Understanding proof of monotonic increasing function and continuity

The name of the pictureThe name of the pictureThe name of the pictureClash Royale CLAN TAG#URR8PPP











up vote
0
down vote

favorite












I found this statement with the proof:



enter image description here



But I don't understand the proof. Where is the contradiction? We have a nonempty interval $J$ contained in the nonempty interval $(f(a),f(b))$. Where is the problem?







share|cite|improve this question



















  • The contradiction comes in that for $yin J$, the equation $y = f(x)$ has no solution.
    – BindersFull
    Jul 24 at 12:58










  • Why is there no solution?
    – mathstackuser
    Jul 24 at 13:16














up vote
0
down vote

favorite












I found this statement with the proof:



enter image description here



But I don't understand the proof. Where is the contradiction? We have a nonempty interval $J$ contained in the nonempty interval $(f(a),f(b))$. Where is the problem?







share|cite|improve this question



















  • The contradiction comes in that for $yin J$, the equation $y = f(x)$ has no solution.
    – BindersFull
    Jul 24 at 12:58










  • Why is there no solution?
    – mathstackuser
    Jul 24 at 13:16












up vote
0
down vote

favorite









up vote
0
down vote

favorite











I found this statement with the proof:



enter image description here



But I don't understand the proof. Where is the contradiction? We have a nonempty interval $J$ contained in the nonempty interval $(f(a),f(b))$. Where is the problem?







share|cite|improve this question











I found this statement with the proof:



enter image description here



But I don't understand the proof. Where is the contradiction? We have a nonempty interval $J$ contained in the nonempty interval $(f(a),f(b))$. Where is the problem?









share|cite|improve this question










share|cite|improve this question




share|cite|improve this question









asked Jul 24 at 12:41









mathstackuser

40410




40410











  • The contradiction comes in that for $yin J$, the equation $y = f(x)$ has no solution.
    – BindersFull
    Jul 24 at 12:58










  • Why is there no solution?
    – mathstackuser
    Jul 24 at 13:16
















  • The contradiction comes in that for $yin J$, the equation $y = f(x)$ has no solution.
    – BindersFull
    Jul 24 at 12:58










  • Why is there no solution?
    – mathstackuser
    Jul 24 at 13:16















The contradiction comes in that for $yin J$, the equation $y = f(x)$ has no solution.
– BindersFull
Jul 24 at 12:58




The contradiction comes in that for $yin J$, the equation $y = f(x)$ has no solution.
– BindersFull
Jul 24 at 12:58












Why is there no solution?
– mathstackuser
Jul 24 at 13:16




Why is there no solution?
– mathstackuser
Jul 24 at 13:16










3 Answers
3






active

oldest

votes

















up vote
2
down vote



accepted










In the above form the proof isn't done well. You know that $y_0^- < f(x_0)$ or $f(x_0) < y_0^+$. Hence at least one of the intervals $J^- = (y_0^-, f(x_0))$ and $J^+ = (f(x_0),y_0^+)$ is non-empty and does not contain any point of the form $f(x)$. This comes from the fact that $f(x_0)$ is contained in none of these intervals and $f(x) le y_0^-$ for $x < x_0$ and $f(x) ge y_0^+$ for $x > x_0$. W.l.o.g. assume $J^- ne emptyset$ and $J^- cap f(I) = emptyset$.



This is a contradiction: By assumption $f(I)$ is an interval which must contain $J^-$ because $f(a) le y_0^-$ and $y_0^+ le f(b)$.






share|cite|improve this answer























  • Of course one of the intervals is non empty. But why does it not contain any point of the form $f(x)$? And isn't $(f(a),f(b))$ always an interval, just by the definition of the notation?
    – mathstackuser
    Jul 24 at 13:18











  • I shall edit my answer.
    – Paul Frost
    Jul 24 at 13:21

















up vote
1
down vote













There have been two answers, but the comments have shown that the arguments at first glance appeared a little obscure or cumbersome. I believe that everything is clarified now, either by enhancing the answers or by additional comments. But let us give another proof which is hopefully more transparent from the beginning.



Observe that in the theorem it is not specified whether $I$ is an open, closed or half-open interval and whether it is bounded or not. We shall prove the stronger result that $f$ is continuous on $I$.



