is first-order logic with constants equally expressive as first-order logic without constants?

The name of the pictureThe name of the pictureThe name of the pictureClash Royale CLAN TAG#URR8PPP











up vote
4
down vote

favorite












I define a logic as a set of formulas $mathcalL$ (formulated in some given signature) with a consequence relation $vDash$. Say a logic $L_1$ is at least as expressive as $L_2$ if there is a conservative translation from $L_1$ to $L_2$, i.e.~there is $t: mathcalL_1rightarrowmathcalL_2$ such that $GammavDash_1varphi$ iff $t(Gamma)vDash_2t(varphi)$. Consider $mathcalL_con$, the language of first-order logic with denumerably many constants, and $mathcalL$, the language of first-order logic with no constants. I suspect that these two languages are equally expressive. In particular, we can translate any formula with constants in $mathcalL_con$ to a formula with only variables in $mathcalL$, with the restriction that different constants are mapped to different variables. So for instance, $F(c_1,c_2)mapsto F(x_1,x_2)$. Is this right?



I guess a more fundamental question is that I do not have a firm grasp of how to prove properties of translations. I suppose that, given the soundness and completeness of first-order logic, one could induct on the complexity of proofs. But this seems rather tedious and does not extend to logics that are known to be incomplete. Is there a canonical way of proving equal expressiveness (or equivalently, the existence of a conservative translation) between any two logics?







share|cite|improve this question

























    up vote
    4
    down vote

    favorite












    I define a logic as a set of formulas $mathcalL$ (formulated in some given signature) with a consequence relation $vDash$. Say a logic $L_1$ is at least as expressive as $L_2$ if there is a conservative translation from $L_1$ to $L_2$, i.e.~there is $t: mathcalL_1rightarrowmathcalL_2$ such that $GammavDash_1varphi$ iff $t(Gamma)vDash_2t(varphi)$. Consider $mathcalL_con$, the language of first-order logic with denumerably many constants, and $mathcalL$, the language of first-order logic with no constants. I suspect that these two languages are equally expressive. In particular, we can translate any formula with constants in $mathcalL_con$ to a formula with only variables in $mathcalL$, with the restriction that different constants are mapped to different variables. So for instance, $F(c_1,c_2)mapsto F(x_1,x_2)$. Is this right?



    I guess a more fundamental question is that I do not have a firm grasp of how to prove properties of translations. I suppose that, given the soundness and completeness of first-order logic, one could induct on the complexity of proofs. But this seems rather tedious and does not extend to logics that are known to be incomplete. Is there a canonical way of proving equal expressiveness (or equivalently, the existence of a conservative translation) between any two logics?







    share|cite|improve this question























      up vote
      4
      down vote

      favorite









      up vote
      4
      down vote

      favorite











      I define a logic as a set of formulas $mathcalL$ (formulated in some given signature) with a consequence relation $vDash$. Say a logic $L_1$ is at least as expressive as $L_2$ if there is a conservative translation from $L_1$ to $L_2$, i.e.~there is $t: mathcalL_1rightarrowmathcalL_2$ such that $GammavDash_1varphi$ iff $t(Gamma)vDash_2t(varphi)$. Consider $mathcalL_con$, the language of first-order logic with denumerably many constants, and $mathcalL$, the language of first-order logic with no constants. I suspect that these two languages are equally expressive. In particular, we can translate any formula with constants in $mathcalL_con$ to a formula with only variables in $mathcalL$, with the restriction that different constants are mapped to different variables. So for instance, $F(c_1,c_2)mapsto F(x_1,x_2)$. Is this right?



