What exactly is circular reasoning?

The name of the pictureThe name of the pictureThe name of the pictureClash Royale CLAN TAG#URR8PPP











up vote
21
down vote

favorite
3












The way I used to be getting it was that circular reasoning occurs when a proof contains its thesis within its assumptions. Then, everything such a proof "proves" is that this particular statement entails itself; which is trivial since any statement entails itself.



But I witnessed a conversation that made me think I'm not getting this at all.



In short, Bob accused Alice of circular reasoning. But Alice responded in a way that perplexed me:




Of course my proof contains its thesis within its assumptions. Each and every proof must be based on axioms, which are assumptions that are not to be proved. Thus each set of axioms implicitly contains all theses that can be proven from this set of axioms. As we know, each theorem in mathematics and logic is little more than a tautology: so is mine.




Not sure what should I think? On the one hand, Alice's reasoning seems correct. I, at least, can't find any error there. On the other hand, this entails that... Every valid proof must be circular! Which is absurd.



What is a circular proof? And what is wrong with the reasoning above?







share|cite|improve this question

















  • 16




    Your understanding, prior to reading about Alice and Bob, is correct.
    – amWhy
    Jul 28 at 23:40







  • 2




    I agree with @amWhy. I deny that each set of axioms implicitly contain all theorems that can be proven from this set of axioms. To say such a thing would be to confuse truth utterly. Otherwise, we'd have to say that the statement, "$1+1=2$" is the same as $fracddx,x^2=2x.$ They're not the same thing at all, even though they're both true.
    – Adrian Keister
    Jul 28 at 23:44






  • 1




    @PoonLevi: I don't think we're using the word "contain" the same way. Surely any mathematician would agree that any given set of axioms would uniquely determine a set of theorems provable from those axioms. If that's how you're using the term "contain", then I'd agree. But if "contain" means that the meaning of the theorems is contained in the meaning of the axioms, I can't go there. Different statements mean different things, or there'd be no use for language at all and no one could distinguish one true statement from another.
    – Adrian Keister
    Jul 29 at 1:45






  • 5




    "Thus each set of axioms implicite contains all thesis" That's weaslely but not nesc. false. However if Alice wishes to take that viewpoint then the job of a proof is to demonstrate how her thesis is contained specifically from the axioms. Bob's complaint, in this viewpoint, isn't that Alice's thesis in contained via the axioms but that her demonstration failed to show how or why it is so contained in a satisfactory manner.
    – fleablood
    Jul 29 at 2:07







  • 1




    @AdrianKeister "They're not the same thing at all, even though they're both true." Although I agree with you, I feel if you make such a claim, you are behoven to explain why you think $1+1=2$ and $frac ddxx^2 =2x$ are different things. (Because $1+1=2$ is an axiom/definition and the other is a result? According to Alice those are the same. I disagree with her but I see her point. Why are you claiming they are different.) " But if "contain" means that the meaning of the theorems is contained in the meaning of the axioms, I can't go there." I don't think that is Alice's viewpoint.
    – fleablood
    Jul 29 at 2:14














up vote
21
down vote

favorite
3












The way I used to be getting it was that circular reasoning occurs when a proof contains its thesis within its assumptions. Then, everything such a proof "proves" is that this particular statement entails itself; which is trivial since any statement entails itself.



But I witnessed a conversation that made me think I'm not getting this at all.



In short, Bob accused Alice of circular reasoning. But Alice responded in a way that perplexed me:




Of course my proof contains its thesis within its assumptions. Each and every proof must be based on axioms, which are assumptions that are not to be proved. Thus each set of axioms implicitly contains all theses that can be proven from this set of axioms. As we know, each theorem in mathematics and logic is little more than a tautology: so is mine.




Not sure what should I think? On the one hand, Alice's reasoning seems correct. I, at least, can't find any error there. On the other hand, this entails that... Every valid proof must be circular! Which is absurd.