Assume that $f$ is not continuous in a point $x_0 in I$. Then $y_0^- < f(x_0)$ or $f(x_0) < y_0^+$. Note that only one of $y_0^pm$ is defined if $x_0$ is a boundary point of $I$. We only consider the case $y_0^- < f(x_0)$, the other case is similar. The case under consideration can only occur when $I' = I cap (-infty,x_0) ne emptyset$. For $x < x_0$ we have $f(x) le y_0^-$, for $x > x_0$ we have $f(x) ge f(x_0)$. Therefore $(y_0^-,f(x_0) cap f(I) = emptyset$. For $xi in I'$ we have $f(xi) le y_0^-$ so that $(y_0^-,f(x_0) subset [f(xi),f(x_0)] subset f(I)$ because $f(I)$ is an interval. This is the desired contradiction.






share|cite|improve this answer




























    up vote
    0
    down vote













    This is essentially Paul Frost's answer, in a slighly less verbose form.



    The range $f(I)$ contains the interval $(f(a),f(b))$, so every point in the interval $(f(a),f(b))$ is of the form $f(x)$ for some $xin I$. On the other hand, only one endpoint of the non-empty interval $J$ is a value of $f$ - because $f$ jumps from $y_0^-$ to $y_0^+$. That is the contradiction.






    share|cite|improve this answer























    • Don't we have $f((a,b))subseteq (f(a),f(b))$ because $f$ is monotone increasing? It loks lik you claim it the other way round? And what do you mean by endpoints of the interval? They are open...
      – mathstackuser
      Jul 24 at 13:38











    • I am assuming that $I$ is an interval containing the points $a$ and $b$. Therefore $f(a)$ and $f(b)$ are values of $f$ that belong to the range, $f(I)$. Since the range is an interval, it must contain the interval $(f(a),f(b))$. In order to prove the inclusion that you wrote down we need continuity, but we don't have it yet. Yes, the interval is open, but surely you understand what are its end points, no?
      – uniquesolution
      Jul 24 at 13:46










    • ... after all, you are using the notation $(a,b)$ to designate an open interval, by means of the "end points" $a,b$.
      – uniquesolution
      Jul 24 at 13:56










    Your Answer




    StackExchange.ifUsing("editor", function ()
    return StackExchange.using("mathjaxEditing", function ()
    StackExchange.MarkdownEditor.creationCallbacks.add(function (editor, postfix)
    StackExchange.mathjaxEditing.prepareWmdForMathJax(editor, postfix, [["$", "$"], ["\\(","\\)"]]);
    );
    );
    , "mathjax-editing");

    StackExchange.ready(function()
    var channelOptions =
    tags: "".split(" "),
    id: "69"
    ;
    initTagRenderer("".split(" "), "".split(" "), channelOptions);

    StackExchange.using("externalEditor", function()
    // Have to fire editor after snippets, if snippets enabled
    if (StackExchange.settings.snippets.snippetsEnabled)
    StackExchange.using("snippets", function()
    createEditor();
    );

    else
    createEditor();

    );

    function createEditor()
    StackExchange.prepareEditor(
    heartbeatType: 'answer',
    convertImagesToLinks: true,
    noModals: false,
    showLowRepImageUploadWarning: true,
    reputationToPostImages: 10,
    bindNavPrevention: true,
    postfix: "",
    noCode: true, onDemand: true,
    discardSelector: ".discard-answer"
    ,immediatelyShowMarkdownHelp:true
    );



    );








     

    draft saved


    draft discarded


















    StackExchange.ready(
    function ()
    StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmath.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f2861293%2funderstanding-proof-of-monotonic-increasing-function-and-continuity%23new-answer', 'question_page');

    );

    Post as a guest






























    3 Answers
    3






    active

    oldest

    votes








    3 Answers
    3






    active

    oldest

    votes









    active

    oldest

    votes






    active

    oldest

    votes








    up vote
    2
    down vote



    accepted










    In the above form the proof isn't done well. You know that $y_0^- < f(x_0)$ or $f(x_0) < y_0^+$. Hence at least one of the intervals $J^- = (y_0^-, f(x_0))$ and $J^+ = (f(x_0),y_0^+)$ is non-empty and does not contain any point of the form $f(x)$. This comes from the fact that $f(x_0)$ is contained in none of these intervals and $f(x) le y_0^-$ for $x < x_0$ and $f(x) ge y_0^+$ for $x > x_0$. W.l.o.g. assume $J^- ne emptyset$ and $J^- cap f(I) = emptyset$.



