Proving that every chain in a Dedekind-finite poset has an upper bound

The name of the pictureThe name of the pictureThe name of the pictureClash Royale CLAN TAG#URR8PPP











up vote
0
down vote

favorite












I'd like to be able to prove the statement in the title's subordinate clause: if $P$ is a Dedekind-finite partially ordered set and $T subset P$ is totally ordered, then $T$ has an upper bound in $P$. Here's what I've tried, essentially building up the natural numbers inside $T$ using AC using an approach based on this answer, but I'd like to know 1) how to finish up this proof if it can be made to work, 2) if there is a proof that uses a weaker choice axiom, or none at all, and 3) if there is a proof that avoids the natural numbers.



Let $(P, leq)$ be a partially ordered set and $T subset P$ a nonempty, totally ordered subset with no upper bound in $P$. Use AC to define $sigma: T to T$ by choosing some $sigma(t) > t$ for each $t in T$. Choose some $z in T$ and consider the collection of all subsets $S subset T$ satisfying $z in S$, $z leq s$ for all $s in S$, and $sigma(S) subset S$; this collection is nonempty since it contains the set $ s in T: z leq s $. Let $N$ be the intersection of all such subsets $S$. Clearly $N$ is nonempty since it contains $z$, and also $sigma(N) subset N$.



At this point, I'd like to be able to show that $N$ is well-ordered by $leq$ and that $sigma$ acts on $N$ as the successor function, i.e. $sigma(n) = minm in N: m > n $. This would imply that $sigma$ is an injection, proving that $P$ contains a Dedekind-infinite set and is therefore Dedekind-infinite, proving the desired statement by contrapositive.



However, I have no clue how to show that $N$ is well-ordered by $leq$, if in fact it is, and I'd be interested in seeing a proof that doesn't build up this much machinery. It feels there's probably a simple argument I'm not seeing.







share|cite|improve this question





















  • Isn't "every chain in a nonempty Dedekind-finite poset has an upper bound" equivalent to "every nonempty Dedekind-finite totally ordered set has a greatest element"? Is there some advantage to stating it in the more general form?
    – bof
    2 days ago










  • @bof Yes, you're quite right! I didn't realize that while I was typing it. I've actually found a solution, which is a little less heavy-handed than "take the intersection of everything in the room and hope for the best", but I'm not sure about the etiquette of answering one's own question.
    – Kyle MacDonald
    2 days ago










  • Answering your own question is perfectly fine.
    – bof
    2 days ago










  • math.meta.stackexchange.com/questions/4680/…
    – bof
    2 days ago










  • Even many quite weak forms of Choice imply that Dedekind-finite = finite, so is there any point in attempting a proof that uses AC?
    – David Hartley
    2 days ago














up vote
0
down vote

favorite












I'd like to be able to prove the statement in the title's subordinate clause: if $P$ is a Dedekind-finite partially ordered set and $T subset P$ is totally ordered, then $T$ has an upper bound in $P$. Here's what I've tried, essentially building up the natural numbers inside $T$ using AC using an approach based on this answer, but I'd like to know 1) how to finish up this proof if it can be made to work, 2) if there is a proof that uses a weaker choice axiom, or none at all, and 3) if there is a proof that avoids the natural numbers.



Let $(P, leq)$ be a partially ordered set and $T subset P$ a nonempty, totally ordered subset with no upper bound in $P$. Use AC to define $sigma: T to T$ by choosing some $sigma(t) > t$ for each $t in T$. Choose some $z in T$ and consider the collection of all subsets $S subset T$ satisfying $z in S$, $z leq s$ for all $s in S$, and $sigma(S) subset S$; this collection is nonempty since it contains the set $ s in T: z leq s $. Let $N$ be the intersection of all such subsets $S$. Clearly $N$ is nonempty since it contains $z$, and also $sigma(N) subset N$.



At this point, I'd like to be able to show that $N$ is well-ordered by $leq$ and that $sigma$ acts on $N$ as the successor function, i.e. $sigma(n) = minm in N: m > n $. This would imply that $sigma$ is an injection, proving that $P$ contains a Dedekind-infinite set and is therefore Dedekind-infinite, proving the desired statement by contrapositive.