What is a circular proof? And what is wrong with the reasoning above?







share|cite|improve this question

















  • 16




    Your understanding, prior to reading about Alice and Bob, is correct.
    – amWhy
    Jul 28 at 23:40







  • 2




    I agree with @amWhy. I deny that each set of axioms implicitly contain all theorems that can be proven from this set of axioms. To say such a thing would be to confuse truth utterly. Otherwise, we'd have to say that the statement, "$1+1=2$" is the same as $fracddx,x^2=2x.$ They're not the same thing at all, even though they're both true.
    – Adrian Keister
    Jul 28 at 23:44






  • 1




    @PoonLevi: I don't think we're using the word "contain" the same way. Surely any mathematician would agree that any given set of axioms would uniquely determine a set of theorems provable from those axioms. If that's how you're using the term "contain", then I'd agree. But if "contain" means that the meaning of the theorems is contained in the meaning of the axioms, I can't go there. Different statements mean different things, or there'd be no use for language at all and no one could distinguish one true statement from another.
    – Adrian Keister
    Jul 29 at 1:45






  • 5




    "Thus each set of axioms implicite contains all thesis" That's weaslely but not nesc. false. However if Alice wishes to take that viewpoint then the job of a proof is to demonstrate how her thesis is contained specifically from the axioms. Bob's complaint, in this viewpoint, isn't that Alice's thesis in contained via the axioms but that her demonstration failed to show how or why it is so contained in a satisfactory manner.
    – fleablood
    Jul 29 at 2:07







  • 1




    @AdrianKeister "They're not the same thing at all, even though they're both true." Although I agree with you, I feel if you make such a claim, you are behoven to explain why you think $1+1=2$ and $frac ddxx^2 =2x$ are different things. (Because $1+1=2$ is an axiom/definition and the other is a result? According to Alice those are the same. I disagree with her but I see her point. Why are you claiming they are different.) " But if "contain" means that the meaning of the theorems is contained in the meaning of the axioms, I can't go there." I don't think that is Alice's viewpoint.
    – fleablood
    Jul 29 at 2:14












up vote
21
down vote

favorite
3









up vote
21
down vote

favorite
3






3





The way I used to be getting it was that circular reasoning occurs when a proof contains its thesis within its assumptions. Then, everything such a proof "proves" is that this particular statement entails itself; which is trivial since any statement entails itself.



But I witnessed a conversation that made me think I'm not getting this at all.



In short, Bob accused Alice of circular reasoning. But Alice responded in a way that perplexed me:




Of course my proof contains its thesis within its assumptions. Each and every proof must be based on axioms, which are assumptions that are not to be proved. Thus each set of axioms implicitly contains all theses that can be proven from this set of axioms. As we know, each theorem in mathematics and logic is little more than a tautology: so is mine.




Not sure what should I think? On the one hand, Alice's reasoning seems correct. I, at least, can't find any error there. On the other hand, this entails that... Every valid proof must be circular! Which is absurd.



What is a circular proof? And what is wrong with the reasoning above?







share|cite|improve this question













The way I used to be getting it was that circular reasoning occurs when a proof contains its thesis within its assumptions. Then, everything such a proof "proves" is that this particular statement entails itself; which is trivial since any statement entails itself.



But I witnessed a conversation that made me think I'm not getting this at all.



In short, Bob accused Alice of circular reasoning. But Alice responded in a way that perplexed me:




Of course my proof contains its thesis within its assumptions. Each and every proof must be based on axioms, which are assumptions that are not to be proved. Thus each set of axioms implicitly contains all theses that can be proven from this set of axioms. As we know, each theorem in mathematics and logic is little more than a tautology: so is mine.




Not sure what should I think? On the one hand, Alice's reasoning seems correct. I, at least, can't find any error there. On the other hand, this entails that... Every valid proof must be circular! Which is absurd.



What is a circular proof? And what is wrong with the reasoning above?









share|cite|improve this question












share|cite|improve this question




share|cite|improve this question








edited Jul 30 at 1:04









Daniel R. Collins

5,4701432




5,4701432









asked Jul 28 at 23:38









gaazkam

408313




408313







  • 16




    Your understanding, prior to reading about Alice and Bob, is correct.
    – amWhy
    Jul 28 at 23:40







  • 2




    I agree with @amWhy. I deny that each set of axioms implicitly contain all theorems that can be proven from this set of axioms. To say such a thing would be to confuse truth utterly. Otherwise, we'd have to say that the statement, "$1+1=2$" is the same as $fracddx,x^2=2x.$ They're not the same thing at all, even though they're both true.
    – Adrian Keister
    Jul 28 at 23:44