    This is a contradiction: By assumption $f(I)$ is an interval which must contain $J^-$ because $f(a) le y_0^-$ and $y_0^+ le f(b)$.






    share|cite|improve this answer























    • Of course one of the intervals is non empty. But why does it not contain any point of the form $f(x)$? And isn't $(f(a),f(b))$ always an interval, just by the definition of the notation?
      – mathstackuser
      Jul 24 at 13:18











    • I shall edit my answer.
      – Paul Frost
      Jul 24 at 13:21














    up vote
    2
    down vote



    accepted










    In the above form the proof isn't done well. You know that $y_0^- < f(x_0)$ or $f(x_0) < y_0^+$. Hence at least one of the intervals $J^- = (y_0^-, f(x_0))$ and $J^+ = (f(x_0),y_0^+)$ is non-empty and does not contain any point of the form $f(x)$. This comes from the fact that $f(x_0)$ is contained in none of these intervals and $f(x) le y_0^-$ for $x < x_0$ and $f(x) ge y_0^+$ for $x > x_0$. W.l.o.g. assume $J^- ne emptyset$ and $J^- cap f(I) = emptyset$.



    This is a contradiction: By assumption $f(I)$ is an interval which must contain $J^-$ because $f(a) le y_0^-$ and $y_0^+ le f(b)$.






    share|cite|improve this answer























    • Of course one of the intervals is non empty. But why does it not contain any point of the form $f(x)$? And isn't $(f(a),f(b))$ always an interval, just by the definition of the notation?
      – mathstackuser
      Jul 24 at 13:18











    • I shall edit my answer.
      – Paul Frost
      Jul 24 at 13:21












    up vote
    2
    down vote



    accepted







    up vote
    2
    down vote



    accepted






    In the above form the proof isn't done well. You know that $y_0^- < f(x_0)$ or $f(x_0) < y_0^+$. Hence at least one of the intervals $J^- = (y_0^-, f(x_0))$ and $J^+ = (f(x_0),y_0^+)$ is non-empty and does not contain any point of the form $f(x)$. This comes from the fact that $f(x_0)$ is contained in none of these intervals and $f(x) le y_0^-$ for $x < x_0$ and $f(x) ge y_0^+$ for $x > x_0$. W.l.o.g. assume $J^- ne emptyset$ and $J^- cap f(I) = emptyset$.



    This is a contradiction: By assumption $f(I)$ is an interval which must contain $J^-$ because $f(a) le y_0^-$ and $y_0^+ le f(b)$.






    share|cite|improve this answer















    In the above form the proof isn't done well. You know that $y_0^- < f(x_0)$ or $f(x_0) < y_0^+$. Hence at least one of the intervals $J^- = (y_0^-, f(x_0))$ and $J^+ = (f(x_0),y_0^+)$ is non-empty and does not contain any point of the form $f(x)$. This comes from the fact that $f(x_0)$ is contained in none of these intervals and $f(x) le y_0^-$ for $x < x_0$ and $f(x) ge y_0^+$ for $x > x_0$. W.l.o.g. assume $J^- ne emptyset$ and $J^- cap f(I) = emptyset$.



    This is a contradiction: By assumption $f(I)$ is an interval which must contain $J^-$ because $f(a) le y_0^-$ and $y_0^+ le f(b)$.







    share|cite|improve this answer















    share|cite|improve this answer



    share|cite|improve this answer








    edited Jul 24 at 13:46


























    answered Jul 24 at 13:03









    Paul Frost

    3,623420




    3,623420











    • Of course one of the intervals is non empty. But why does it not contain any point of the form $f(x)$? And isn't $(f(a),f(b))$ always an interval, just by the definition of the notation?
      – mathstackuser
      Jul 24 at 13:18











    • I shall edit my answer.
      – Paul Frost
      Jul 24 at 13:21
















    • Of course one of the intervals is non empty. But why does it not contain any point of the form $f(x)$? And isn't $(f(a),f(b))$ always an interval, just by the definition of the notation?
      – mathstackuser
      Jul 24 at 13:18











    • I shall edit my answer.
      – Paul Frost
      Jul 24 at 13:21















    Of course one of the intervals is non empty. But why does it not contain any point of the form $f(x)$? And isn't $(f(a),f(b))$ always an interval, just by the definition of the notation?
    – mathstackuser
    Jul 24 at 13:18





    Of course one of the intervals is non empty. But why does it not contain any point of the form $f(x)$? And isn't $(f(a),f(b))$ always an interval, just by the definition of the notation?
    – mathstackuser
    Jul 24 at 13:18













    I shall edit my answer.
    – Paul Frost
    Jul 24 at 13:21




    I shall edit my answer.
    – Paul Frost
    Jul 24 at 13:21










    up vote
    1
    down vote













    There have been two answers, but the comments have shown that the arguments at first glance appeared a little obscure or cumbersome. I believe that everything is clarified now, either by enhancing the answers or by additional comments. But let us give another proof which is hopefully more transparent from the beginning.



