How to prove that $m < n Longleftrightarrow m + 1 < n + 1$ when defining natural numbers from scratch in ZFC?

The name of the pictureThe name of the pictureThe name of the pictureClash Royale CLAN TAG#URR8PPP











up vote
0
down vote

favorite












An important results for natural numbers and their ordering by $<$ (that is, $in$, $m < n$ means $m in n$) is that for any natural numbers $m,n$ and $k$, we have $m < n Longleftrightarrow m + 1 < n + 1$.



What preliminary results are needed? This is also a preliminary result, a lemma for the following result by induction: $forall m,n,k in mathbbN, m < n Longleftrightarrow m + k < n + k$.



Mathematical induction is assumed, of course, as is the fact that $m + 1 = mcupm$. Also, it has already been proven that $leq$ ($m leq n$ stands for $m < n$ or $m = n$) is a well-ordering on $mathbbN$. The addition is defined as follows: $forall m,n in mathbbN$,



  • $m + 0 = m$,


  • $m + (n + 1) = (m + n) + 1$.







share|cite|improve this question



















  • $m + 1 = mcupm$ is just one way to construct a set behaving like the natural numbers; the actual construction used should be of no consequence in an argument using the axioms. Once you've shown that your construction indeed fulfills the axioms, of course.
    – Arthur
    Jul 29 at 8:39







  • 1




    @Arthur: Depending on how you do things, you might want to argue that directly. And while it is true that the finite von Neumann ordinals is just one of many ways of doing this, it is also the standard way of constructing the natural numbers in set theory. So standard to the point that many people out side of set theory would consider it "the way of doing it" (which often has sour implications on the view people have on set theoretic foundations later in their life).
    – Asaf Karagila
    Jul 29 at 11:33














up vote
0
down vote

favorite












An important results for natural numbers and their ordering by $<$ (that is, $in$, $m < n$ means $m in n$) is that for any natural numbers $m,n$ and $k$, we have $m < n Longleftrightarrow m + 1 < n + 1$.



What preliminary results are needed? This is also a preliminary result, a lemma for the following result by induction: $forall m,n,k in mathbbN, m < n Longleftrightarrow m + k < n + k$.



Mathematical induction is assumed, of course, as is the fact that $m + 1 = mcupm$. Also, it has already been proven that $leq$ ($m leq n$ stands for $m < n$ or $m = n$) is a well-ordering on $mathbbN$. The addition is defined as follows: $forall m,n in mathbbN$,



  • $m + 0 = m$,


  • $m + (n + 1) = (m + n) + 1$.







share|cite|improve this question



















  • $m + 1 = mcupm$ is just one way to construct a set behaving like the natural numbers; the actual construction used should be of no consequence in an argument using the axioms. Once you've shown that your construction indeed fulfills the axioms, of course.
    – Arthur
    Jul 29 at 8:39







  • 1




    @Arthur: Depending on how you do things, you might want to argue that directly. And while it is true that the finite von Neumann ordinals is just one of many ways of doing this, it is also the standard way of constructing the natural numbers in set theory. So standard to the point that many people out side of set theory would consider it "the way of doing it" (which often has sour implications on the view people have on set theoretic foundations later in their life).
    – Asaf Karagila
    Jul 29 at 11:33












up vote
0
down vote

favorite









up vote
0
down vote

favorite











An important results for natural numbers and their ordering by $<$ (that is, $in$, $m < n$ means $m in n$) is that for any natural numbers $m,n$ and $k$, we have $m < n Longleftrightarrow m + 1 < n + 1$.



What preliminary results are needed? This is also a preliminary result, a lemma for the following result by induction: $forall m,n,k in mathbbN, m < n Longleftrightarrow m + k < n + k$.



Mathematical induction is assumed, of course, as is the fact that $m + 1 = mcupm$. Also, it has already been proven that $leq$ ($m leq n$ stands for $m < n$ or $m = n$) is a well-ordering on $mathbbN$. The addition is defined as follows: $forall m,n in mathbbN$,



  • $m + 0 = m$,


  • $m + (n + 1) = (m + n) + 1$.







share|cite|improve this question











An important results for natural numbers and their ordering by $<$ (that is, $in$, $m < n$ means $m in n$) is that for any natural numbers $m,n$ and $k$, we have $m < n Longleftrightarrow m + 1 < n + 1$.