      I guess a more fundamental question is that I do not have a firm grasp of how to prove properties of translations. I suppose that, given the soundness and completeness of first-order logic, one could induct on the complexity of proofs. But this seems rather tedious and does not extend to logics that are known to be incomplete. Is there a canonical way of proving equal expressiveness (or equivalently, the existence of a conservative translation) between any two logics?







      share|cite|improve this question













      I define a logic as a set of formulas $mathcalL$ (formulated in some given signature) with a consequence relation $vDash$. Say a logic $L_1$ is at least as expressive as $L_2$ if there is a conservative translation from $L_1$ to $L_2$, i.e.~there is $t: mathcalL_1rightarrowmathcalL_2$ such that $GammavDash_1varphi$ iff $t(Gamma)vDash_2t(varphi)$. Consider $mathcalL_con$, the language of first-order logic with denumerably many constants, and $mathcalL$, the language of first-order logic with no constants. I suspect that these two languages are equally expressive. In particular, we can translate any formula with constants in $mathcalL_con$ to a formula with only variables in $mathcalL$, with the restriction that different constants are mapped to different variables. So for instance, $F(c_1,c_2)mapsto F(x_1,x_2)$. Is this right?



      I guess a more fundamental question is that I do not have a firm grasp of how to prove properties of translations. I suppose that, given the soundness and completeness of first-order logic, one could induct on the complexity of proofs. But this seems rather tedious and does not extend to logics that are known to be incomplete. Is there a canonical way of proving equal expressiveness (or equivalently, the existence of a conservative translation) between any two logics?









      share|cite|improve this question












      share|cite|improve this question




      share|cite|improve this question








      edited Jul 24 at 4:30









      Taroccoesbrocco

      3,48941431




      3,48941431









      asked Jul 23 at 18:51









      discretizer

      1077




      1077




















          1 Answer
          1






          active

          oldest

          votes

















          up vote
          3
          down vote



          accepted










          Translating constant symbols to variables does not work well, because in most logics where you contemplate formulas with free variables, the intended semantics is that of their universal closure. In those systems you have, for example
          $$ p(x) vDash p(y) qquadtextbut notqquad p(c_0) vDash p(c_1) $$
          because the models that satisfy $p(x)$ are exactly those where $p$ holds for every individual, which are the same models that satisfy $p(y)$.




          You can, however, simulate constants using new function and predicate symbols. Construct a new language by adding a fresh variable letter $0$, a single new unary predicate symbol $Z$, and countably many new symbol functions $f_n$, and then translate



          • each constant $c_n$ as $f_n(0)$;

          • all other parts of terms remain unchanged;

          • each atomic formula $p(t_1, ldots, t_n)$ as
            $$ neg exists 0Bigl (Z(0) land forall x(Z(x)to x=0) land neg p(t[t_1],ldots,t[t_n]Bigr); $$

          • and all connectives and quantifiers remain themselves

          I hope this qualifies for your concept of a translation $mathcal L_1tomathcal L_2$. If you want to be completely rigid about it, you could "make room" for the new $0,Z,f_n$ symbols by selecting existing symbols for them and shifting the existing symbols out of the way with the Hilbert's-hotel map as part of the translation, but I'm not going to complicate my notation by making that explicit.



          Suppose that for some $Gamma$, $varphi$ we have that $t(Gamma) vDash_2 t(varphi)$ and for some model $mathfrak M$ we have $mathfrak MvDash_1 Gamma$. Then we can construct a new $mathfrak M_2$ by selecting a single of $mathfrak M$'s elements to have the $Z$ property, and letting $(f_n)^mathfrak M_2$ map everything to $(c_n)^mathfrak M$ for each $n$.



          Then $mathfrak M_2vDash_2 t(psi)$ exactly if $mathfrak MvDash_1 psi$. Now since $mathfrak MvDash_1 Gamma$ we have $mathfrak M_2vDash_2 t(Gamma)$ and then by assumption $mathfrak M_2 vDash_2 t(varphi)$ and then $mathfrak MvDash_1 varphi$.