    Observe that in the theorem it is not specified whether $I$ is an open, closed or half-open interval and whether it is bounded or not. We shall prove the stronger result that $f$ is continuous on $I$.



    Assume that $f$ is not continuous in a point $x_0 in I$. Then $y_0^- < f(x_0)$ or $f(x_0) < y_0^+$. Note that only one of $y_0^pm$ is defined if $x_0$ is a boundary point of $I$. We only consider the case $y_0^- < f(x_0)$, the other case is similar. The case under consideration can only occur when $I' = I cap (-infty,x_0) ne emptyset$. For $x < x_0$ we have $f(x) le y_0^-$, for $x > x_0$ we have $f(x) ge f(x_0)$. Therefore $(y_0^-,f(x_0) cap f(I) = emptyset$. For $xi in I'$ we have $f(xi) le y_0^-$ so that $(y_0^-,f(x_0) subset [f(xi),f(x_0)] subset f(I)$ because $f(I)$ is an interval. This is the desired contradiction.






    share|cite|improve this answer

























      up vote
      1
      down vote













      There have been two answers, but the comments have shown that the arguments at first glance appeared a little obscure or cumbersome. I believe that everything is clarified now, either by enhancing the answers or by additional comments. But let us give another proof which is hopefully more transparent from the beginning.



      Observe that in the theorem it is not specified whether $I$ is an open, closed or half-open interval and whether it is bounded or not. We shall prove the stronger result that $f$ is continuous on $I$.



      Assume that $f$ is not continuous in a point $x_0 in I$. Then $y_0^- < f(x_0)$ or $f(x_0) < y_0^+$. Note that only one of $y_0^pm$ is defined if $x_0$ is a boundary point of $I$. We only consider the case $y_0^- < f(x_0)$, the other case is similar. The case under consideration can only occur when $I' = I cap (-infty,x_0) ne emptyset$. For $x < x_0$ we have $f(x) le y_0^-$, for $x > x_0$ we have $f(x) ge f(x_0)$. Therefore $(y_0^-,f(x_0) cap f(I) = emptyset$. For $xi in I'$ we have $f(xi) le y_0^-$ so that $(y_0^-,f(x_0) subset [f(xi),f(x_0)] subset f(I)$ because $f(I)$ is an interval. This is the desired contradiction.






      share|cite|improve this answer























        up vote
        1
        down vote










        up vote
        1
        down vote









        There have been two answers, but the comments have shown that the arguments at first glance appeared a little obscure or cumbersome. I believe that everything is clarified now, either by enhancing the answers or by additional comments. But let us give another proof which is hopefully more transparent from the beginning.



        Observe that in the theorem it is not specified whether $I$ is an open, closed or half-open interval and whether it is bounded or not. We shall prove the stronger result that $f$ is continuous on $I$.



        Assume that $f$ is not continuous in a point $x_0 in I$. Then $y_0^- < f(x_0)$ or $f(x_0) < y_0^+$. Note that only one of $y_0^pm$ is defined if $x_0$ is a boundary point of $I$. We only consider the case $y_0^- < f(x_0)$, the other case is similar. The case under consideration can only occur when $I' = I cap (-infty,x_0) ne emptyset$. For $x < x_0$ we have $f(x) le y_0^-$, for $x > x_0$ we have $f(x) ge f(x_0)$. Therefore $(y_0^-,f(x_0) cap f(I) = emptyset$. For $xi in I'$ we have $f(xi) le y_0^-$ so that $(y_0^-,f(x_0) subset [f(xi),f(x_0)] subset f(I)$ because $f(I)$ is an interval. This is the desired contradiction.






        share|cite|improve this answer













        There have been two answers, but the comments have shown that the arguments at first glance appeared a little obscure or cumbersome. I believe that everything is clarified now, either by enhancing the answers or by additional comments. But let us give another proof which is hopefully more transparent from the beginning.