What preliminary results are needed? This is also a preliminary result, a lemma for the following result by induction: $forall m,n,k in mathbbN, m < n Longleftrightarrow m + k < n + k$.



Mathematical induction is assumed, of course, as is the fact that $m + 1 = mcupm$. Also, it has already been proven that $leq$ ($m leq n$ stands for $m < n$ or $m = n$) is a well-ordering on $mathbbN$. The addition is defined as follows: $forall m,n in mathbbN$,



  • $m + 0 = m$,


  • $m + (n + 1) = (m + n) + 1$.









share|cite|improve this question










share|cite|improve this question




share|cite|improve this question









asked Jul 29 at 8:16









Jxt921

896616




896616











  • $m + 1 = mcupm$ is just one way to construct a set behaving like the natural numbers; the actual construction used should be of no consequence in an argument using the axioms. Once you've shown that your construction indeed fulfills the axioms, of course.
    – Arthur
    Jul 29 at 8:39







  • 1




    @Arthur: Depending on how you do things, you might want to argue that directly. And while it is true that the finite von Neumann ordinals is just one of many ways of doing this, it is also the standard way of constructing the natural numbers in set theory. So standard to the point that many people out side of set theory would consider it "the way of doing it" (which often has sour implications on the view people have on set theoretic foundations later in their life).
    – Asaf Karagila
    Jul 29 at 11:33
















  • $m + 1 = mcupm$ is just one way to construct a set behaving like the natural numbers; the actual construction used should be of no consequence in an argument using the axioms. Once you've shown that your construction indeed fulfills the axioms, of course.
    – Arthur
    Jul 29 at 8:39







  • 1




    @Arthur: Depending on how you do things, you might want to argue that directly. And while it is true that the finite von Neumann ordinals is just one of many ways of doing this, it is also the standard way of constructing the natural numbers in set theory. So standard to the point that many people out side of set theory would consider it "the way of doing it" (which often has sour implications on the view people have on set theoretic foundations later in their life).
    – Asaf Karagila
    Jul 29 at 11:33















$m + 1 = mcupm$ is just one way to construct a set behaving like the natural numbers; the actual construction used should be of no consequence in an argument using the axioms. Once you've shown that your construction indeed fulfills the axioms, of course.
– Arthur
Jul 29 at 8:39





$m + 1 = mcupm$ is just one way to construct a set behaving like the natural numbers; the actual construction used should be of no consequence in an argument using the axioms. Once you've shown that your construction indeed fulfills the axioms, of course.
– Arthur
Jul 29 at 8:39





1




1




@Arthur: Depending on how you do things, you might want to argue that directly. And while it is true that the finite von Neumann ordinals is just one of many ways of doing this, it is also the standard way of constructing the natural numbers in set theory. So standard to the point that many people out side of set theory would consider it "the way of doing it" (which often has sour implications on the view people have on set theoretic foundations later in their life).
– Asaf Karagila
Jul 29 at 11:33




@Arthur: Depending on how you do things, you might want to argue that directly. And while it is true that the finite von Neumann ordinals is just one of many ways of doing this, it is also the standard way of constructing the natural numbers in set theory. So standard to the point that many people out side of set theory would consider it "the way of doing it" (which often has sour implications on the view people have on set theoretic foundations later in their life).
– Asaf Karagila
Jul 29 at 11:33










1 Answer
1






active

oldest

votes

















up vote
5
down vote



accepted










First of all, if $m+1<n+1$, then $mcupmin ncupn$, therefore either $mcupm=n$, in which case $min n$ and we are done, or $mcupmin n$, in which case $min n$ and we are done again.



Secondly, if $min n$, then either $mcupmin n$, in which case we are clearly done; or $mcupm=n$, in which case $nin ncupn$ so $mcupmin ncupn$.