  • 1




    @PoonLevi: I don't think we're using the word "contain" the same way. Surely any mathematician would agree that any given set of axioms would uniquely determine a set of theorems provable from those axioms. If that's how you're using the term "contain", then I'd agree. But if "contain" means that the meaning of the theorems is contained in the meaning of the axioms, I can't go there. Different statements mean different things, or there'd be no use for language at all and no one could distinguish one true statement from another.
    – Adrian Keister
    Jul 29 at 1:45






  • 5




    "Thus each set of axioms implicite contains all thesis" That's weaslely but not nesc. false. However if Alice wishes to take that viewpoint then the job of a proof is to demonstrate how her thesis is contained specifically from the axioms. Bob's complaint, in this viewpoint, isn't that Alice's thesis in contained via the axioms but that her demonstration failed to show how or why it is so contained in a satisfactory manner.
    – fleablood
    Jul 29 at 2:07







  • 1




    @AdrianKeister "They're not the same thing at all, even though they're both true." Although I agree with you, I feel if you make such a claim, you are behoven to explain why you think $1+1=2$ and $frac ddxx^2 =2x$ are different things. (Because $1+1=2$ is an axiom/definition and the other is a result? According to Alice those are the same. I disagree with her but I see her point. Why are you claiming they are different.) " But if "contain" means that the meaning of the theorems is contained in the meaning of the axioms, I can't go there." I don't think that is Alice's viewpoint.
    – fleablood
    Jul 29 at 2:14












  • 16




    Your understanding, prior to reading about Alice and Bob, is correct.
    – amWhy
    Jul 28 at 23:40







  • 2




    I agree with @amWhy. I deny that each set of axioms implicitly contain all theorems that can be proven from this set of axioms. To say such a thing would be to confuse truth utterly. Otherwise, we'd have to say that the statement, "$1+1=2$" is the same as $fracddx,x^2=2x.$ They're not the same thing at all, even though they're both true.
    – Adrian Keister
    Jul 28 at 23:44






  • 1




    @PoonLevi: I don't think we're using the word "contain" the same way. Surely any mathematician would agree that any given set of axioms would uniquely determine a set of theorems provable from those axioms. If that's how you're using the term "contain", then I'd agree. But if "contain" means that the meaning of the theorems is contained in the meaning of the axioms, I can't go there. Different statements mean different things, or there'd be no use for language at all and no one could distinguish one true statement from another.
    – Adrian Keister
    Jul 29 at 1:45






  • 5




    "Thus each set of axioms implicite contains all thesis" That's weaslely but not nesc. false. However if Alice wishes to take that viewpoint then the job of a proof is to demonstrate how her thesis is contained specifically from the axioms. Bob's complaint, in this viewpoint, isn't that Alice's thesis in contained via the axioms but that her demonstration failed to show how or why it is so contained in a satisfactory manner.
    – fleablood
    Jul 29 at 2:07







  • 1




    @AdrianKeister "They're not the same thing at all, even though they're both true." Although I agree with you, I feel if you make such a claim, you are behoven to explain why you think $1+1=2$ and $frac ddxx^2 =2x$ are different things. (Because $1+1=2$ is an axiom/definition and the other is a result? According to Alice those are the same. I disagree with her but I see her point. Why are you claiming they are different.) " But if "contain" means that the meaning of the theorems is contained in the meaning of the axioms, I can't go there." I don't think that is Alice's viewpoint.
    – fleablood
    Jul 29 at 2:14







16




16




Your understanding, prior to reading about Alice and Bob, is correct.
– amWhy
Jul 28 at 23:40





Your understanding, prior to reading about Alice and Bob, is correct.
– amWhy
Jul 28 at 23:40





2




2




I agree with @amWhy. I deny that each set of axioms implicitly contain all theorems that can be proven from this set of axioms. To say such a thing would be to confuse truth utterly. Otherwise, we'd have to say that the statement, "$1+1=2$" is the same as $fracddx,x^2=2x.$ They're not the same thing at all, even though they're both true.
– Adrian Keister
Jul 28 at 23:44




I agree with @amWhy. I deny that each set of axioms implicitly contain all theorems that can be proven from this set of axioms. To say such a thing would be to confuse truth utterly. Otherwise, we'd have to say that the statement, "$1+1=2$" is the same as $fracddx,x^2=2x.$ They're not the same thing at all, even though they're both true.
– Adrian Keister
Jul 28 at 23:44




