Let $ A $ and $ B $ be arbitrary sets. Is there a function $ f:A times Ato B $ such that all functions from $A$ to $B$ are representable by $f$?

The name of the pictureThe name of the pictureThe name of the pictureClash Royale CLAN TAG#URR8PPP











up vote
1
down vote

favorite












$mathbfdef:$ let $A, B$ be sets, and $ f : A times A rightarrow B$ be any
function. A function$ g : A rightarrow B $ is representable by $f$ iff there is $ a in A$ such
that for all $ x in A, g(x) = f(x, a)$.



$mathbfTheorem:$ [Cantor’s Little Theorem] Let $ A, B $ be sets and $f : A × A → B$
be any function such that all functions $g : A → B$ are representable by $f$. Then
every function $φ : B → B$ has a fixed point.



$mathbfproof:$ Suppose that $f : A × A → B$ is such a function that all functions
$g : A → B$ are representable by $f$. Let $φ : B → B$ be any function. Define
a function $ψ : A → A × A$ , called Cantor’s diagonalization, by $ψ(x) = (x, x)$.
Let $h = φ ◦ f ◦ ψ$;Since the function $h : A → B$ is representable by $f$ , we have an $a ∈ A$
such that for all $x ∈ A, h(x) = f(x, a)$. In particular, $h(a) = f(a, a)$. But
$h(a) = φ(f(ψ(a))) = φ(f(a, a))$. Writing $f(a, a) = b$, we have $φ(b) = b$. Thus
$φ$ has a fixed point, namely,$b$.



$mathbfQuestion:$ It says Let $ A, B $ be sets and $f : A × A → B$
be any function such that $mathbfall$ functions $g : A → B$ are representable by $f$.This assumption seems logically wrong to me because the cardinality of the set of all functions from $A$ to $B$ is bigger than the cardinality of $A$,so how can there exists a function $f : A × A → B$
such that $mathbfall$ functions $g : A → B$ are representable by it?In the proof the assumption is applied to the function "h" (defined in the proof ).



link of the paper containing the theorem:https://mat.iitm.ac.in/home/asingh/public_html/papers/cantor.pdf







share|cite|improve this question

















  • 1




    And yet you seem fine with the idea that there are sets $B$ such that any function $Bto B$ has a fixed point? I would find that as counterintuitive, if not more. I can only think of one such set (or two, really, because of vacuous truths), and in that case your problem isn't really a problem.
    – Arthur
    Jul 15 at 10:31











  • It seems to be saying: "if there is such a function f, then ...."
    – Bram28
    Jul 15 at 10:32






  • 1




    @Arthur I can think of lots of sets $B$ such that every function $f:Bto B$ has a fixed point, but they are all isomorphic, they are all one-element sets. I don't believe there are any other examples. Do you have one?
    – bof
    Jul 15 at 10:46






  • 1




    @bumba But the consequence is important. If I said "If pigs can fly, then chickens have teeth", that's a true statement (with current gene editing technology, at least). But your objections here amount to "but pigs can't fly, how can that statement be true?" It is true exactly because the consequence isn't (except for a few trivial cases where the assumption is also true).
    – Arthur
    Jul 15 at 10:54







  • 1




    @Arthur Nope. If there were no functions $f:emptysettoemptyset$ then it would be true "vacuously" that every function $f:emptysettoemptyset$ had a fixed point. But in fact there is one function $f:emptysettoemptyset$ and it has no fixed points.
    – bof
    Jul 15 at 11:16














up vote
1
down vote

favorite












$mathbfdef:$ let $A, B$ be sets, and $ f : A times A rightarrow B$ be any
function. A function$ g : A rightarrow B $ is representable by $f$ iff there is $ a in A$ such
that for all $ x in A, g(x) = f(x, a)$.



$mathbfTheorem:$ [Cantor’s Little Theorem] Let $ A, B $ be sets and $f : A × A → B$
be any function such that all functions $g : A → B$ are representable by $f$. Then
every function $φ : B → B$ has a fixed point.



$mathbfproof:$ Suppose that $f : A × A → B$ is such a function that all functions
$g : A → B$ are representable by $f$. Let $φ : B → B$ be any function. Define
a function $ψ : A → A × A$ , called Cantor’s diagonalization, by $ψ(x) = (x, x)$.
Let $h = φ ◦ f ◦ ψ$;Since the function $h : A → B$ is representable by $f$ , we have an $a ∈ A$
such that for all $x ∈ A, h(x) = f(x, a)$. In particular, $h(a) = f(a, a)$. But
$h(a) = φ(f(ψ(a))) = φ(f(a, a))$. Writing $f(a, a) = b$, we have $φ(b) = b$. Thus
$φ$ has a fixed point, namely,$b$.



$mathbfQuestion:$ It says Let $ A, B $ be sets and $f : A × A → B$
be any function such that $mathbfall$ functions $g : A → B$ are representable by $f$.This assumption seems logically wrong to me because the cardinality of the set of all functions from $A$ to $B$ is bigger than the cardinality of $A$,so how can there exists a function $f : A × A → B$
such that $mathbfall$ functions $g : A → B$ are representable by it?In the proof the assumption is applied to the function "h" (defined in the proof ).



link of the paper containing the theorem:https://mat.iitm.ac.in/home/asingh/public_html/papers/cantor.pdf







share|cite|improve this question

















  • 1




    And yet you seem fine with the idea that there are sets $B$ such that any function $Bto B$ has a fixed point? I would find that as counterintuitive, if not more. I can only think of one such set (or two, really, because of vacuous truths), and in that case your problem isn't really a problem.
    – Arthur
    Jul 15 at 10:31











  • It seems to be saying: "if there is such a function f, then ...."
    – Bram28
    Jul 15 at 10:32






  • 1




    @Arthur I can think of lots of sets $B$ such that every function $f:Bto B$ has a fixed point, but they are all isomorphic, they are all one-element sets. I don't believe there are any other examples. Do you have one?
    – bof
    Jul 15 at 10:46






  • 1




    @bumba But the consequence is important. If I said "If pigs can fly, then chickens have teeth", that's a true statement (with current gene editing technology, at least). But your objections here amount to "but pigs can't fly, how can that statement be true?" It is true exactly because the consequence isn't (except for a few trivial cases where the assumption is also true).
    – Arthur
    Jul 15 at 10:54







  • 1




    @Arthur Nope. If there were no functions $f:emptysettoemptyset$ then it would be true "vacuously" that every function $f:emptysettoemptyset$ had a fixed point. But in fact there is one function $f:emptysettoemptyset$ and it has no fixed points.
    – bof
    Jul 15 at 11:16












up vote
1
down vote

favorite









up vote
1
down vote

favorite











$mathbfdef:$ let $A, B$ be sets, and $ f : A times A rightarrow B$ be any
function. A function$ g : A rightarrow B $ is representable by $f$ iff there is $ a in A$ such
that for all $ x in A, g(x) = f(x, a)$.