However, I have no clue how to show that $N$ is well-ordered by $leq$, if in fact it is, and I'd be interested in seeing a proof that doesn't build up this much machinery. It feels there's probably a simple argument I'm not seeing.







share|cite|improve this question





















  • Isn't "every chain in a nonempty Dedekind-finite poset has an upper bound" equivalent to "every nonempty Dedekind-finite totally ordered set has a greatest element"? Is there some advantage to stating it in the more general form?
    – bof
    2 days ago










  • @bof Yes, you're quite right! I didn't realize that while I was typing it. I've actually found a solution, which is a little less heavy-handed than "take the intersection of everything in the room and hope for the best", but I'm not sure about the etiquette of answering one's own question.
    – Kyle MacDonald
    2 days ago










  • Answering your own question is perfectly fine.
    – bof
    2 days ago










  • math.meta.stackexchange.com/questions/4680/…
    – bof
    2 days ago










  • Even many quite weak forms of Choice imply that Dedekind-finite = finite, so is there any point in attempting a proof that uses AC?
    – David Hartley
    2 days ago












up vote
0
down vote

favorite









up vote
0
down vote

favorite











I'd like to be able to prove the statement in the title's subordinate clause: if $P$ is a Dedekind-finite partially ordered set and $T subset P$ is totally ordered, then $T$ has an upper bound in $P$. Here's what I've tried, essentially building up the natural numbers inside $T$ using AC using an approach based on this answer, but I'd like to know 1) how to finish up this proof if it can be made to work, 2) if there is a proof that uses a weaker choice axiom, or none at all, and 3) if there is a proof that avoids the natural numbers.



Let $(P, leq)$ be a partially ordered set and $T subset P$ a nonempty, totally ordered subset with no upper bound in $P$. Use AC to define $sigma: T to T$ by choosing some $sigma(t) > t$ for each $t in T$. Choose some $z in T$ and consider the collection of all subsets $S subset T$ satisfying $z in S$, $z leq s$ for all $s in S$, and $sigma(S) subset S$; this collection is nonempty since it contains the set $ s in T: z leq s $. Let $N$ be the intersection of all such subsets $S$. Clearly $N$ is nonempty since it contains $z$, and also $sigma(N) subset N$.



At this point, I'd like to be able to show that $N$ is well-ordered by $leq$ and that $sigma$ acts on $N$ as the successor function, i.e. $sigma(n) = minm in N: m > n $. This would imply that $sigma$ is an injection, proving that $P$ contains a Dedekind-infinite set and is therefore Dedekind-infinite, proving the desired statement by contrapositive.



However, I have no clue how to show that $N$ is well-ordered by $leq$, if in fact it is, and I'd be interested in seeing a proof that doesn't build up this much machinery. It feels there's probably a simple argument I'm not seeing.







share|cite|improve this question













I'd like to be able to prove the statement in the title's subordinate clause: if $P$ is a Dedekind-finite partially ordered set and $T subset P$ is totally ordered, then $T$ has an upper bound in $P$. Here's what I've tried, essentially building up the natural numbers inside $T$ using AC using an approach based on this answer, but I'd like to know 1) how to finish up this proof if it can be made to work, 2) if there is a proof that uses a weaker choice axiom, or none at all, and 3) if there is a proof that avoids the natural numbers.



Let $(P, leq)$ be a partially ordered set and $T subset P$ a nonempty, totally ordered subset with no upper bound in $P$. Use AC to define $sigma: T to T$ by choosing some $sigma(t) > t$ for each $t in T$. Choose some $z in T$ and consider the collection of all subsets $S subset T$ satisfying $z in S$, $z leq s$ for all $s in S$, and $sigma(S) subset S$; this collection is nonempty since it contains the set $ s in T: z leq s $. Let $N$ be the intersection of all such subsets $S$. Clearly $N$ is nonempty since it contains $z$, and also $sigma(N) subset N$.



At this point, I'd like to be able to show that $N$ is well-ordered by $leq$ and that $sigma$ acts on $N$ as the successor function, i.e. $sigma(n) = minm in N: m > n $. This would imply that $sigma$ is an injection, proving that $P$ contains a Dedekind-infinite set and is therefore Dedekind-infinite, proving the desired statement by contrapositive.