          Conversely, suppose $Gamma vDash_1 varphi$ and we have some $mathfrak M vDash_2 t(Gamma)$. Then,




          • either there is a unique $m_0inmathfrak M$ that satisfies $Z(m_0)$, and in that case we can construct an $mathfrak M_1$ by the reverse of the above procedure -- namely, let $(c_n)^mathfrak M_1$ be $f^mathfrak M(m_0)$ -- such that $mathfrak M_1vDash_1 psi$ iff $mathfrak MvDash_2 t(psi)$.


          • or there is no such element, in which case the translation of every atomic formula is true in $mathfrak M$ for all values of the variables. In that case let $mathfrak M_0$ be the model with a single element where all predicates are true; then $mathfrak M_0vDash_1 psi$ iff $mathfrak MvDash_2 t(psi)$.

          (The negations in the translation of atomic formulas are there to allow $mathfrak M_0$ to work when $p$ is the equality predicate $=$, which we're not allowed to make "always false" when constructing a model -- but we can make it "always true" by selecting a model with a single element).






          share|cite|improve this answer























          • Thank you so much for the detailed answer! Just to clarify: so if we fix the set of predicates and variables in our signature, then the language of first-order logic with constants would be strictly more expressive than the language of first-order logic without constants (because there are no ways to translate the individual constants into a language without constants such that $p(c_i)notvDash p(c_j)$ for $ineq j$ comes out true)?
            – discretizer
            Jul 25 at 13:55










          • @discretizer: Generally the only thing that would happen is that you'd need a more complex translation than this one, expressing the constants you remove by co-opting some of the predicates you still have. As long as there's a single binary predicate or a single binary function left in the language, it is still possible to find a translation for the full pure predicate calculus (with a countable infinitely of constants, functions and predicates of every arity). However, if you restrict yourself to unary functions and predicates, then you do lose expressivity.
            – Henning Makholm
            Jul 25 at 14:51











          • ah yes. sorry I overlooked the hilbert-map argument using existing symbols). Many thanks again.
            – discretizer
            Jul 25 at 15:21










          Your Answer




          StackExchange.ifUsing("editor", function ()
          return StackExchange.using("mathjaxEditing", function ()
          StackExchange.MarkdownEditor.creationCallbacks.add(function (editor, postfix)
          StackExchange.mathjaxEditing.prepareWmdForMathJax(editor, postfix, [["$", "$"], ["\\(","\\)"]]);
          );
          );
          , "mathjax-editing");

          StackExchange.ready(function()
          var channelOptions =
          tags: "".split(" "),
          id: "69"
          ;
          initTagRenderer("".split(" "), "".split(" "), channelOptions);

          StackExchange.using("externalEditor", function()
          // Have to fire editor after snippets, if snippets enabled
          if (StackExchange.settings.snippets.snippetsEnabled)
          StackExchange.using("snippets", function()
          createEditor();
          );

          else
          createEditor();

          );

          function createEditor()
          StackExchange.prepareEditor(
          heartbeatType: 'answer',
          convertImagesToLinks: true,
          noModals: false,
          showLowRepImageUploadWarning: true,
          reputationToPostImages: 10,
          bindNavPrevention: true,
          postfix: "",
          noCode: true, onDemand: true,
          discardSelector: ".discard-answer"
          ,immediatelyShowMarkdownHelp:true
          );



          );








           

          draft saved


          draft discarded


















          StackExchange.ready(
          function ()
          StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmath.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f2860666%2fis-first-order-logic-with-constants-equally-expressive-as-first-order-logic-with%23new-answer', 'question_page');

          );

          Post as a guest






























          1 Answer
          1






          active

          oldest

          votes








          1 Answer
          1






          active

          oldest

          votes









          active

          oldest

          votes






          active

          oldest

          votes








          up vote
          3
          down vote



          accepted










          Translating constant symbols to variables does not work well, because in most logics where you contemplate formulas with free variables, the intended semantics is that of their universal closure. In those systems you have, for example
          $$ p(x) vDash p(y) qquadtextbut notqquad p(c_0) vDash p(c_1) $$
          because the models that satisfy $p(x)$ are exactly those where $p$ holds for every individual, which are the same models that satisfy $p(y)$.