$mathbfTheorem:$ [Cantor’s Little Theorem] Let $ A, B $ be sets and $f : A × A → B$
be any function such that all functions $g : A → B$ are representable by $f$. Then
every function $φ : B → B$ has a fixed point.



$mathbfproof:$ Suppose that $f : A × A → B$ is such a function that all functions
$g : A → B$ are representable by $f$. Let $φ : B → B$ be any function. Define
a function $ψ : A → A × A$ , called Cantor’s diagonalization, by $ψ(x) = (x, x)$.
Let $h = φ ◦ f ◦ ψ$;Since the function $h : A → B$ is representable by $f$ , we have an $a ∈ A$
such that for all $x ∈ A, h(x) = f(x, a)$. In particular, $h(a) = f(a, a)$. But
$h(a) = φ(f(ψ(a))) = φ(f(a, a))$. Writing $f(a, a) = b$, we have $φ(b) = b$. Thus
$φ$ has a fixed point, namely,$b$.



$mathbfQuestion:$ It says Let $ A, B $ be sets and $f : A × A → B$
be any function such that $mathbfall$ functions $g : A → B$ are representable by $f$.This assumption seems logically wrong to me because the cardinality of the set of all functions from $A$ to $B$ is bigger than the cardinality of $A$,so how can there exists a function $f : A × A → B$
such that $mathbfall$ functions $g : A → B$ are representable by it?In the proof the assumption is applied to the function "h" (defined in the proof ).



link of the paper containing the theorem:https://mat.iitm.ac.in/home/asingh/public_html/papers/cantor.pdf







share|cite|improve this question













$mathbfdef:$ let $A, B$ be sets, and $ f : A times A rightarrow B$ be any
function. A function$ g : A rightarrow B $ is representable by $f$ iff there is $ a in A$ such
that for all $ x in A, g(x) = f(x, a)$.



$mathbfTheorem:$ [Cantor’s Little Theorem] Let $ A, B $ be sets and $f : A × A → B$
be any function such that all functions $g : A → B$ are representable by $f$. Then
every function $φ : B → B$ has a fixed point.



$mathbfproof:$ Suppose that $f : A × A → B$ is such a function that all functions
$g : A → B$ are representable by $f$. Let $φ : B → B$ be any function. Define
a function $ψ : A → A × A$ , called Cantor’s diagonalization, by $ψ(x) = (x, x)$.
Let $h = φ ◦ f ◦ ψ$;Since the function $h : A → B$ is representable by $f$ , we have an $a ∈ A$
such that for all $x ∈ A, h(x) = f(x, a)$. In particular, $h(a) = f(a, a)$. But
$h(a) = φ(f(ψ(a))) = φ(f(a, a))$. Writing $f(a, a) = b$, we have $φ(b) = b$. Thus
$φ$ has a fixed point, namely,$b$.



$mathbfQuestion:$ It says Let $ A, B $ be sets and $f : A × A → B$
be any function such that $mathbfall$ functions $g : A → B$ are representable by $f$.This assumption seems logically wrong to me because the cardinality of the set of all functions from $A$ to $B$ is bigger than the cardinality of $A$,so how can there exists a function $f : A × A → B$
such that $mathbfall$ functions $g : A → B$ are representable by it?In the proof the assumption is applied to the function "h" (defined in the proof ).



link of the paper containing the theorem:https://mat.iitm.ac.in/home/asingh/public_html/papers/cantor.pdf









share|cite|improve this question












share|cite|improve this question




share|cite|improve this question








edited Jul 15 at 11:59
























asked Jul 15 at 10:25









bumba

246




246







  • 1




    And yet you seem fine with the idea that there are sets $B$ such that any function $Bto B$ has a fixed point? I would find that as counterintuitive, if not more. I can only think of one such set (or two, really, because of vacuous truths), and in that case your problem isn't really a problem.
    – Arthur
    Jul 15 at 10:31











  • It seems to be saying: "if there is such a function f, then ...."
    – Bram28
    Jul 15 at 10:32






  • 1




    @Arthur I can think of lots of sets $B$ such that every function $f:Bto B$ has a fixed point, but they are all isomorphic, they are all one-element sets. I don't believe there are any other examples. Do you have one?
    – bof
    Jul 15 at 10:46






  • 1




    @bumba But the consequence is important. If I said "If pigs can fly, then chickens have teeth", that's a true statement (with current gene editing technology, at least). But your objections here amount to "but pigs can't fly, how can that statement be true?" It is true exactly because the consequence isn't (except for a few trivial cases where the assumption is also true).
    – Arthur
    Jul 15 at 10:54







  • 1




    @Arthur Nope. If there were no functions $f:emptysettoemptyset$ then it would be true "vacuously" that every function $f:emptysettoemptyset$ had a fixed point. But in fact there is one function $f:emptysettoemptyset$ and it has no fixed points.
    – bof
    Jul 15 at 11:16












  • 1




    And yet you seem fine with the idea that there are sets $B$ such that any function $Bto B$ has a fixed point? I would find that as counterintuitive, if not more. I can only think of one such set (or two, really, because of vacuous truths), and in that case your problem isn't really a problem.
    – Arthur
    Jul 15 at 10:31











  • It seems to be saying: "if there is such a function f, then ...."
    – Bram28
    Jul 15 at 10:32






  • 1




    @Arthur I can think of lots of sets $B$ such that every function $f:Bto B$ has a fixed point, but they are all isomorphic, they are all one-element sets. I don't believe there are any other examples. Do you have one?
    – bof
    Jul 15 at 10:46






  • 1




    @bumba But the consequence is important. If I said "If pigs can fly, then chickens have teeth", that's a true statement (with current gene editing technology, at least). But your objections here amount to "but pigs can't fly, how can that statement be true?" It is true exactly because the consequence isn't (except for a few trivial cases where the assumption is also true).
    – Arthur
    Jul 15 at 10:54