1




1




@PoonLevi: I don't think we're using the word "contain" the same way. Surely any mathematician would agree that any given set of axioms would uniquely determine a set of theorems provable from those axioms. If that's how you're using the term "contain", then I'd agree. But if "contain" means that the meaning of the theorems is contained in the meaning of the axioms, I can't go there. Different statements mean different things, or there'd be no use for language at all and no one could distinguish one true statement from another.
– Adrian Keister
Jul 29 at 1:45




@PoonLevi: I don't think we're using the word "contain" the same way. Surely any mathematician would agree that any given set of axioms would uniquely determine a set of theorems provable from those axioms. If that's how you're using the term "contain", then I'd agree. But if "contain" means that the meaning of the theorems is contained in the meaning of the axioms, I can't go there. Different statements mean different things, or there'd be no use for language at all and no one could distinguish one true statement from another.
– Adrian Keister
Jul 29 at 1:45




5




5




"Thus each set of axioms implicite contains all thesis" That's weaslely but not nesc. false. However if Alice wishes to take that viewpoint then the job of a proof is to demonstrate how her thesis is contained specifically from the axioms. Bob's complaint, in this viewpoint, isn't that Alice's thesis in contained via the axioms but that her demonstration failed to show how or why it is so contained in a satisfactory manner.
– fleablood
Jul 29 at 2:07





"Thus each set of axioms implicite contains all thesis" That's weaslely but not nesc. false. However if Alice wishes to take that viewpoint then the job of a proof is to demonstrate how her thesis is contained specifically from the axioms. Bob's complaint, in this viewpoint, isn't that Alice's thesis in contained via the axioms but that her demonstration failed to show how or why it is so contained in a satisfactory manner.
– fleablood
Jul 29 at 2:07





1




1




@AdrianKeister "They're not the same thing at all, even though they're both true." Although I agree with you, I feel if you make such a claim, you are behoven to explain why you think $1+1=2$ and $frac ddxx^2 =2x$ are different things. (Because $1+1=2$ is an axiom/definition and the other is a result? According to Alice those are the same. I disagree with her but I see her point. Why are you claiming they are different.) " But if "contain" means that the meaning of the theorems is contained in the meaning of the axioms, I can't go there." I don't think that is Alice's viewpoint.
– fleablood
Jul 29 at 2:14




@AdrianKeister "They're not the same thing at all, even though they're both true." Although I agree with you, I feel if you make such a claim, you are behoven to explain why you think $1+1=2$ and $frac ddxx^2 =2x$ are different things. (Because $1+1=2$ is an axiom/definition and the other is a result? According to Alice those are the same. I disagree with her but I see her point. Why are you claiming they are different.) " But if "contain" means that the meaning of the theorems is contained in the meaning of the axioms, I can't go there." I don't think that is Alice's viewpoint.
– fleablood
Jul 29 at 2:14










10 Answers
10






active

oldest

votes

















up vote
29
down vote














Of course my proof contains its thesis within its assumptions. Each and every proof must be based on axioms, which are assumptions that are not to be proved.




Hold it right there, Alice. These specific axioms are to be accepted without proof but nothing else is. For anything that is true that is not one of these axioms, the role of proof must be to demonstrate that such a truth can be derived from these axioms and how it would be so derived.




Thus each set of axioms implicite contains all thesis that can be proven from this set of axioms.




Implicit. But the role of a proof is to make the implicit explicit. I can claim that Fermat's last theorem is true. That is a true statement. But merely claiming it is not the same as a proof. I can claim the axioms of mathematics imply Fermat's last theorem and that would be true. But that's still not a proof. To prove it, I must demonstrate how the axioms imply it. And in doing so I can not base any of my demonstration implications upon the knowledge that I know it to be true.




As we know, each theorem in mathematics and logics is little more than a tautology:




That's not actually what a tautology is. But I'll assume you mean a true statement.




so is mine.