          You can, however, simulate constants using new function and predicate symbols. Construct a new language by adding a fresh variable letter $0$, a single new unary predicate symbol $Z$, and countably many new symbol functions $f_n$, and then translate



          • each constant $c_n$ as $f_n(0)$;

          • all other parts of terms remain unchanged;

          • each atomic formula $p(t_1, ldots, t_n)$ as
            $$ neg exists 0Bigl (Z(0) land forall x(Z(x)to x=0) land neg p(t[t_1],ldots,t[t_n]Bigr); $$

          • and all connectives and quantifiers remain themselves

          I hope this qualifies for your concept of a translation $mathcal L_1tomathcal L_2$. If you want to be completely rigid about it, you could "make room" for the new $0,Z,f_n$ symbols by selecting existing symbols for them and shifting the existing symbols out of the way with the Hilbert's-hotel map as part of the translation, but I'm not going to complicate my notation by making that explicit.



          Suppose that for some $Gamma$, $varphi$ we have that $t(Gamma) vDash_2 t(varphi)$ and for some model $mathfrak M$ we have $mathfrak MvDash_1 Gamma$. Then we can construct a new $mathfrak M_2$ by selecting a single of $mathfrak M$'s elements to have the $Z$ property, and letting $(f_n)^mathfrak M_2$ map everything to $(c_n)^mathfrak M$ for each $n$.



          Then $mathfrak M_2vDash_2 t(psi)$ exactly if $mathfrak MvDash_1 psi$. Now since $mathfrak MvDash_1 Gamma$ we have $mathfrak M_2vDash_2 t(Gamma)$ and then by assumption $mathfrak M_2 vDash_2 t(varphi)$ and then $mathfrak MvDash_1 varphi$.



          Conversely, suppose $Gamma vDash_1 varphi$ and we have some $mathfrak M vDash_2 t(Gamma)$. Then,




          • either there is a unique $m_0inmathfrak M$ that satisfies $Z(m_0)$, and in that case we can construct an $mathfrak M_1$ by the reverse of the above procedure -- namely, let $(c_n)^mathfrak M_1$ be $f^mathfrak M(m_0)$ -- such that $mathfrak M_1vDash_1 psi$ iff $mathfrak MvDash_2 t(psi)$.


          • or there is no such element, in which case the translation of every atomic formula is true in $mathfrak M$ for all values of the variables. In that case let $mathfrak M_0$ be the model with a single element where all predicates are true; then $mathfrak M_0vDash_1 psi$ iff $mathfrak MvDash_2 t(psi)$.

          (The negations in the translation of atomic formulas are there to allow $mathfrak M_0$ to work when $p$ is the equality predicate $=$, which we're not allowed to make "always false" when constructing a model -- but we can make it "always true" by selecting a model with a single element).






          share|cite|improve this answer























          • Thank you so much for the detailed answer! Just to clarify: so if we fix the set of predicates and variables in our signature, then the language of first-order logic with constants would be strictly more expressive than the language of first-order logic without constants (because there are no ways to translate the individual constants into a language without constants such that $p(c_i)notvDash p(c_j)$ for $ineq j$ comes out true)?
            – discretizer
            Jul 25 at 13:55










          • @discretizer: Generally the only thing that would happen is that you'd need a more complex translation than this one, expressing the constants you remove by co-opting some of the predicates you still have. As long as there's a single binary predicate or a single binary function left in the language, it is still possible to find a translation for the full pure predicate calculus (with a countable infinitely of constants, functions and predicates of every arity). However, if you restrict yourself to unary functions and predicates, then you do lose expressivity.
            – Henning Makholm
            Jul 25 at 14:51











          • ah yes. sorry I overlooked the hilbert-map argument using existing symbols). Many thanks again.
            – discretizer
            Jul 25 at 15:21














          up vote
          3
          down vote



          accepted










          Translating constant symbols to variables does not work well, because in most logics where you contemplate formulas with free variables, the intended semantics is that of their universal closure. In those systems you have, for example
          $$ p(x) vDash p(y) qquadtextbut notqquad p(c_0) vDash p(c_1) $$
          because the models that satisfy $p(x)$ are exactly those where $p$ holds for every individual, which are the same models that satisfy $p(y)$.