  • 1




    @Arthur Nope. If there were no functions $f:emptysettoemptyset$ then it would be true "vacuously" that every function $f:emptysettoemptyset$ had a fixed point. But in fact there is one function $f:emptysettoemptyset$ and it has no fixed points.
    – bof
    Jul 15 at 11:16







1




1




And yet you seem fine with the idea that there are sets $B$ such that any function $Bto B$ has a fixed point? I would find that as counterintuitive, if not more. I can only think of one such set (or two, really, because of vacuous truths), and in that case your problem isn't really a problem.
– Arthur
Jul 15 at 10:31





And yet you seem fine with the idea that there are sets $B$ such that any function $Bto B$ has a fixed point? I would find that as counterintuitive, if not more. I can only think of one such set (or two, really, because of vacuous truths), and in that case your problem isn't really a problem.
– Arthur
Jul 15 at 10:31













It seems to be saying: "if there is such a function f, then ...."
– Bram28
Jul 15 at 10:32




It seems to be saying: "if there is such a function f, then ...."
– Bram28
Jul 15 at 10:32




1




1




@Arthur I can think of lots of sets $B$ such that every function $f:Bto B$ has a fixed point, but they are all isomorphic, they are all one-element sets. I don't believe there are any other examples. Do you have one?
– bof
Jul 15 at 10:46




@Arthur I can think of lots of sets $B$ such that every function $f:Bto B$ has a fixed point, but they are all isomorphic, they are all one-element sets. I don't believe there are any other examples. Do you have one?
– bof
Jul 15 at 10:46




1




1




@bumba But the consequence is important. If I said "If pigs can fly, then chickens have teeth", that's a true statement (with current gene editing technology, at least). But your objections here amount to "but pigs can't fly, how can that statement be true?" It is true exactly because the consequence isn't (except for a few trivial cases where the assumption is also true).
– Arthur
Jul 15 at 10:54





@bumba But the consequence is important. If I said "If pigs can fly, then chickens have teeth", that's a true statement (with current gene editing technology, at least). But your objections here amount to "but pigs can't fly, how can that statement be true?" It is true exactly because the consequence isn't (except for a few trivial cases where the assumption is also true).
– Arthur
Jul 15 at 10:54





1




1




@Arthur Nope. If there were no functions $f:emptysettoemptyset$ then it would be true "vacuously" that every function $f:emptysettoemptyset$ had a fixed point. But in fact there is one function $f:emptysettoemptyset$ and it has no fixed points.
– bof
Jul 15 at 11:16




@Arthur Nope. If there were no functions $f:emptysettoemptyset$ then it would be true "vacuously" that every function $f:emptysettoemptyset$ had a fixed point. But in fact there is one function $f:emptysettoemptyset$ and it has no fixed points.
– bof
Jul 15 at 11:16










5 Answers
5






active

oldest

votes

















up vote
3
down vote













Have you seen the classic proof that $sqrt 2$ is irrational? In modern terms, it's really more a proof of a statement like this:




If $a, b$ are integers such that $a^2 = 2b^2$, then for any natural number $n$ we have $2^nmid a, b$.




This is an if-then-formulated theorem. If we stop worrying about circularity here for a moment, note that it is well-known that the assumption, i.e. the existence of such integers $a, b$, is (nearly) impossible. Yet the theorem is true. How could this be?



This is exactly because the conclusion, that $a, b$ are both divisible by any power of $2$, is impossible (unless $a = b = 0$, which is an uninteresting triviality).



In your case, you have the statement (slightly paraphrased to make the if-then structure a bit clearer)




If $ A, B $ be sets and $f : A × A → B$ is a function such that all functions $g : A → B$ are representable by $f$, then every function $φ : B → B$ has a fixed point.




You seem hung up on the fact that the assumption, i.e. the existence of such a function $f$, seems impossible when the fact is that this is (almost) a proof by contradiction, just like the classical proof of the irrationality of $sqrt 2$. That's because the conclusion, that any function $Bto B$ has a fixed point, is impossible (unless $|B|<2$, which is an uninteresting triviality). Your theorem is still true.






share|cite|improve this answer























  • PS. That $|B|<2$ is not really an uninteresting triviality. I just formulated it that way to make the parallel to a result you ought to know well that much clearer.
    – Arthur
    Jul 15 at 11:10










  • I really like better to prove the irratinoality of $sqrt 2$ in terms of parity of $2$-valuations though.
    – Arnaud Mortier
    Jul 15 at 11:19










  • @ArnaudMortier But that's not the classic proof. And it's not so well known that I can rely on it as a reference point.
    – Arthur
    Jul 15 at 11:19











  • @bumba there is no need to read the whole paper, it is very clear. What do you find unclear in our answers?
    – Arnaud Mortier
    Jul 15 at 11:20










  • @bumba Your question, as stated, doesn't require reading the paper at all. You seem to have problems parsing the statement of the theorem and comprehending how it could possibly be true. I have answered that as best I can. If you have a question about the proof or application of the theorem, which would require people to read the paper, then you will have to make a new question post about that.
    – Arthur
    Jul 15 at 11:21


















up vote
1
down vote













Here is another theorem:




Theorem: If $A$ is a nonempty finite set such that there is an injective map $Atimes Ato A$, then every map $Ato A$ has a fixed point.




You would say, but this assumption doesn't make sense, there are no injective maps $Atimes Ato A$ since $Atimes A$ is bigger than $A$. And you would be almost right: $Atimes A$ is bigger than $A$ except in very exceptional cases, and this theorem is precisely telling you which are these exceptional cases.






share|cite|improve this answer






























    up vote
    0
    down vote













    Your mistake is thinking that the cardinality of the set $B^A$ of all functions from $A$ to $B$ must be bigger than the cardinality of $A$.



    For example, if $A$ is non empty and $B$ is empty, then there is no function from $A$ to $B$, so the cardinality of $B^A$ is $0$, which is less than the cardinality of $A$.



    Also, if $A$ has at least two elements and $B$ has a single element $b$, then there is a unique function $f colon A to B$ (mapping all elements of $A$ to $b$), and so the cardinality of $B^A$ is $1$, which is less than the cardinality of $A$.






    share|cite|improve this answer





















    • in the proof the assumption is applied to the function "h" (defined in the proof ) which is not one of your trivial type
      – bumba
      Jul 15 at 11:56










    • What makes you think that it's not a "trivial" function as you call it?
      – Luca Bressan
      Jul 15 at 12:01










    • sorry it seems that i am wrong
      – bumba
      Jul 15 at 12:33

















    up vote
    0
    down vote













    First of all it is my personal opinion that a false hypothesis does not have to be a "wrong hypothesis", for me a wrong hypothesis is one that does not allow you to conclude your thesis.