No one cares if your statement is true. We care if you can demonstrate how it is true. You did not do that.






share|cite|improve this answer



















  • 3




    To quote Google, a tautology (in logic) is "a statement that is true by necessity or by virtue of its logical form". That describes mathematics in a nutshell.
    – Theo Bendit
    Jul 29 at 3:49






  • 2




    "Thus each set of axioms implicite contains all thesis that can be proven from this set of axioms." No, that's not true. At least not if rules of inference are not axioms, and axioms are not rules of inference. Axioms don't imply anything at all without rules of inference.
    – Doug Spoonwood
    Jul 29 at 4:18










  • @DougSpoonwood I'd agree with that. But Alice wouldn't. Alice would say rules of inference and all potentially inferred statements (even those which haven't yet been inferred) are in the .... whatever it is that Alice is calling th body of math. This can be one way of looking at it, but it has nothing to do with proofs and how we know things are true or not. I'd say Alice is wrong but, I can't just say "she's stupid; ignore her"
    – fleablood
    Jul 29 at 5:06







  • 1




    @TheoBendit I think google isn't correct about that, or maybe they are using some colloquial definition. Most people who study formal logic use "tautology" to mean exactly that a statement is true under all possible assignments to the variables. What "all possible assignments" and "variables" means depends on the logic. So $a + b = b + a$ is a tautology in quantified arithmetic logic, but not if you are reasoning about strings with $+$ being string concatenation. $forall x. P(x) to P(x)$ is a tautology in First Order Logic, letting $P$ range over all possible relations.
    – DanielV
    Jul 30 at 0:18






  • 1




    In my head, $1+1= 2$ is the definition of $2$. Not a theorem, not an axiom. Simply stating that 'whenever I use the squggle "$2$", take that to be shorthand for "$1+1$"'.
    – Arthur
    Jul 30 at 9:31


















up vote
10
down vote













I believe this has a simple resolution:



When we say informally that Alice is required to prove a result, it is sloppy language; she is actually required to prove the implication axioms $implies$ result. So of course, she can have the axioms in her premises. However, she cannon have axioms $implies$ result as one of her premises; that would be circular reasoning.






share|cite|improve this answer





















  • Are you defining circular reasoning, as making a statement that a certain conclusion (result) follows from a set of axioms, without proof?
    – Pieter Rousseau
    Jul 30 at 6:45










  • @PieterRousseau I would say yes, at least as a practical definition that we use informally. However, if you back me into a corner, I would retreat to saying that a circular argument is any argument which has anything else other than axioms as premises (I would have to phrase it much more carefully m of course since that definition clearly encompasses more arguments than just the ones we would like to call circular.
    – Ovi
    Jul 30 at 7:48











  • " she is actually required to prove the implication axioms ⟹ result. " For clarification, you're saying that basically Alice has to show "axioms $vdash$ result" instead of "$vdash$ (axioms $rightarrow$ result)", correct? Also, you said "However, she cannon..." I think you meant 'cannot'... though maybe Alice is a cannon shrugs and laughs.
    – Doug Spoonwood
    Jul 30 at 7:52











  • @Ovi. Thanks for the clarification, I think I can agree with your more formal definition, because the premise (axioms ⟹ result) without proof is simply that: an unproven premise, nothing circular (I think). Unless I really misunderstood your answer.
    – Pieter Rousseau
    Jul 30 at 8:19










  • @DougSpoonwood Yes, I think so. I'm just a student so honestly I wasn't even familiar with the sideways T. I looked it up and it seems to mean "RHS is provable from LHS", but then I'm not sure what just "$vdash P$ means without a LHS
    – Ovi
    Jul 30 at 9:42

















up vote
10
down vote













All reasoning (whether formal or informal, mathematical, scientific, every-day-life, etc.) needs to satisfy two basic criteria in order to be considered good (sound) reasoning:



  1. The steps in the argument need to be logical (valid .. the conclusion follows from the premises)


  2. The assumptions (premises) need to be acceptable (true or at least agreed upon by the parties involved in the debate within which the argument is offered)


Now, what Alice is pointing out is that in the domain of deductive reasoning (which includes mathematical reasoning), the information contained in the conclusion is already contained in the premises ... in a way, the conclusion thus 'merely' pulls this out. .. Alice thus seems to be saying: "all mathematical reasoning is circular .. so why attack my argument on being circular?"



However, this is not a good defense against the charge of circular reasoning. First of all, there is a big difference between 'pulling out', say, some complicated theorem of arithmetic out of the Peano Axioms on the one hand, and simply assuming that very theorem as an assumption proven on the other:



In the former scenario, contrary to Alice's claim, we really do not say that circular reasoning is taking place: as long as the assumptions of the argument are nothing more than the agreed upon Peano Axioms, and as long as each inference leading up the the theorem is logically valid, then such an argument satisfied the two forementioned criteria, and is therefore perfectly acceptable.



