Is EAO third figure valid in all cases?
Clash Royale CLAN TAG#URR8PPP
up vote
3
down vote
favorite
EAO third figure has the form :
M-P
M-S
S-P
As an example :
No men are roses
All men are cabbages
Some cabbages are not roses
I'm new to logic and I'm wondering how above syllogism is valid.
Suppose there are $2$ men, $500$ roses, and $100$ cabbages;
then the second premise does imply there exist 2 cabbages that are not roses. No issues so far.
But what if I choose $0$ men ? The first two premises seem to not care about this ?
logic
add a comment |Â
up vote
3
down vote
favorite
EAO third figure has the form :
M-P
M-S
S-P
As an example :
No men are roses
All men are cabbages
Some cabbages are not roses
I'm new to logic and I'm wondering how above syllogism is valid.
Suppose there are $2$ men, $500$ roses, and $100$ cabbages;
then the second premise does imply there exist 2 cabbages that are not roses. No issues so far.
But what if I choose $0$ men ? The first two premises seem to not care about this ?
logic
add a comment |Â
up vote
3
down vote
favorite
up vote
3
down vote
favorite
EAO third figure has the form :
M-P
M-S
S-P
As an example :
No men are roses
All men are cabbages
Some cabbages are not roses
I'm new to logic and I'm wondering how above syllogism is valid.
Suppose there are $2$ men, $500$ roses, and $100$ cabbages;
then the second premise does imply there exist 2 cabbages that are not roses. No issues so far.
But what if I choose $0$ men ? The first two premises seem to not care about this ?
logic
EAO third figure has the form :
M-P
M-S
S-P
As an example :
No men are roses
All men are cabbages
Some cabbages are not roses
I'm new to logic and I'm wondering how above syllogism is valid.
Suppose there are $2$ men, $500$ roses, and $100$ cabbages;
then the second premise does imply there exist 2 cabbages that are not roses. No issues so far.
But what if I choose $0$ men ? The first two premises seem to not care about this ?
logic
asked 2 days ago
rsadhvika
1,4891026
1,4891026
add a comment |Â
add a comment |Â
1 Answer
1
active
oldest
votes
up vote
4
down vote
There is a well-known distinction between unconditionally valid categorical syllogisms and conditionally valid categorical syllogisms.
EAO-3 is an example of a conditionally valid syllogism: if you assume that every class (category) of objects is non-empty (this assumption is sometimes called the Assumption of Categorical Import), then the syllogism is valid. But if you do not make that assumption, then you can indeed get a counterexample by using an empty category, as you found.
Indeed, any syllogism where both premises are universal statements, but the conclusion is an existential statement, can at best be conditionally valid.
Good to know that some valid forms require non-empty sets. I think I get this... Thank you so much :)
– rsadhvika
2 days ago
@rsadhvika You're welcome! :)
– Bram28
2 days ago
add a comment |Â
1 Answer
1
active
oldest
votes
1 Answer
1
active
oldest
votes
active
oldest
votes
active
oldest
votes
up vote
4
down vote
There is a well-known distinction between unconditionally valid categorical syllogisms and conditionally valid categorical syllogisms.
EAO-3 is an example of a conditionally valid syllogism: if you assume that every class (category) of objects is non-empty (this assumption is sometimes called the Assumption of Categorical Import), then the syllogism is valid. But if you do not make that assumption, then you can indeed get a counterexample by using an empty category, as you found.
Indeed, any syllogism where both premises are universal statements, but the conclusion is an existential statement, can at best be conditionally valid.
Good to know that some valid forms require non-empty sets. I think I get this... Thank you so much :)
– rsadhvika
2 days ago
@rsadhvika You're welcome! :)
– Bram28
2 days ago
add a comment |Â
up vote
4
down vote
There is a well-known distinction between unconditionally valid categorical syllogisms and conditionally valid categorical syllogisms.
EAO-3 is an example of a conditionally valid syllogism: if you assume that every class (category) of objects is non-empty (this assumption is sometimes called the Assumption of Categorical Import), then the syllogism is valid. But if you do not make that assumption, then you can indeed get a counterexample by using an empty category, as you found.
Indeed, any syllogism where both premises are universal statements, but the conclusion is an existential statement, can at best be conditionally valid.
Good to know that some valid forms require non-empty sets. I think I get this... Thank you so much :)
– rsadhvika
2 days ago
@rsadhvika You're welcome! :)
– Bram28
2 days ago
add a comment |Â
up vote
4
down vote
up vote
4
down vote
There is a well-known distinction between unconditionally valid categorical syllogisms and conditionally valid categorical syllogisms.
EAO-3 is an example of a conditionally valid syllogism: if you assume that every class (category) of objects is non-empty (this assumption is sometimes called the Assumption of Categorical Import), then the syllogism is valid. But if you do not make that assumption, then you can indeed get a counterexample by using an empty category, as you found.
Indeed, any syllogism where both premises are universal statements, but the conclusion is an existential statement, can at best be conditionally valid.
There is a well-known distinction between unconditionally valid categorical syllogisms and conditionally valid categorical syllogisms.
EAO-3 is an example of a conditionally valid syllogism: if you assume that every class (category) of objects is non-empty (this assumption is sometimes called the Assumption of Categorical Import), then the syllogism is valid. But if you do not make that assumption, then you can indeed get a counterexample by using an empty category, as you found.
Indeed, any syllogism where both premises are universal statements, but the conclusion is an existential statement, can at best be conditionally valid.
edited 2 days ago
answered 2 days ago
Bram28
54.5k33778
54.5k33778
Good to know that some valid forms require non-empty sets. I think I get this... Thank you so much :)
– rsadhvika
2 days ago
@rsadhvika You're welcome! :)
– Bram28
2 days ago
add a comment |Â
Good to know that some valid forms require non-empty sets. I think I get this... Thank you so much :)
– rsadhvika
2 days ago
@rsadhvika You're welcome! :)
– Bram28
2 days ago
Good to know that some valid forms require non-empty sets. I think I get this... Thank you so much :)
– rsadhvika
2 days ago
Good to know that some valid forms require non-empty sets. I think I get this... Thank you so much :)
– rsadhvika
2 days ago
@rsadhvika You're welcome! :)
– Bram28
2 days ago
@rsadhvika You're welcome! :)
– Bram28
2 days ago
add a comment |Â
Sign up or log in
StackExchange.ready(function ()
StackExchange.helpers.onClickDraftSave('#login-link');
);
Sign up using Google
Sign up using Facebook
Sign up using Email and Password
Post as a guest
StackExchange.ready(
function ()
StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmath.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f2872101%2fis-eao-third-figure-valid-in-all-cases%23new-answer', 'question_page');
);
Post as a guest
Sign up or log in
StackExchange.ready(function ()
StackExchange.helpers.onClickDraftSave('#login-link');
);
Sign up using Google
Sign up using Facebook
Sign up using Email and Password
Post as a guest
Sign up or log in
StackExchange.ready(function ()
StackExchange.helpers.onClickDraftSave('#login-link');
);
Sign up using Google
Sign up using Facebook
Sign up using Email and Password
Post as a guest
Sign up or log in
StackExchange.ready(function ()
StackExchange.helpers.onClickDraftSave('#login-link');
);
Sign up using Google
Sign up using Facebook
Sign up using Email and Password
Sign up using Google
Sign up using Facebook
Sign up using Email and Password