    With that said, as others have already noted the hypothesis




    all functions $g colon A to B$ are represented by $f$




    is not at all logically false, indeed it is verified whenever $B$ has only one element, and that is also the only case of course, since for every $B$ with al least two elements you can find a function with no fixed point (hence violating the thesis of Cantor's Little theorem).



    So this theorem may seem pretty useless since it applies to so few families of sets, nevertheless if you replace sets and functions with objects and morphisms of a cartesian closed category the same proof provides you with a criterion for fixed points.



    This can applied to the category of dcpos and continuous functions between them, in this way you get Kleene fixed point theorem.



    There are other applications of this theorem in [this paper] from Lawvere who I believe was the first person to notice the importance of this theorem for cartesian closed categories.



    I hope this helps.






    share|cite|improve this answer




























      up vote
      0
      down vote













      If $B$ is empty, then there is a unique function $phi : B to B$ and it has no fixed point. If $B$ has $1$ element, then there is a unique function $phi: B to B$ and it has a fixed point. If $B$ has $2$ elements (or more), then Cantor's theorem as it is usually stated tells us that for any set $A$, there is no surjective function from $A$ to the set of functions $A to B$ and hence no function $A times A to B$ that represents every function from $A$ to $B$ in the sense of your question. Hence the hypothesis of your "Theorem" is false if $B$ has more than $1$ element.



      So your statement is correct for non-empty sets $A$ and $B$ and is very closely related to Cantor's theorem as normally stated but it is extremely misleading: the existence of a fixed point for every function $phi : B to B$ just means that $B$ has exactly one $1$ element.






      share|cite|improve this answer



















      • 1




        If $B$ is empty, then not every function $Bto B$ has a fixed point -- indeed, the empty function does not.
        – Henning Makholm
        Jul 15 at 22:34










      • @HenningMakholm: thanks for picking up my error, which I believe I have now fixed.
        – Rob Arthan
        Jul 17 at 23:16










      Your Answer




      StackExchange.ifUsing("editor", function ()
      return StackExchange.using("mathjaxEditing", function ()
      StackExchange.MarkdownEditor.creationCallbacks.add(function (editor, postfix)
      StackExchange.mathjaxEditing.prepareWmdForMathJax(editor, postfix, [["$", "$"], ["\\(","\\)"]]);
      );
      );
      , "mathjax-editing");

      StackExchange.ready(function()
      var channelOptions =
      tags: "".split(" "),
      id: "69"
      ;
      initTagRenderer("".split(" "), "".split(" "), channelOptions);

      StackExchange.using("externalEditor", function()
      // Have to fire editor after snippets, if snippets enabled
      if (StackExchange.settings.snippets.snippetsEnabled)
      StackExchange.using("snippets", function()
      createEditor();
      );

      else
      createEditor();

      );

      function createEditor()
      StackExchange.prepareEditor(
      heartbeatType: 'answer',
      convertImagesToLinks: true,
      noModals: false,
      showLowRepImageUploadWarning: true,
      reputationToPostImages: 10,
      bindNavPrevention: true,
      postfix: "",
      noCode: true, onDemand: true,
      discardSelector: ".discard-answer"
      ,immediatelyShowMarkdownHelp:true
      );



      );








       

      draft saved


      draft discarded


















      StackExchange.ready(
      function ()
      StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmath.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f2852366%2flet-a-and-b-be-arbitrary-sets-is-there-a-function-fa-times-a-to-b%23new-answer', 'question_page');

      );

      Post as a guest






























      5 Answers
      5






      active

      oldest

      votes








      5 Answers
      5






      active

      oldest

      votes









      active

      oldest

      votes






      active

      oldest

      votes








      up vote
      3
      down vote













      Have you seen the classic proof that $sqrt 2$ is irrational? In modern terms, it's really more a proof of a statement like this:




      If $a, b$ are integers such that $a^2 = 2b^2$, then for any natural number $n$ we have $2^nmid a, b$.




      This is an if-then-formulated theorem. If we stop worrying about circularity here for a moment, note that it is well-known that the assumption, i.e. the existence of such integers $a, b$, is (nearly) impossible. Yet the theorem is true. How could this be?



      This is exactly because the conclusion, that $a, b$ are both divisible by any power of $2$, is impossible (unless $a = b = 0$, which is an uninteresting triviality).



      In your case, you have the statement (slightly paraphrased to make the if-then structure a bit clearer)




      If $ A, B $ be sets and $f : A × A → B$ is a function such that all functions $g : A → B$ are representable by $f$, then every function $φ : B → B$ has a fixed point.




      You seem hung up on the fact that the assumption, i.e. the existence of such a function $f$, seems impossible when the fact is that this is (almost) a proof by contradiction, just like the classical proof of the irrationality of $sqrt 2$. That's because the conclusion, that any function $Bto B$ has a fixed point, is impossible (unless $|B|<2$, which is an uninteresting triviality). Your theorem is still true.






      share|cite|improve this answer























      • PS. That $|B|<2$ is not really an uninteresting triviality. I just formulated it that way to make the parallel to a result you ought to know well that much clearer.
        – Arthur
        Jul 15 at 11:10










      • I really like better to prove the irratinoality of $sqrt 2$ in terms of parity of $2$-valuations though.
        – Arnaud Mortier
        Jul 15 at 11:19










      • @ArnaudMortier But that's not the classic proof. And it's not so well known that I can rely on it as a reference point.
        – Arthur
        Jul 15 at 11:19











      • @bumba there is no need to read the whole paper, it is very clear. What do you find unclear in our answers?
        – Arnaud Mortier
        Jul 15 at 11:20










      • @bumba Your question, as stated, doesn't require reading the paper at all. You seem to have problems parsing the statement of the theorem and comprehending how it could possibly be true. I have answered that as best I can. If you have a question about the proof or application of the theorem, which would require people to read the paper, then you will have to make a new question post about that.
        – Arthur
        Jul 15 at 11:21















      up vote
      3
      down vote













      Have you seen the classic proof that $sqrt 2$ is irrational? In modern terms, it's really more a proof of a statement like this:




      If $a, b$ are integers such that $a^2 = 2b^2$, then for any natural number $n$ we have $2^nmid a, b$.