What did we use? We used the fact that $n$ is transitive, so $xin yin n$ means $xin n$. It is tempting that we directly appeal to the fact that $in$ is well-founded, and therefore there are no $in$-loops, but it doesn't matter. If they were are $in$-loops in that definition it would just show that $<$ is not a linear ordering (or a partial ordering for that matter), the proof would still work.






share|cite|improve this answer





















  • Thank you, Asaf. Trying by myself, I managed to do one side of the equivalence, namely the first one in your answer. As for the second one, from what I can see, there is an additional lemma required: for any natural numbers $m$ and $n$, $n < m$ implies $n + 1 leq m$.
    – Jxt921
    Jul 31 at 10:47










  • Hmm. It might be needed to have that $in$ is in fact well-founded (from which you can easily derive that $n+1leq m$).
    – Asaf Karagila
    Jul 31 at 11:40










  • I don't think it's necessary to use the axiom of foundation. In fact, we could use the result that $leq$ is a total order on $mathbbN$: assume that $n < m$. As $mathbbN$ is totally ordered by $leq$, then we have $n + 1 leq m$ or $m < n + 1$. The latter implies that either $m = n$ or $m < n$, contradicting $n < m$ due to transitive and irreflexive nature of $<$ as a strict order with respect to total order $leq$ on $mathbbN$.
    – Jxt921
    Jul 31 at 17:24










  • Oh, I meant that $in$ is well-founded on the natural numbers. If you already have that this is a total order, then it's even easier.
    – Asaf Karagila
    Jul 31 at 17:39










Your Answer




StackExchange.ifUsing("editor", function ()
return StackExchange.using("mathjaxEditing", function ()
StackExchange.MarkdownEditor.creationCallbacks.add(function (editor, postfix)
StackExchange.mathjaxEditing.prepareWmdForMathJax(editor, postfix, [["$", "$"], ["\\(","\\)"]]);
);
);
, "mathjax-editing");

StackExchange.ready(function()
var channelOptions =
tags: "".split(" "),
id: "69"
;
initTagRenderer("".split(" "), "".split(" "), channelOptions);

StackExchange.using("externalEditor", function()
// Have to fire editor after snippets, if snippets enabled
if (StackExchange.settings.snippets.snippetsEnabled)
StackExchange.using("snippets", function()
createEditor();
);

else
createEditor();

);

function createEditor()
StackExchange.prepareEditor(
heartbeatType: 'answer',
convertImagesToLinks: true,
noModals: false,
showLowRepImageUploadWarning: true,
reputationToPostImages: 10,
bindNavPrevention: true,
postfix: "",
noCode: true, onDemand: true,
discardSelector: ".discard-answer"
,immediatelyShowMarkdownHelp:true
);



);








 

draft saved


draft discarded


















StackExchange.ready(
function ()
StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmath.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f2865886%2fhow-to-prove-that-m-n-longleftrightarrow-m-1-n-1-when-defining-natura%23new-answer', 'question_page');

);

Post as a guest






























1 Answer
1






active

oldest

votes








1 Answer
1






active

oldest

votes









active

oldest

votes






active

oldest

votes








up vote
5
down vote



accepted










First of all, if $m+1<n+1$, then $mcupmin ncupn$, therefore either $mcupm=n$, in which case $min n$ and we are done, or $mcupmin n$, in which case $min n$ and we are done again.



Secondly, if $min n$, then either $mcupmin n$, in which case we are clearly done; or $mcupm=n$, in which case $nin ncupn$ so $mcupmin ncupn$.




What did we use? We used the fact that $n$ is transitive, so $xin yin n$ means $xin n$. It is tempting that we directly appeal to the fact that $in$ is well-founded, and therefore there are no $in$-loops, but it doesn't matter. If they were are $in$-loops in that definition it would just show that $<$ is not a linear ordering (or a partial ordering for that matter), the proof would still work.






share|cite|improve this answer





















  • Thank you, Asaf. Trying by myself, I managed to do one side of the equivalence, namely the first one in your answer. As for the second one, from what I can see, there is an additional lemma required: for any natural numbers $m$ and $n$, $n < m$ implies $n + 1 leq m$.
    – Jxt921
    Jul 31 at 10:47










  • Hmm. It might be needed to have that $in$ is in fact well-founded (from which you can easily derive that $n+1leq m$).
    – Asaf Karagila
    Jul 31 at 11:40










  • I don't think it's necessary to use the axiom of foundation. In fact, we could use the result that $leq$ is a total order on $mathbbN$: assume that $n < m$. As $mathbbN$ is totally ordered by $leq$, then we have $n + 1 leq m$ or $m < n + 1$. The latter implies that either $m = n$ or $m < n$, contradicting $n < m$ due to transitive and irreflexive nature of $<$ as a strict order with respect to total order $leq$ on $mathbbN$.
    – Jxt921
    Jul 31 at 17:24










  • Oh, I meant that $in$ is well-founded on the natural numbers. If you already have that this is a total order, then it's even easier.
    – Asaf Karagila
    Jul 31 at 17:39














up vote
5
down vote



accepted










First of all, if $m+1<n+1$, then $mcupmin ncupn$, therefore either $mcupm=n$, in which case $min n$ and we are done, or $mcupmin n$, in which case $min n$ and we are done again.