          You can, however, simulate constants using new function and predicate symbols. Construct a new language by adding a fresh variable letter $0$, a single new unary predicate symbol $Z$, and countably many new symbol functions $f_n$, and then translate



          • each constant $c_n$ as $f_n(0)$;

          • all other parts of terms remain unchanged;

          • each atomic formula $p(t_1, ldots, t_n)$ as
            $$ neg exists 0Bigl (Z(0) land forall x(Z(x)to x=0) land neg p(t[t_1],ldots,t[t_n]Bigr); $$

          • and all connectives and quantifiers remain themselves

          I hope this qualifies for your concept of a translation $mathcal L_1tomathcal L_2$. If you want to be completely rigid about it, you could "make room" for the new $0,Z,f_n$ symbols by selecting existing symbols for them and shifting the existing symbols out of the way with the Hilbert's-hotel map as part of the translation, but I'm not going to complicate my notation by making that explicit.



          Suppose that for some $Gamma$, $varphi$ we have that $t(Gamma) vDash_2 t(varphi)$ and for some model $mathfrak M$ we have $mathfrak MvDash_1 Gamma$. Then we can construct a new $mathfrak M_2$ by selecting a single of $mathfrak M$'s elements to have the $Z$ property, and letting $(f_n)^mathfrak M_2$ map everything to $(c_n)^mathfrak M$ for each $n$.



          Then $mathfrak M_2vDash_2 t(psi)$ exactly if $mathfrak MvDash_1 psi$. Now since $mathfrak MvDash_1 Gamma$ we have $mathfrak M_2vDash_2 t(Gamma)$ and then by assumption $mathfrak M_2 vDash_2 t(varphi)$ and then $mathfrak MvDash_1 varphi$.



          Conversely, suppose $Gamma vDash_1 varphi$ and we have some $mathfrak M vDash_2 t(Gamma)$. Then,




          • either there is a unique $m_0inmathfrak M$ that satisfies $Z(m_0)$, and in that case we can construct an $mathfrak M_1$ by the reverse of the above procedure -- namely, let $(c_n)^mathfrak M_1$ be $f^mathfrak M(m_0)$ -- such that $mathfrak M_1vDash_1 psi$ iff $mathfrak MvDash_2 t(psi)$.


          • or there is no such element, in which case the translation of every atomic formula is true in $mathfrak M$ for all values of the variables. In that case let $mathfrak M_0$ be the model with a single element where all predicates are true; then $mathfrak M_0vDash_1 psi$ iff $mathfrak MvDash_2 t(psi)$.

          (The negations in the translation of atomic formulas are there to allow $mathfrak M_0$ to work when $p$ is the equality predicate $=$, which we're not allowed to make "always false" when constructing a model -- but we can make it "always true" by selecting a model with a single element).






          share|cite|improve this answer























          • Thank you so much for the detailed answer! Just to clarify: so if we fix the set of predicates and variables in our signature, then the language of first-order logic with constants would be strictly more expressive than the language of first-order logic without constants (because there are no ways to translate the individual constants into a language without constants such that $p(c_i)notvDash p(c_j)$ for $ineq j$ comes out true)?
            – discretizer
            Jul 25 at 13:55