        Observe that in the theorem it is not specified whether $I$ is an open, closed or half-open interval and whether it is bounded or not. We shall prove the stronger result that $f$ is continuous on $I$.



        Assume that $f$ is not continuous in a point $x_0 in I$. Then $y_0^- < f(x_0)$ or $f(x_0) < y_0^+$. Note that only one of $y_0^pm$ is defined if $x_0$ is a boundary point of $I$. We only consider the case $y_0^- < f(x_0)$, the other case is similar. The case under consideration can only occur when $I' = I cap (-infty,x_0) ne emptyset$. For $x < x_0$ we have $f(x) le y_0^-$, for $x > x_0$ we have $f(x) ge f(x_0)$. Therefore $(y_0^-,f(x_0) cap f(I) = emptyset$. For $xi in I'$ we have $f(xi) le y_0^-$ so that $(y_0^-,f(x_0) subset [f(xi),f(x_0)] subset f(I)$ because $f(I)$ is an interval. This is the desired contradiction.







        share|cite|improve this answer













        share|cite|improve this answer



        share|cite|improve this answer











        answered Jul 24 at 16:17









        Paul Frost

        3,623420




        3,623420




















            up vote
            0
            down vote













            This is essentially Paul Frost's answer, in a slighly less verbose form.



            The range $f(I)$ contains the interval $(f(a),f(b))$, so every point in the interval $(f(a),f(b))$ is of the form $f(x)$ for some $xin I$. On the other hand, only one endpoint of the non-empty interval $J$ is a value of $f$ - because $f$ jumps from $y_0^-$ to $y_0^+$. That is the contradiction.






            share|cite|improve this answer























            • Don't we have $f((a,b))subseteq (f(a),f(b))$ because $f$ is monotone increasing? It loks lik you claim it the other way round? And what do you mean by endpoints of the interval? They are open...
              – mathstackuser
              Jul 24 at 13:38











            • I am assuming that $I$ is an interval containing the points $a$ and $b$. Therefore $f(a)$ and $f(b)$ are values of $f$ that belong to the range, $f(I)$. Since the range is an interval, it must contain the interval $(f(a),f(b))$. In order to prove the inclusion that you wrote down we need continuity, but we don't have it yet. Yes, the interval is open, but surely you understand what are its end points, no?
              – uniquesolution
              Jul 24 at 13:46










            • ... after all, you are using the notation $(a,b)$ to designate an open interval, by means of the "end points" $a,b$.
              – uniquesolution
              Jul 24 at 13:56














            up vote
            0
            down vote













            This is essentially Paul Frost's answer, in a slighly less verbose form.



            The range $f(I)$ contains the interval $(f(a),f(b))$, so every point in the interval $(f(a),f(b))$ is of the form $f(x)$ for some $xin I$. On the other hand, only one endpoint of the non-empty interval $J$ is a value of $f$ - because $f$ jumps from $y_0^-$ to $y_0^+$. That is the contradiction.






            share|cite|improve this answer























            • Don't we have $f((a,b))subseteq (f(a),f(b))$ because $f$ is monotone increasing? It loks lik you claim it the other way round? And what do you mean by endpoints of the interval? They are open...
              – mathstackuser
              Jul 24 at 13:38











            • I am assuming that $I$ is an interval containing the points $a$ and $b$. Therefore $f(a)$ and $f(b)$ are values of $f$ that belong to the range, $f(I)$. Since the range is an interval, it must contain the interval $(f(a),f(b))$. In order to prove the inclusion that you wrote down we need continuity, but we don't have it yet. Yes, the interval is open, but surely you understand what are its end points, no?
              – uniquesolution
              Jul 24 at 13:46










            • ... after all, you are using the notation $(a,b)$ to designate an open interval, by means of the "end points" $a,b$.
              – uniquesolution
              Jul 24 at 13:56












            up vote
            0
            down vote










            up vote
            0
            down vote









            This is essentially Paul Frost's answer, in a slighly less verbose form.



            The range $f(I)$ contains the interval $(f(a),f(b))$, so every point in the interval $(f(a),f(b))$ is of the form $f(x)$ for some $xin I$. On the other hand, only one endpoint of the non-empty interval $J$ is a value of $f$ - because $f$ jumps from $y_0^-$ to $y_0^+$. That is the contradiction.






            share|cite|improve this answer















            This is essentially Paul Frost's answer, in a slighly less verbose form.