Secondly, if $min n$, then either $mcupmin n$, in which case we are clearly done; or $mcupm=n$, in which case $nin ncupn$ so $mcupmin ncupn$.




What did we use? We used the fact that $n$ is transitive, so $xin yin n$ means $xin n$. It is tempting that we directly appeal to the fact that $in$ is well-founded, and therefore there are no $in$-loops, but it doesn't matter. If they were are $in$-loops in that definition it would just show that $<$ is not a linear ordering (or a partial ordering for that matter), the proof would still work.






share|cite|improve this answer





















  • Thank you, Asaf. Trying by myself, I managed to do one side of the equivalence, namely the first one in your answer. As for the second one, from what I can see, there is an additional lemma required: for any natural numbers $m$ and $n$, $n < m$ implies $n + 1 leq m$.
    – Jxt921
    Jul 31 at 10:47










  • Hmm. It might be needed to have that $in$ is in fact well-founded (from which you can easily derive that $n+1leq m$).
    – Asaf Karagila
    Jul 31 at 11:40










  • I don't think it's necessary to use the axiom of foundation. In fact, we could use the result that $leq$ is a total order on $mathbbN$: assume that $n < m$. As $mathbbN$ is totally ordered by $leq$, then we have $n + 1 leq m$ or $m < n + 1$. The latter implies that either $m = n$ or $m < n$, contradicting $n < m$ due to transitive and irreflexive nature of $<$ as a strict order with respect to total order $leq$ on $mathbbN$.
    – Jxt921
    Jul 31 at 17:24










  • Oh, I meant that $in$ is well-founded on the natural numbers. If you already have that this is a total order, then it's even easier.
    – Asaf Karagila
    Jul 31 at 17:39












up vote
5
down vote



accepted







up vote
5
down vote



accepted






First of all, if $m+1<n+1$, then $mcupmin ncupn$, therefore either $mcupm=n$, in which case $min n$ and we are done, or $mcupmin n$, in which case $min n$ and we are done again.



Secondly, if $min n$, then either $mcupmin n$, in which case we are clearly done; or $mcupm=n$, in which case $nin ncupn$ so $mcupmin ncupn$.




What did we use? We used the fact that $n$ is transitive, so $xin yin n$ means $xin n$. It is tempting that we directly appeal to the fact that $in$ is well-founded, and therefore there are no $in$-loops, but it doesn't matter. If they were are $in$-loops in that definition it would just show that $<$ is not a linear ordering (or a partial ordering for that matter), the proof would still work.






share|cite|improve this answer













First of all, if $m+1<n+1$, then $mcupmin ncupn$, therefore either $mcupm=n$, in which case $min n$ and we are done, or $mcupmin n$, in which case $min n$ and we are done again.



Secondly, if $min n$, then either $mcupmin n$, in which case we are clearly done; or $mcupm=n$, in which case $nin ncupn$ so $mcupmin ncupn$.




What did we use? We used the fact that $n$ is transitive, so $xin yin n$ means $xin n$. It is tempting that we directly appeal to the fact that $in$ is well-founded, and therefore there are no $in$-loops, but it doesn't matter. If they were are $in$-loops in that definition it would just show that $<$ is not a linear ordering (or a partial ordering for that matter), the proof would still work.







share|cite|improve this answer













share|cite|improve this answer



share|cite|improve this answer











answered Jul 29 at 8:27









Asaf Karagila

291k31402732




291k31402732











  • Thank you, Asaf. Trying by myself, I managed to do one side of the equivalence, namely the first one in your answer. As for the second one, from what I can see, there is an additional lemma required: for any natural numbers $m$ and $n$, $n < m$ implies $n + 1 leq m$.
    – Jxt921
    Jul 31 at 10:47










  • Hmm. It might be needed to have that $in$ is in fact well-founded (from which you can easily derive that $n+1leq m$).
    – Asaf Karagila
    Jul 31 at 11:40