          • @discretizer: Generally the only thing that would happen is that you'd need a more complex translation than this one, expressing the constants you remove by co-opting some of the predicates you still have. As long as there's a single binary predicate or a single binary function left in the language, it is still possible to find a translation for the full pure predicate calculus (with a countable infinitely of constants, functions and predicates of every arity). However, if you restrict yourself to unary functions and predicates, then you do lose expressivity.
            – Henning Makholm
            Jul 25 at 14:51











          • ah yes. sorry I overlooked the hilbert-map argument using existing symbols). Many thanks again.
            – discretizer
            Jul 25 at 15:21












          up vote
          3
          down vote



          accepted







          up vote
          3
          down vote



          accepted






          Translating constant symbols to variables does not work well, because in most logics where you contemplate formulas with free variables, the intended semantics is that of their universal closure. In those systems you have, for example
          $$ p(x) vDash p(y) qquadtextbut notqquad p(c_0) vDash p(c_1) $$
          because the models that satisfy $p(x)$ are exactly those where $p$ holds for every individual, which are the same models that satisfy $p(y)$.




          You can, however, simulate constants using new function and predicate symbols. Construct a new language by adding a fresh variable letter $0$, a single new unary predicate symbol $Z$, and countably many new symbol functions $f_n$, and then translate



          • each constant $c_n$ as $f_n(0)$;

          • all other parts of terms remain unchanged;

          • each atomic formula $p(t_1, ldots, t_n)$ as
            $$ neg exists 0Bigl (Z(0) land forall x(Z(x)to x=0) land neg p(t[t_1],ldots,t[t_n]Bigr); $$

          • and all connectives and quantifiers remain themselves

          I hope this qualifies for your concept of a translation $mathcal L_1tomathcal L_2$. If you want to be completely rigid about it, you could "make room" for the new $0,Z,f_n$ symbols by selecting existing symbols for them and shifting the existing symbols out of the way with the Hilbert's-hotel map as part of the translation, but I'm not going to complicate my notation by making that explicit.



          Suppose that for some $Gamma$, $varphi$ we have that $t(Gamma) vDash_2 t(varphi)$ and for some model $mathfrak M$ we have $mathfrak MvDash_1 Gamma$. Then we can construct a new $mathfrak M_2$ by selecting a single of $mathfrak M$'s elements to have the $Z$ property, and letting $(f_n)^mathfrak M_2$ map everything to $(c_n)^mathfrak M$ for each $n$.



          Then $mathfrak M_2vDash_2 t(psi)$ exactly if $mathfrak MvDash_1 psi$. Now since $mathfrak MvDash_1 Gamma$ we have $mathfrak M_2vDash_2 t(Gamma)$ and then by assumption $mathfrak M_2 vDash_2 t(varphi)$ and then $mathfrak MvDash_1 varphi$.



          Conversely, suppose $Gamma vDash_1 varphi$ and we have some $mathfrak M vDash_2 t(Gamma)$. Then,




          • either there is a unique $m_0inmathfrak M$ that satisfies $Z(m_0)$, and in that case we can construct an $mathfrak M_1$ by the reverse of the above procedure -- namely, let $(c_n)^mathfrak M_1$ be $f^mathfrak M(m_0)$ -- such that $mathfrak M_1vDash_1 psi$ iff $mathfrak MvDash_2 t(psi)$.


          • or there is no such element, in which case the translation of every atomic formula is true in $mathfrak M$ for all values of the variables. In that case let $mathfrak M_0$ be the model with a single element where all predicates are true; then $mathfrak M_0vDash_1 psi$ iff $mathfrak MvDash_2 t(psi)$.

          (The negations in the translation of atomic formulas are there to allow $mathfrak M_0$ to work when $p$ is the equality predicate $=$, which we're not allowed to make "always false" when constructing a model -- but we can make it "always true" by selecting a model with a single element).






          share|cite|improve this answer















          Translating constant symbols to variables does not work well, because in most logics where you contemplate formulas with free variables, the intended semantics is that of their universal closure. In those systems you have, for example
          $$ p(x) vDash p(y) qquadtextbut notqquad p(c_0) vDash p(c_1) $$
          because the models that satisfy $p(x)$ are exactly those where $p$ holds for every individual, which are the same models that satisfy $p(y)$.