            The range $f(I)$ contains the interval $(f(a),f(b))$, so every point in the interval $(f(a),f(b))$ is of the form $f(x)$ for some $xin I$. On the other hand, only one endpoint of the non-empty interval $J$ is a value of $f$ - because $f$ jumps from $y_0^-$ to $y_0^+$. That is the contradiction.







            share|cite|improve this answer















            share|cite|improve this answer



            share|cite|improve this answer








            edited Jul 24 at 13:52


























            answered Jul 24 at 12:53









            uniquesolution

            7,630721




            7,630721











            • Don't we have $f((a,b))subseteq (f(a),f(b))$ because $f$ is monotone increasing? It loks lik you claim it the other way round? And what do you mean by endpoints of the interval? They are open...
              – mathstackuser
              Jul 24 at 13:38











            • I am assuming that $I$ is an interval containing the points $a$ and $b$. Therefore $f(a)$ and $f(b)$ are values of $f$ that belong to the range, $f(I)$. Since the range is an interval, it must contain the interval $(f(a),f(b))$. In order to prove the inclusion that you wrote down we need continuity, but we don't have it yet. Yes, the interval is open, but surely you understand what are its end points, no?
              – uniquesolution
              Jul 24 at 13:46










            • ... after all, you are using the notation $(a,b)$ to designate an open interval, by means of the "end points" $a,b$.
              – uniquesolution
              Jul 24 at 13:56
















            • Don't we have $f((a,b))subseteq (f(a),f(b))$ because $f$ is monotone increasing? It loks lik you claim it the other way round? And what do you mean by endpoints of the interval? They are open...
              – mathstackuser
              Jul 24 at 13:38











            • I am assuming that $I$ is an interval containing the points $a$ and $b$. Therefore $f(a)$ and $f(b)$ are values of $f$ that belong to the range, $f(I)$. Since the range is an interval, it must contain the interval $(f(a),f(b))$. In order to prove the inclusion that you wrote down we need continuity, but we don't have it yet. Yes, the interval is open, but surely you understand what are its end points, no?
              – uniquesolution
              Jul 24 at 13:46










            • ... after all, you are using the notation $(a,b)$ to designate an open interval, by means of the "end points" $a,b$.
              – uniquesolution
              Jul 24 at 13:56















            Don't we have $f((a,b))subseteq (f(a),f(b))$ because $f$ is monotone increasing? It loks lik you claim it the other way round? And what do you mean by endpoints of the interval? They are open...
            – mathstackuser
            Jul 24 at 13:38





            Don't we have $f((a,b))subseteq (f(a),f(b))$ because $f$ is monotone increasing? It loks lik you claim it the other way round? And what do you mean by endpoints of the interval? They are open...
            – mathstackuser
            Jul 24 at 13:38













            I am assuming that $I$ is an interval containing the points $a$ and $b$. Therefore $f(a)$ and $f(b)$ are values of $f$ that belong to the range, $f(I)$. Since the range is an interval, it must contain the interval $(f(a),f(b))$. In order to prove the inclusion that you wrote down we need continuity, but we don't have it yet. Yes, the interval is open, but surely you understand what are its end points, no?
            – uniquesolution
            Jul 24 at 13:46




            I am assuming that $I$ is an interval containing the points $a$ and $b$. Therefore $f(a)$ and $f(b)$ are values of $f$ that belong to the range, $f(I)$. Since the range is an interval, it must contain the interval $(f(a),f(b))$. In order to prove the inclusion that you wrote down we need continuity, but we don't have it yet. Yes, the interval is open, but surely you understand what are its end points, no?
            – uniquesolution
            Jul 24 at 13:46












            ... after all, you are using the notation $(a,b)$ to designate an open interval, by means of the "end points" $a,b$.
            – uniquesolution
            Jul 24 at 13:56




            ... after all, you are using the notation $(a,b)$ to designate an open interval, by means of the "end points" $a,b$.
            – uniquesolution
            Jul 24 at 13:56












             

            draft saved


            draft discarded


























             


            draft saved


            draft discarded














            StackExchange.ready(
            function ()
            StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmath.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f2861293%2funderstanding-proof-of-monotonic-increasing-function-and-continuity%23new-answer', 'question_page');

            );

            Post as a guest













































































            Comments

            Popular posts from this blog

            What is the equation of a 3D cone with generalised tilt?

            Color the edges and diagonals of a regular polygon

            Relationship between determinant of matrix and determinant of adjoint?