      This is an if-then-formulated theorem. If we stop worrying about circularity here for a moment, note that it is well-known that the assumption, i.e. the existence of such integers $a, b$, is (nearly) impossible. Yet the theorem is true. How could this be?



      This is exactly because the conclusion, that $a, b$ are both divisible by any power of $2$, is impossible (unless $a = b = 0$, which is an uninteresting triviality).



      In your case, you have the statement (slightly paraphrased to make the if-then structure a bit clearer)




      If $ A, B $ be sets and $f : A × A → B$ is a function such that all functions $g : A → B$ are representable by $f$, then every function $φ : B → B$ has a fixed point.




      You seem hung up on the fact that the assumption, i.e. the existence of such a function $f$, seems impossible when the fact is that this is (almost) a proof by contradiction, just like the classical proof of the irrationality of $sqrt 2$. That's because the conclusion, that any function $Bto B$ has a fixed point, is impossible (unless $|B|<2$, which is an uninteresting triviality). Your theorem is still true.






      share|cite|improve this answer























      • PS. That $|B|<2$ is not really an uninteresting triviality. I just formulated it that way to make the parallel to a result you ought to know well that much clearer.
        – Arthur
        Jul 15 at 11:10










      • I really like better to prove the irratinoality of $sqrt 2$ in terms of parity of $2$-valuations though.
        – Arnaud Mortier
        Jul 15 at 11:19










      • @ArnaudMortier But that's not the classic proof. And it's not so well known that I can rely on it as a reference point.
        – Arthur
        Jul 15 at 11:19











      • @bumba there is no need to read the whole paper, it is very clear. What do you find unclear in our answers?
        – Arnaud Mortier
        Jul 15 at 11:20










      • @bumba Your question, as stated, doesn't require reading the paper at all. You seem to have problems parsing the statement of the theorem and comprehending how it could possibly be true. I have answered that as best I can. If you have a question about the proof or application of the theorem, which would require people to read the paper, then you will have to make a new question post about that.
        – Arthur
        Jul 15 at 11:21













      up vote
      3
      down vote










      up vote
      3
      down vote









      Have you seen the classic proof that $sqrt 2$ is irrational? In modern terms, it's really more a proof of a statement like this:




      If $a, b$ are integers such that $a^2 = 2b^2$, then for any natural number $n$ we have $2^nmid a, b$.




      This is an if-then-formulated theorem. If we stop worrying about circularity here for a moment, note that it is well-known that the assumption, i.e. the existence of such integers $a, b$, is (nearly) impossible. Yet the theorem is true. How could this be?



      This is exactly because the conclusion, that $a, b$ are both divisible by any power of $2$, is impossible (unless $a = b = 0$, which is an uninteresting triviality).



      In your case, you have the statement (slightly paraphrased to make the if-then structure a bit clearer)




      If $ A, B $ be sets and $f : A × A → B$ is a function such that all functions $g : A → B$ are representable by $f$, then every function $φ : B → B$ has a fixed point.




      You seem hung up on the fact that the assumption, i.e. the existence of such a function $f$, seems impossible when the fact is that this is (almost) a proof by contradiction, just like the classical proof of the irrationality of $sqrt 2$. That's because the conclusion, that any function $Bto B$ has a fixed point, is impossible (unless $|B|<2$, which is an uninteresting triviality). Your theorem is still true.






      share|cite|improve this answer















      Have you seen the classic proof that $sqrt 2$ is irrational? In modern terms, it's really more a proof of a statement like this:




      If $a, b$ are integers such that $a^2 = 2b^2$, then for any natural number $n$ we have $2^nmid a, b$.




      This is an if-then-formulated theorem. If we stop worrying about circularity here for a moment, note that it is well-known that the assumption, i.e. the existence of such integers $a, b$, is (nearly) impossible. Yet the theorem is true. How could this be?



      This is exactly because the conclusion, that $a, b$ are both divisible by any power of $2$, is impossible (unless $a = b = 0$, which is an uninteresting triviality).



      In your case, you have the statement (slightly paraphrased to make the if-then structure a bit clearer)




      If $ A, B $ be sets and $f : A × A → B$ is a function such that all functions $g : A → B$ are representable by $f$, then every function $φ : B → B$ has a fixed point.




      You seem hung up on the fact that the assumption, i.e. the existence of such a function $f$, seems impossible when the fact is that this is (almost) a proof by contradiction, just like the classical proof of the irrationality of $sqrt 2$. That's because the conclusion, that any function $Bto B$ has a fixed point, is impossible (unless $|B|<2$, which is an uninteresting triviality). Your theorem is still true.







      share|cite|improve this answer















      share|cite|improve this answer



      share|cite|improve this answer








      edited Jul 15 at 11:14


























      answered Jul 15 at 11:09









      Arthur

      99k793175




      99k793175











      • PS. That $|B|<2$ is not really an uninteresting triviality. I just formulated it that way to make the parallel to a result you ought to know well that much clearer.
        – Arthur
        Jul 15 at 11:10










      • I really like better to prove the irratinoality of $sqrt 2$ in terms of parity of $2$-valuations though.
        – Arnaud Mortier
        Jul 15 at 11:19










      • @ArnaudMortier But that's not the classic proof. And it's not so well known that I can rely on it as a reference point.
        – Arthur
        Jul 15 at 11:19











      • @bumba there is no need to read the whole paper, it is very clear. What do you find unclear in our answers?
        – Arnaud Mortier
        Jul 15 at 11:20










      • @bumba Your question, as stated, doesn't require reading the paper at all. You seem to have problems parsing the statement of the theorem and comprehending how it could possibly be true. I have answered that as best I can. If you have a question about the proof or application of the theorem, which would require people to read the paper, then you will have to make a new question post about that.
        – Arthur
        Jul 15 at 11:21

















      • PS. That $|B|<2$ is not really an uninteresting triviality. I just formulated it that way to make the parallel to a result you ought to know well that much clearer.
        – Arthur
        Jul 15 at 11:10










      • I really like better to prove the irratinoality of $sqrt 2$ in terms of parity of $2$-valuations though.
        – Arnaud Mortier
        Jul 15 at 11:19










      • @ArnaudMortier But that's not the classic proof. And it's not so well known that I can rely on it as a reference point.
        – Arthur
        Jul 15 at 11:19











      • @bumba there is no need to read the whole paper, it is very clear. What do you find unclear in our answers?
        – Arnaud Mortier
        Jul 15 at 11:20