          You can, however, simulate constants using new function and predicate symbols. Construct a new language by adding a fresh variable letter $0$, a single new unary predicate symbol $Z$, and countably many new symbol functions $f_n$, and then translate



          • each constant $c_n$ as $f_n(0)$;

          • all other parts of terms remain unchanged;

          • each atomic formula $p(t_1, ldots, t_n)$ as
            $$ neg exists 0Bigl (Z(0) land forall x(Z(x)to x=0) land neg p(t[t_1],ldots,t[t_n]Bigr); $$

          • and all connectives and quantifiers remain themselves

          I hope this qualifies for your concept of a translation $mathcal L_1tomathcal L_2$. If you want to be completely rigid about it, you could "make room" for the new $0,Z,f_n$ symbols by selecting existing symbols for them and shifting the existing symbols out of the way with the Hilbert's-hotel map as part of the translation, but I'm not going to complicate my notation by making that explicit.



          Suppose that for some $Gamma$, $varphi$ we have that $t(Gamma) vDash_2 t(varphi)$ and for some model $mathfrak M$ we have $mathfrak MvDash_1 Gamma$. Then we can construct a new $mathfrak M_2$ by selecting a single of $mathfrak M$'s elements to have the $Z$ property, and letting $(f_n)^mathfrak M_2$ map everything to $(c_n)^mathfrak M$ for each $n$.



          Then $mathfrak M_2vDash_2 t(psi)$ exactly if $mathfrak MvDash_1 psi$. Now since $mathfrak MvDash_1 Gamma$ we have $mathfrak M_2vDash_2 t(Gamma)$ and then by assumption $mathfrak M_2 vDash_2 t(varphi)$ and then $mathfrak MvDash_1 varphi$.



          Conversely, suppose $Gamma vDash_1 varphi$ and we have some $mathfrak M vDash_2 t(Gamma)$. Then,




          • either there is a unique $m_0inmathfrak M$ that satisfies $Z(m_0)$, and in that case we can construct an $mathfrak M_1$ by the reverse of the above procedure -- namely, let $(c_n)^mathfrak M_1$ be $f^mathfrak M(m_0)$ -- such that $mathfrak M_1vDash_1 psi$ iff $mathfrak MvDash_2 t(psi)$.


          • or there is no such element, in which case the translation of every atomic formula is true in $mathfrak M$ for all values of the variables. In that case let $mathfrak M_0$ be the model with a single element where all predicates are true; then $mathfrak M_0vDash_1 psi$ iff $mathfrak MvDash_2 t(psi)$.

          (The negations in the translation of atomic formulas are there to allow $mathfrak M_0$ to work when $p$ is the equality predicate $=$, which we're not allowed to make "always false" when constructing a model -- but we can make it "always true" by selecting a model with a single element).







          share|cite|improve this answer















          share|cite|improve this answer



          share|cite|improve this answer








          edited Jul 24 at 2:13


























          answered Jul 24 at 2:01









          Henning Makholm

          225k16290516




          225k16290516











          • Thank you so much for the detailed answer! Just to clarify: so if we fix the set of predicates and variables in our signature, then the language of first-order logic with constants would be strictly more expressive than the language of first-order logic without constants (because there are no ways to translate the individual constants into a language without constants such that $p(c_i)notvDash p(c_j)$ for $ineq j$ comes out true)?
            – discretizer
            Jul 25 at 13:55