  • I don't think it's necessary to use the axiom of foundation. In fact, we could use the result that $leq$ is a total order on $mathbbN$: assume that $n < m$. As $mathbbN$ is totally ordered by $leq$, then we have $n + 1 leq m$ or $m < n + 1$. The latter implies that either $m = n$ or $m < n$, contradicting $n < m$ due to transitive and irreflexive nature of $<$ as a strict order with respect to total order $leq$ on $mathbbN$.
    – Jxt921
    Jul 31 at 17:24










  • Oh, I meant that $in$ is well-founded on the natural numbers. If you already have that this is a total order, then it's even easier.
    – Asaf Karagila
    Jul 31 at 17:39
















  • Thank you, Asaf. Trying by myself, I managed to do one side of the equivalence, namely the first one in your answer. As for the second one, from what I can see, there is an additional lemma required: for any natural numbers $m$ and $n$, $n < m$ implies $n + 1 leq m$.
    – Jxt921
    Jul 31 at 10:47










  • Hmm. It might be needed to have that $in$ is in fact well-founded (from which you can easily derive that $n+1leq m$).
    – Asaf Karagila
    Jul 31 at 11:40










  • I don't think it's necessary to use the axiom of foundation. In fact, we could use the result that $leq$ is a total order on $mathbbN$: assume that $n < m$. As $mathbbN$ is totally ordered by $leq$, then we have $n + 1 leq m$ or $m < n + 1$. The latter implies that either $m = n$ or $m < n$, contradicting $n < m$ due to transitive and irreflexive nature of $<$ as a strict order with respect to total order $leq$ on $mathbbN$.
    – Jxt921
    Jul 31 at 17:24










  • Oh, I meant that $in$ is well-founded on the natural numbers. If you already have that this is a total order, then it's even easier.
    – Asaf Karagila
    Jul 31 at 17:39















Thank you, Asaf. Trying by myself, I managed to do one side of the equivalence, namely the first one in your answer. As for the second one, from what I can see, there is an additional lemma required: for any natural numbers $m$ and $n$, $n < m$ implies $n + 1 leq m$.
– Jxt921
Jul 31 at 10:47




Thank you, Asaf. Trying by myself, I managed to do one side of the equivalence, namely the first one in your answer. As for the second one, from what I can see, there is an additional lemma required: for any natural numbers $m$ and $n$, $n < m$ implies $n + 1 leq m$.
– Jxt921
Jul 31 at 10:47












Hmm. It might be needed to have that $in$ is in fact well-founded (from which you can easily derive that $n+1leq m$).
– Asaf Karagila
Jul 31 at 11:40




Hmm. It might be needed to have that $in$ is in fact well-founded (from which you can easily derive that $n+1leq m$).
– Asaf Karagila
Jul 31 at 11:40












I don't think it's necessary to use the axiom of foundation. In fact, we could use the result that $leq$ is a total order on $mathbbN$: assume that $n < m$. As $mathbbN$ is totally ordered by $leq$, then we have $n + 1 leq m$ or $m < n + 1$. The latter implies that either $m = n$ or $m < n$, contradicting $n < m$ due to transitive and irreflexive nature of $<$ as a strict order with respect to total order $leq$ on $mathbbN$.
– Jxt921
Jul 31 at 17:24




I don't think it's necessary to use the axiom of foundation. In fact, we could use the result that $leq$ is a total order on $mathbbN$: assume that $n < m$. As $mathbbN$ is totally ordered by $leq$, then we have $n + 1 leq m$ or $m < n + 1$. The latter implies that either $m = n$ or $m < n$, contradicting $n < m$ due to transitive and irreflexive nature of $<$ as a strict order with respect to total order $leq$ on $mathbbN$.
– Jxt921
Jul 31 at 17:24












Oh, I meant that $in$ is well-founded on the natural numbers. If you already have that this is a total order, then it's even easier.
– Asaf Karagila
Jul 31 at 17:39




Oh, I meant that $in$ is well-founded on the natural numbers. If you already have that this is a total order, then it's even easier.
– Asaf Karagila
Jul 31 at 17:39












 

draft saved


draft discarded


























 


draft saved


draft discarded














StackExchange.ready(
function ()
StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmath.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f2865886%2fhow-to-prove-that-m-n-longleftrightarrow-m-1-n-1-when-defining-natura%23new-answer', 'question_page');

);

Post as a guest













































































Comments

Popular posts from this blog

What is the equation of a 3D cone with generalised tilt?

Color the edges and diagonals of a regular polygon

Relationship between determinant of matrix and determinant of adjoint?