      • @bumba Your question, as stated, doesn't require reading the paper at all. You seem to have problems parsing the statement of the theorem and comprehending how it could possibly be true. I have answered that as best I can. If you have a question about the proof or application of the theorem, which would require people to read the paper, then you will have to make a new question post about that.
        – Arthur
        Jul 15 at 11:21
















      PS. That $|B|<2$ is not really an uninteresting triviality. I just formulated it that way to make the parallel to a result you ought to know well that much clearer.
      – Arthur
      Jul 15 at 11:10




      PS. That $|B|<2$ is not really an uninteresting triviality. I just formulated it that way to make the parallel to a result you ought to know well that much clearer.
      – Arthur
      Jul 15 at 11:10












      I really like better to prove the irratinoality of $sqrt 2$ in terms of parity of $2$-valuations though.
      – Arnaud Mortier
      Jul 15 at 11:19




      I really like better to prove the irratinoality of $sqrt 2$ in terms of parity of $2$-valuations though.
      – Arnaud Mortier
      Jul 15 at 11:19












      @ArnaudMortier But that's not the classic proof. And it's not so well known that I can rely on it as a reference point.
      – Arthur
      Jul 15 at 11:19





      @ArnaudMortier But that's not the classic proof. And it's not so well known that I can rely on it as a reference point.
      – Arthur
      Jul 15 at 11:19













      @bumba there is no need to read the whole paper, it is very clear. What do you find unclear in our answers?
      – Arnaud Mortier
      Jul 15 at 11:20




      @bumba there is no need to read the whole paper, it is very clear. What do you find unclear in our answers?
      – Arnaud Mortier
      Jul 15 at 11:20












      @bumba Your question, as stated, doesn't require reading the paper at all. You seem to have problems parsing the statement of the theorem and comprehending how it could possibly be true. I have answered that as best I can. If you have a question about the proof or application of the theorem, which would require people to read the paper, then you will have to make a new question post about that.
      – Arthur
      Jul 15 at 11:21





      @bumba Your question, as stated, doesn't require reading the paper at all. You seem to have problems parsing the statement of the theorem and comprehending how it could possibly be true. I have answered that as best I can. If you have a question about the proof or application of the theorem, which would require people to read the paper, then you will have to make a new question post about that.
      – Arthur
      Jul 15 at 11:21











      up vote
      1
      down vote













      Here is another theorem:




      Theorem: If $A$ is a nonempty finite set such that there is an injective map $Atimes Ato A$, then every map $Ato A$ has a fixed point.




      You would say, but this assumption doesn't make sense, there are no injective maps $Atimes Ato A$ since $Atimes A$ is bigger than $A$. And you would be almost right: $Atimes A$ is bigger than $A$ except in very exceptional cases, and this theorem is precisely telling you which are these exceptional cases.






      share|cite|improve this answer



























        up vote
        1
        down vote













        Here is another theorem:




        Theorem: If $A$ is a nonempty finite set such that there is an injective map $Atimes Ato A$, then every map $Ato A$ has a fixed point.




        You would say, but this assumption doesn't make sense, there are no injective maps $Atimes Ato A$ since $Atimes A$ is bigger than $A$. And you would be almost right: $Atimes A$ is bigger than $A$ except in very exceptional cases, and this theorem is precisely telling you which are these exceptional cases.






        share|cite|improve this answer

























          up vote
          1
          down vote










          up vote
          1
          down vote









          Here is another theorem:




          Theorem: If $A$ is a nonempty finite set such that there is an injective map $Atimes Ato A$, then every map $Ato A$ has a fixed point.




          You would say, but this assumption doesn't make sense, there are no injective maps $Atimes Ato A$ since $Atimes A$ is bigger than $A$. And you would be almost right: $Atimes A$ is bigger than $A$ except in very exceptional cases, and this theorem is precisely telling you which are these exceptional cases.






          share|cite|improve this answer















          Here is another theorem:




          Theorem: If $A$ is a nonempty finite set such that there is an injective map $Atimes Ato A$, then every map $Ato A$ has a fixed point.




          You would say, but this assumption doesn't make sense, there are no injective maps $Atimes Ato A$ since $Atimes A$ is bigger than $A$. And you would be almost right: $Atimes A$ is bigger than $A$ except in very exceptional cases, and this theorem is precisely telling you which are these exceptional cases.







          share|cite|improve this answer















          share|cite|improve this answer



          share|cite|improve this answer








          edited Jul 15 at 11:35


























          answered Jul 15 at 11:11









          Arnaud Mortier

          19.2k22159




          19.2k22159




















              up vote
              0
              down vote













              Your mistake is thinking that the cardinality of the set $B^A$ of all functions from $A$ to $B$ must be bigger than the cardinality of $A$.



              For example, if $A$ is non empty and $B$ is empty, then there is no function from $A$ to $B$, so the cardinality of $B^A$ is $0$, which is less than the cardinality of $A$.



              Also, if $A$ has at least two elements and $B$ has a single element $b$, then there is a unique function $f colon A to B$ (mapping all elements of $A$ to $b$), and so the cardinality of $B^A$ is $1$, which is less than the cardinality of $A$.






              share|cite|improve this answer





















              • in the proof the assumption is applied to the function "h" (defined in the proof ) which is not one of your trivial type
                – bumba
                Jul 15 at 11:56










              • What makes you think that it's not a "trivial" function as you call it?
                – Luca Bressan
                Jul 15 at 12:01










              • sorry it seems that i am wrong
                – bumba
                Jul 15 at 12:33














              up vote
              0
              down vote













              Your mistake is thinking that the cardinality of the set $B^A$ of all functions from $A$ to $B$ must be bigger than the cardinality of $A$.



              For example, if $A$ is non empty and $B$ is empty, then there is no function from $A$ to $B$, so the cardinality of $B^A$ is $0$, which is less than the cardinality of $A$.



              Also, if $A$ has at least two elements and $B$ has a single element $b$, then there is a unique function $f colon A to B$ (mapping all elements of $A$ to $b$), and so the cardinality of $B^A$ is $1$, which is less than the cardinality of $A$.






              share|cite|improve this answer





















              • in the proof the assumption is applied to the function "h" (defined in the proof ) which is not one of your trivial type
                – bumba
                Jul 15 at 11:56










              • What makes you think that it's not a "trivial" function as you call it?
                – Luca Bressan
                Jul 15 at 12:01










              • sorry it seems that i am wrong
                – bumba
                Jul 15 at 12:33












              up vote
              0
              down vote










              up vote
              0
              down vote









              Your mistake is thinking that the cardinality of the set $B^A$ of all functions from $A$ to $B$ must be bigger than the cardinality of $A$.