          • @discretizer: Generally the only thing that would happen is that you'd need a more complex translation than this one, expressing the constants you remove by co-opting some of the predicates you still have. As long as there's a single binary predicate or a single binary function left in the language, it is still possible to find a translation for the full pure predicate calculus (with a countable infinitely of constants, functions and predicates of every arity). However, if you restrict yourself to unary functions and predicates, then you do lose expressivity.
            – Henning Makholm
            Jul 25 at 14:51











          • ah yes. sorry I overlooked the hilbert-map argument using existing symbols). Many thanks again.
            – discretizer
            Jul 25 at 15:21
















          • Thank you so much for the detailed answer! Just to clarify: so if we fix the set of predicates and variables in our signature, then the language of first-order logic with constants would be strictly more expressive than the language of first-order logic without constants (because there are no ways to translate the individual constants into a language without constants such that $p(c_i)notvDash p(c_j)$ for $ineq j$ comes out true)?
            – discretizer
            Jul 25 at 13:55










          • @discretizer: Generally the only thing that would happen is that you'd need a more complex translation than this one, expressing the constants you remove by co-opting some of the predicates you still have. As long as there's a single binary predicate or a single binary function left in the language, it is still possible to find a translation for the full pure predicate calculus (with a countable infinitely of constants, functions and predicates of every arity). However, if you restrict yourself to unary functions and predicates, then you do lose expressivity.
            – Henning Makholm
            Jul 25 at 14:51











          • ah yes. sorry I overlooked the hilbert-map argument using existing symbols). Many thanks again.
            – discretizer
            Jul 25 at 15:21















          Thank you so much for the detailed answer! Just to clarify: so if we fix the set of predicates and variables in our signature, then the language of first-order logic with constants would be strictly more expressive than the language of first-order logic without constants (because there are no ways to translate the individual constants into a language without constants such that $p(c_i)notvDash p(c_j)$ for $ineq j$ comes out true)?
          – discretizer
          Jul 25 at 13:55




          Thank you so much for the detailed answer! Just to clarify: so if we fix the set of predicates and variables in our signature, then the language of first-order logic with constants would be strictly more expressive than the language of first-order logic without constants (because there are no ways to translate the individual constants into a language without constants such that $p(c_i)notvDash p(c_j)$ for $ineq j$ comes out true)?
          – discretizer
          Jul 25 at 13:55












          @discretizer: Generally the only thing that would happen is that you'd need a more complex translation than this one, expressing the constants you remove by co-opting some of the predicates you still have. As long as there's a single binary predicate or a single binary function left in the language, it is still possible to find a translation for the full pure predicate calculus (with a countable infinitely of constants, functions and predicates of every arity). However, if you restrict yourself to unary functions and predicates, then you do lose expressivity.
          – Henning Makholm
          Jul 25 at 14:51





          @discretizer: Generally the only thing that would happen is that you'd need a more complex translation than this one, expressing the constants you remove by co-opting some of the predicates you still have. As long as there's a single binary predicate or a single binary function left in the language, it is still possible to find a translation for the full pure predicate calculus (with a countable infinitely of constants, functions and predicates of every arity). However, if you restrict yourself to unary functions and predicates, then you do lose expressivity.
          – Henning Makholm
          Jul 25 at 14:51













          ah yes. sorry I overlooked the hilbert-map argument using existing symbols). Many thanks again.
          – discretizer
          Jul 25 at 15:21




          ah yes. sorry I overlooked the hilbert-map argument using existing symbols). Many thanks again.
          – discretizer
          Jul 25 at 15:21












           

          draft saved


          draft discarded


























           


          draft saved


          draft discarded














          StackExchange.ready(
          function ()
          StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmath.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f2860666%2fis-first-order-logic-with-constants-equally-expressive-as-first-order-logic-with%23new-answer', 'question_page');

          );

          Post as a guest













































































          Comments

          Popular posts from this blog

          What is the equation of a 3D cone with generalised tilt?

          Color the edges and diagonals of a regular polygon

          Relationship between determinant of matrix and determinant of adjoint?