However, I have no clue how to show that $N$ is well-ordered by $leq$, if in fact it is, and I'd be interested in seeing a proof that doesn't build up this much machinery. It feels there's probably a simple argument I'm not seeing.









share|cite|improve this question












share|cite|improve this question




share|cite|improve this question








edited Aug 4 at 0:51
























asked Aug 4 at 0:30









Kyle MacDonald

1066




1066











  • Isn't "every chain in a nonempty Dedekind-finite poset has an upper bound" equivalent to "every nonempty Dedekind-finite totally ordered set has a greatest element"? Is there some advantage to stating it in the more general form?
    – bof
    2 days ago










  • @bof Yes, you're quite right! I didn't realize that while I was typing it. I've actually found a solution, which is a little less heavy-handed than "take the intersection of everything in the room and hope for the best", but I'm not sure about the etiquette of answering one's own question.
    – Kyle MacDonald
    2 days ago










  • Answering your own question is perfectly fine.
    – bof
    2 days ago










  • math.meta.stackexchange.com/questions/4680/…
    – bof
    2 days ago










  • Even many quite weak forms of Choice imply that Dedekind-finite = finite, so is there any point in attempting a proof that uses AC?
    – David Hartley
    2 days ago
















  • Isn't "every chain in a nonempty Dedekind-finite poset has an upper bound" equivalent to "every nonempty Dedekind-finite totally ordered set has a greatest element"? Is there some advantage to stating it in the more general form?
    – bof
    2 days ago










  • @bof Yes, you're quite right! I didn't realize that while I was typing it. I've actually found a solution, which is a little less heavy-handed than "take the intersection of everything in the room and hope for the best", but I'm not sure about the etiquette of answering one's own question.
    – Kyle MacDonald
    2 days ago










  • Answering your own question is perfectly fine.
    – bof
    2 days ago










  • math.meta.stackexchange.com/questions/4680/…
    – bof
    2 days ago










  • Even many quite weak forms of Choice imply that Dedekind-finite = finite, so is there any point in attempting a proof that uses AC?
    – David Hartley
    2 days ago















Isn't "every chain in a nonempty Dedekind-finite poset has an upper bound" equivalent to "every nonempty Dedekind-finite totally ordered set has a greatest element"? Is there some advantage to stating it in the more general form?
– bof
2 days ago




Isn't "every chain in a nonempty Dedekind-finite poset has an upper bound" equivalent to "every nonempty Dedekind-finite totally ordered set has a greatest element"? Is there some advantage to stating it in the more general form?
– bof
2 days ago












@bof Yes, you're quite right! I didn't realize that while I was typing it. I've actually found a solution, which is a little less heavy-handed than "take the intersection of everything in the room and hope for the best", but I'm not sure about the etiquette of answering one's own question.
– Kyle MacDonald
2 days ago




@bof Yes, you're quite right! I didn't realize that while I was typing it. I've actually found a solution, which is a little less heavy-handed than "take the intersection of everything in the room and hope for the best", but I'm not sure about the etiquette of answering one's own question.
– Kyle MacDonald
2 days ago












Answering your own question is perfectly fine.
– bof
2 days ago




Answering your own question is perfectly fine.
– bof
2 days ago












math.meta.stackexchange.com/questions/4680/…
– bof
2 days ago




math.meta.stackexchange.com/questions/4680/…
– bof
2 days ago












Even many quite weak forms of Choice imply that Dedekind-finite = finite, so is there any point in attempting a proof that uses AC?
– David Hartley
2 days ago




Even many quite weak forms of Choice imply that Dedekind-finite = finite, so is there any point in attempting a proof that uses AC?
– David Hartley
2 days ago










1 Answer
1






active

oldest

votes

















up vote
1
down vote













As bof observed, your claim is equivalent to, every non-empty totally-ordered Dedekind-finite set has a maximum. But that implies every non-empty subset of such a set also has a maximum and, by reversing the order, a minimum. I.e. every such set is well-ordered and so finite. There are apparently models of ZF with infinite, Dedekind-finite sets of reals and so your claim cannot be proved without some extra assumption.






share|cite|improve this answer





















  • Thanks for pointing that out -- I've got a proof that uses Zorn quite liberally, and will post it for completeness, but it's good to know that something more than ZF really is necessary.
    – Kyle MacDonald
    2 days ago










Your Answer




StackExchange.ifUsing("editor", function ()
return StackExchange.using("mathjaxEditing", function ()
StackExchange.MarkdownEditor.creationCallbacks.add(function (editor, postfix)
StackExchange.mathjaxEditing.prepareWmdForMathJax(editor, postfix, [["$", "$"], ["\\(","\\)"]]);
);
);
, "mathjax-editing");

StackExchange.ready(function()
var channelOptions =
tags: "".split(" "),
id: "69"
;
initTagRenderer("".split(" "), "".split(" "), channelOptions);

