $D$.




        The flaw is in the "we can form an ordered pair $(a,b)$" part. If B is empty, then we can't form any ordered pairs containing $a$, and thus the proof that $a$ is in $C$ fails.






        share|cite|improve this answer













        If we rewrite the proof, the flaw becomes more apparent:




        Given arbitrary element $a$ of $A$, $a$ we can form an ordered pair $(a,b)$ where $b$ is in $B$. Since $(a,b)$ would then be in $AxB$, it follows that it is $CxD$, and thus $a$ is in $C$. A similar argument shows that $b$ is in $D$.




        The flaw is in the "we can form an ordered pair $(a,b)$" part. If B is empty, then we can't form any ordered pairs containing $a$, and thus the proof that $a$ is in $C$ fails.







        share|cite|improve this answer













        share|cite|improve this answer



        share|cite|improve this answer











        answered Jul 25 at 22:41









        Acccumulation

        4,4352314




        4,4352314






















             

            draft saved


            draft discarded


























             


            draft saved


            draft discarded














            StackExchange.ready(
            function ()
            StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmath.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f2862882%2fwhich-part-of-this-theorem-and-corresponding-proof-about-relations-is-incorrect%23new-answer', 'question_page');

            );

            Post as a guest













































































            Comments

            Popular posts from this blog

            What is the equation of a 3D cone with generalised tilt?

            Color the edges and diagonals of a regular polygon

            Relationship between determinant of matrix and determinant of adjoint?