              For example, if $A$ is non empty and $B$ is empty, then there is no function from $A$ to $B$, so the cardinality of $B^A$ is $0$, which is less than the cardinality of $A$.



              Also, if $A$ has at least two elements and $B$ has a single element $b$, then there is a unique function $f colon A to B$ (mapping all elements of $A$ to $b$), and so the cardinality of $B^A$ is $1$, which is less than the cardinality of $A$.






              share|cite|improve this answer













              Your mistake is thinking that the cardinality of the set $B^A$ of all functions from $A$ to $B$ must be bigger than the cardinality of $A$.



              For example, if $A$ is non empty and $B$ is empty, then there is no function from $A$ to $B$, so the cardinality of $B^A$ is $0$, which is less than the cardinality of $A$.



              Also, if $A$ has at least two elements and $B$ has a single element $b$, then there is a unique function $f colon A to B$ (mapping all elements of $A$ to $b$), and so the cardinality of $B^A$ is $1$, which is less than the cardinality of $A$.







              share|cite|improve this answer













              share|cite|improve this answer



              share|cite|improve this answer











              answered Jul 15 at 11:07









              Luca Bressan

              3,86621036




              3,86621036











              • in the proof the assumption is applied to the function "h" (defined in the proof ) which is not one of your trivial type
                – bumba
                Jul 15 at 11:56










              • What makes you think that it's not a "trivial" function as you call it?
                – Luca Bressan
                Jul 15 at 12:01










              • sorry it seems that i am wrong
                – bumba
                Jul 15 at 12:33
















              • in the proof the assumption is applied to the function "h" (defined in the proof ) which is not one of your trivial type
                – bumba
                Jul 15 at 11:56










              • What makes you think that it's not a "trivial" function as you call it?
                – Luca Bressan
                Jul 15 at 12:01










              • sorry it seems that i am wrong
                – bumba
                Jul 15 at 12:33















              in the proof the assumption is applied to the function "h" (defined in the proof ) which is not one of your trivial type
              – bumba
              Jul 15 at 11:56




              in the proof the assumption is applied to the function "h" (defined in the proof ) which is not one of your trivial type
              – bumba
              Jul 15 at 11:56












              What makes you think that it's not a "trivial" function as you call it?
              – Luca Bressan
              Jul 15 at 12:01




              What makes you think that it's not a "trivial" function as you call it?
              – Luca Bressan
              Jul 15 at 12:01












              sorry it seems that i am wrong
              – bumba
              Jul 15 at 12:33




              sorry it seems that i am wrong
              – bumba
              Jul 15 at 12:33










              up vote
              0
              down vote













              First of all it is my personal opinion that a false hypothesis does not have to be a "wrong hypothesis", for me a wrong hypothesis is one that does not allow you to conclude your thesis.



              With that said, as others have already noted the hypothesis




              all functions $g colon A to B$ are represented by $f$




              is not at all logically false, indeed it is verified whenever $B$ has only one element, and that is also the only case of course, since for every $B$ with al least two elements you can find a function with no fixed point (hence violating the thesis of Cantor's Little theorem).



              So this theorem may seem pretty useless since it applies to so few families of sets, nevertheless if you replace sets and functions with objects and morphisms of a cartesian closed category the same proof provides you with a criterion for fixed points.



              This can applied to the category of dcpos and continuous functions between them, in this way you get Kleene fixed point theorem.



              There are other applications of this theorem in [this paper] from Lawvere who I believe was the first person to notice the importance of this theorem for cartesian closed categories.



              I hope this helps.






              share|cite|improve this answer

























                up vote
                0
                down vote













                First of all it is my personal opinion that a false hypothesis does not have to be a "wrong hypothesis", for me a wrong hypothesis is one that does not allow you to conclude your thesis.



                With that said, as others have already noted the hypothesis




                all functions $g colon A to B$ are represented by $f$




                is not at all logically false, indeed it is verified whenever $B$ has only one element, and that is also the only case of course, since for every $B$ with al least two elements you can find a function with no fixed point (hence violating the thesis of Cantor's Little theorem).



                So this theorem may seem pretty useless since it applies to so few families of sets, nevertheless if you replace sets and functions with objects and morphisms of a cartesian closed category the same proof provides you with a criterion for fixed points.



                This can applied to the category of dcpos and continuous functions between them, in this way you get Kleene fixed point theorem.



                There are other applications of this theorem in [this paper] from Lawvere who I believe was the first person to notice the importance of this theorem for cartesian closed categories.



                I hope this helps.






                share|cite|improve this answer























                  up vote
                  0
                  down vote










                  up vote
                  0
                  down vote









                  First of all it is my personal opinion that a false hypothesis does not have to be a "wrong hypothesis", for me a wrong hypothesis is one that does not allow you to conclude your thesis.



                  With that said, as others have already noted the hypothesis




                  all functions $g colon A to B$ are represented by $f$




                  is not at all logically false, indeed it is verified whenever $B$ has only one element, and that is also the only case of course, since for every $B$ with al least two elements you can find a function with no fixed point (hence violating the thesis of Cantor's Little theorem).



                  So this theorem may seem pretty useless since it applies to so few families of sets, nevertheless if you replace sets and functions with objects and morphisms of a cartesian closed category the same proof provides you with a criterion for fixed points.



                  This can applied to the category of dcpos and continuous functions between them, in this way you get Kleene fixed point theorem.



                  There are other applications of this theorem in [this paper] from Lawvere who I believe was the first person to notice the importance of this theorem for cartesian closed categories.



                  I hope this helps.






                  share|cite|improve this answer













                  First of all it is my personal opinion that a false hypothesis does not have to be a "wrong hypothesis", for me a wrong hypothesis is one that does not allow you to conclude your thesis.



                  With that said, as others have already noted the hypothesis




                  all functions $g colon A to B$ are represented by $f$




                  is not at all logically false, indeed it is verified whenever $B$ has only one element, and that is also the only case of course, since for every $B$ with al least two elements you can find a function with no fixed point (hence violating the thesis of Cantor's Little theorem).



                  So this theorem may seem pretty useless since it applies to so few families of sets, nevertheless if you replace sets and functions with objects and morphisms of a cartesian closed category the same proof provides you with a criterion for fixed points.



                  This can applied to the category of dcpos and continuous functions between them, in this way you get Kleene fixed point theorem.