StackExchange.using("externalEditor", function()
// Have to fire editor after snippets, if snippets enabled
if (StackExchange.settings.snippets.snippetsEnabled)
StackExchange.using("snippets", function()
createEditor();
);

else
createEditor();

);

function createEditor()
StackExchange.prepareEditor(
heartbeatType: 'answer',
convertImagesToLinks: true,
noModals: false,
showLowRepImageUploadWarning: true,
reputationToPostImages: 10,
bindNavPrevention: true,
postfix: "",
noCode: true, onDemand: true,
discardSelector: ".discard-answer"
,immediatelyShowMarkdownHelp:true
);



);








 

draft saved


draft discarded


















StackExchange.ready(
function ()
StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmath.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f2871604%2fproving-that-every-chain-in-a-dedekind-finite-poset-has-an-upper-bound%23new-answer', 'question_page');

);

Post as a guest






























1 Answer
1






active

oldest

votes








1 Answer
1






active

oldest

votes









active

oldest

votes






active

oldest

votes








up vote
1
down vote













As bof observed, your claim is equivalent to, every non-empty totally-ordered Dedekind-finite set has a maximum. But that implies every non-empty subset of such a set also has a maximum and, by reversing the order, a minimum. I.e. every such set is well-ordered and so finite. There are apparently models of ZF with infinite, Dedekind-finite sets of reals and so your claim cannot be proved without some extra assumption.






share|cite|improve this answer





















  • Thanks for pointing that out -- I've got a proof that uses Zorn quite liberally, and will post it for completeness, but it's good to know that something more than ZF really is necessary.
    – Kyle MacDonald
    2 days ago














up vote
1
down vote













As bof observed, your claim is equivalent to, every non-empty totally-ordered Dedekind-finite set has a maximum. But that implies every non-empty subset of such a set also has a maximum and, by reversing the order, a minimum. I.e. every such set is well-ordered and so finite. There are apparently models of ZF with infinite, Dedekind-finite sets of reals and so your claim cannot be proved without some extra assumption.






share|cite|improve this answer





















  • Thanks for pointing that out -- I've got a proof that uses Zorn quite liberally, and will post it for completeness, but it's good to know that something more than ZF really is necessary.
    – Kyle MacDonald
    2 days ago












up vote
1
down vote










up vote
1
down vote









As bof observed, your claim is equivalent to, every non-empty totally-ordered Dedekind-finite set has a maximum. But that implies every non-empty subset of such a set also has a maximum and, by reversing the order, a minimum. I.e. every such set is well-ordered and so finite. There are apparently models of ZF with infinite, Dedekind-finite sets of reals and so your claim cannot be proved without some extra assumption.






share|cite|improve this answer













As bof observed, your claim is equivalent to, every non-empty totally-ordered Dedekind-finite set has a maximum. But that implies every non-empty subset of such a set also has a maximum and, by reversing the order, a minimum. I.e. every such set is well-ordered and so finite. There are apparently models of ZF with infinite, Dedekind-finite sets of reals and so your claim cannot be proved without some extra assumption.







share|cite|improve this answer













share|cite|improve this answer



share|cite|improve this answer











answered 2 days ago









David Hartley

550138




550138











  • Thanks for pointing that out -- I've got a proof that uses Zorn quite liberally, and will post it for completeness, but it's good to know that something more than ZF really is necessary.
    – Kyle MacDonald
    2 days ago
















  • Thanks for pointing that out -- I've got a proof that uses Zorn quite liberally, and will post it for completeness, but it's good to know that something more than ZF really is necessary.
    – Kyle MacDonald
    2 days ago















Thanks for pointing that out -- I've got a proof that uses Zorn quite liberally, and will post it for completeness, but it's good to know that something more than ZF really is necessary.
– Kyle MacDonald
2 days ago




Thanks for pointing that out -- I've got a proof that uses Zorn quite liberally, and will post it for completeness, but it's good to know that something more than ZF really is necessary.
– Kyle MacDonald
2 days ago












 

draft saved


draft discarded


























 


draft saved


draft discarded














StackExchange.ready(
function ()
StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmath.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f2871604%2fproving-that-every-chain-in-a-dedekind-finite-poset-has-an-upper-bound%23new-answer', 'question_page');

);

Post as a guest













































































Comments

Popular posts from this blog

What is the equation of a 3D cone with generalised tilt?

Relationship between determinant of matrix and determinant of adjoint?

Color the edges and diagonals of a regular polygon