                  There are other applications of this theorem in [this paper] from Lawvere who I believe was the first person to notice the importance of this theorem for cartesian closed categories.



                  I hope this helps.







                  share|cite|improve this answer













                  share|cite|improve this answer



                  share|cite|improve this answer











                  answered Jul 16 at 9:59









                  Giorgio Mossa

                  13.3k11748




                  13.3k11748




















                      up vote
                      0
                      down vote













                      If $B$ is empty, then there is a unique function $phi : B to B$ and it has no fixed point. If $B$ has $1$ element, then there is a unique function $phi: B to B$ and it has a fixed point. If $B$ has $2$ elements (or more), then Cantor's theorem as it is usually stated tells us that for any set $A$, there is no surjective function from $A$ to the set of functions $A to B$ and hence no function $A times A to B$ that represents every function from $A$ to $B$ in the sense of your question. Hence the hypothesis of your "Theorem" is false if $B$ has more than $1$ element.



                      So your statement is correct for non-empty sets $A$ and $B$ and is very closely related to Cantor's theorem as normally stated but it is extremely misleading: the existence of a fixed point for every function $phi : B to B$ just means that $B$ has exactly one $1$ element.






                      share|cite|improve this answer



















                      • 1




                        If $B$ is empty, then not every function $Bto B$ has a fixed point -- indeed, the empty function does not.
                        – Henning Makholm
                        Jul 15 at 22:34










                      • @HenningMakholm: thanks for picking up my error, which I believe I have now fixed.
                        – Rob Arthan
                        Jul 17 at 23:16














                      up vote
                      0
                      down vote













                      If $B$ is empty, then there is a unique function $phi : B to B$ and it has no fixed point. If $B$ has $1$ element, then there is a unique function $phi: B to B$ and it has a fixed point. If $B$ has $2$ elements (or more), then Cantor's theorem as it is usually stated tells us that for any set $A$, there is no surjective function from $A$ to the set of functions $A to B$ and hence no function $A times A to B$ that represents every function from $A$ to $B$ in the sense of your question. Hence the hypothesis of your "Theorem" is false if $B$ has more than $1$ element.



                      So your statement is correct for non-empty sets $A$ and $B$ and is very closely related to Cantor's theorem as normally stated but it is extremely misleading: the existence of a fixed point for every function $phi : B to B$ just means that $B$ has exactly one $1$ element.






                      share|cite|improve this answer



















                      • 1




                        If $B$ is empty, then not every function $Bto B$ has a fixed point -- indeed, the empty function does not.
                        – Henning Makholm
                        Jul 15 at 22:34










                      • @HenningMakholm: thanks for picking up my error, which I believe I have now fixed.
                        – Rob Arthan
                        Jul 17 at 23:16












                      up vote
                      0
                      down vote










                      up vote
                      0
                      down vote









                      If $B$ is empty, then there is a unique function $phi : B to B$ and it has no fixed point. If $B$ has $1$ element, then there is a unique function $phi: B to B$ and it has a fixed point. If $B$ has $2$ elements (or more), then Cantor's theorem as it is usually stated tells us that for any set $A$, there is no surjective function from $A$ to the set of functions $A to B$ and hence no function $A times A to B$ that represents every function from $A$ to $B$ in the sense of your question. Hence the hypothesis of your "Theorem" is false if $B$ has more than $1$ element.



                      So your statement is correct for non-empty sets $A$ and $B$ and is very closely related to Cantor's theorem as normally stated but it is extremely misleading: the existence of a fixed point for every function $phi : B to B$ just means that $B$ has exactly one $1$ element.






                      share|cite|improve this answer















                      If $B$ is empty, then there is a unique function $phi : B to B$ and it has no fixed point. If $B$ has $1$ element, then there is a unique function $phi: B to B$ and it has a fixed point. If $B$ has $2$ elements (or more), then Cantor's theorem as it is usually stated tells us that for any set $A$, there is no surjective function from $A$ to the set of functions $A to B$ and hence no function $A times A to B$ that represents every function from $A$ to $B$ in the sense of your question. Hence the hypothesis of your "Theorem" is false if $B$ has more than $1$ element.



                      So your statement is correct for non-empty sets $A$ and $B$ and is very closely related to Cantor's theorem as normally stated but it is extremely misleading: the existence of a fixed point for every function $phi : B to B$ just means that $B$ has exactly one $1$ element.







                      share|cite|improve this answer















                      share|cite|improve this answer



                      share|cite|improve this answer








                      edited Jul 17 at 23:28


























                      answered Jul 15 at 21:44









                      Rob Arthan

                      27.1k42863




                      27.1k42863







                      • 1




                        If $B$ is empty, then not every function $Bto B$ has a fixed point -- indeed, the empty function does not.
                        – Henning Makholm
                        Jul 15 at 22:34










                      • @HenningMakholm: thanks for picking up my error, which I believe I have now fixed.
                        – Rob Arthan
                        Jul 17 at 23:16












                      • 1




                        If $B$ is empty, then not every function $Bto B$ has a fixed point -- indeed, the empty function does not.
                        – Henning Makholm
                        Jul 15 at 22:34










                      • @HenningMakholm: thanks for picking up my error, which I believe I have now fixed.
                        – Rob Arthan
                        Jul 17 at 23:16







                      1




                      1




                      If $B$ is empty, then not every function $Bto B$ has a fixed point -- indeed, the empty function does not.
                      – Henning Makholm
                      Jul 15 at 22:34




                      If $B$ is empty, then not every function $Bto B$ has a fixed point -- indeed, the empty function does not.
                      – Henning Makholm
                      Jul 15 at 22:34












                      @HenningMakholm: thanks for picking up my error, which I believe I have now fixed.
                      – Rob Arthan
                      Jul 17 at 23:16




                      @HenningMakholm: thanks for picking up my error, which I believe I have now fixed.
                      – Rob Arthan
                      Jul 17 at 23:16












                       

                      draft saved


                      draft discarded


























                       


                      draft saved


                      draft discarded














                      StackExchange.ready(
                      function ()
                      StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmath.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f2852366%2flet-a-and-b-be-arbitrary-sets-is-there-a-function-fa-times-a-to-b%23new-answer', 'question_page');

                      );

                      Post as a guest













































































                      Comments

                      Popular posts from this blog

                      What is the equation of a 3D cone with generalised tilt?

                      Color the edges and diagonals of a regular polygon

                      Relationship between determinant of matrix and determinant of adjoint?