In the latter case, however, circular reasoning is taking place: if all we agreed upon were the Peano axioms, but if the argument uses the conclusion (which is not part of those axioms) as an assumption, then that argument violates the second criterion. It can be said to 'beg the question' ... as it 'begs' the answer to the very question (is the theorem true?) we had in the first place.






share|cite|improve this answer























  • "Alice is correct that every proof relies on a set of axioms to which Alice and Bob have to agree beforehand." Alice said: "As we know, each theorem in mathematics and logics is little more than a tautology" Since she says all theorems are contained in the axioms, it seems that she would say that all axioms are tautologies. But, natural deduction proofs exist which don't use any tautologies at all, nor any axioms. Why need Alice and Bob agree on axioms instead of using a pure natural deduction system?
    – Doug Spoonwood
    Jul 29 at 5:45







  • 1




    @DougSpoonwood, while your point is quite sensible in non-mathematical contexts, the mathematical answer is: natural deductions from what? Whatever starting point for reasoning that you have, must, from a mathematical standpoint, be an assumption. (In logical reasoning applied to life this is not so: your starting point can be an assumption, or a concrete observation. Mathematics has no concrete observations not based on other assumptions.)
    – Wildcard
    Jul 29 at 8:26






  • 1




    @DougSpoonwood Natural deduction systems tend to minimize or even eliminate logical axioms. The non-logical axioms that discuss the actual domain subject matter, e.g. real numbers, remain unless you go full type theory. In that latter case (and the former case to a lesser extent), instead of agreeing about axioms, you have to agree on what constitutes a valid rule of inference/construction. At any rate, the (usual, semantic) definition of "tautology" doesn't depend on the deductive system.
    – Derek Elkins
    Jul 29 at 22:48










  • I feel it's important (albeit probably obvious) to note that, while we mustn't use our thesis as assumption in our proof, we must assume the negation of our thesis if we want to proof our thesis via contradiction.
    – Sudix
    Jul 29 at 23:10











  • It seems to me though that in defining good reasoning, you are using good reasoning. Is this not circular?
    – Pieter Rousseau
    Jul 30 at 6:35

















up vote
5
down vote













The fallacious version of circular reasoning is an appeal to the proposition



$$(A to A) to A tagC$$



That is, to establish a proposition $A$ from no premises, you first establish the proposition $A$ under an assumption of $A$. Example:



  • Accuser: "You stole that."

  • Defendant: "No I didn't, it was mine."

  • Accuser: "It couldn't have been yours because you can't steal something you own."

In that case the accuser is correct as far as pointing out that "stealing" implies "not yours" which implies "stealing", the $A to A$ part, but the fallacy comes from dropping the assumption and concluding "stealing" under no assumptions, which is the final $to A$.



Guessing what Bob's side of the argument was : "Because the semantic meaning of a theorem is contained in the semantic meaning of the assumptions, you used circular reasoning". Here Bob is making 2 mistakes. First, he is equating circular reasoning with the proposition $A to A$. But that isn't what circular reasoning is, because $A to A$ always holds, how can you object to that?



Second, he is not addressing the argument that Alice made. Even if $(A to A) to A$ (for her specific claim) applies to the assumptions and conclusions of her argument: unless she appealed to that theorem as an inference, she hasn't made any mistake. $(A to A) to A$ does hold in the case that $A$ itself is provable, such as when $A$ is a tautology. Observing this isn't deductively equivalent to assuming $(A to A) to A$ holds in all cases and using that as an inference.






share|cite|improve this answer




























    up vote
    4
    down vote













    If her thesis is true, you could argue she is somehow right. But we dont know that her thesis is true. Lets say A is the set of axioms, and S(A) all true statements derivable from this set, and t her thesis. Then she wants to show that t in S(A). Only if this were true she could use that t is in S(A). But she doesnt know it.



    To make it clear to her: you could ask why not use also not t to show that the axiom system is contradictory. How does she know not t is not in S(A)






    share|cite|improve this answer





















    • This hits the nail right on the head.
      – Vincent
      Jul 30 at 15:27

















    up vote
    3
    down vote













    (Not really an answer, but too long for a comment. Refer to amWhy's comment and Bram28's answer for a direct answer to your question.)



    From what I understand, tautologies have a reputation in philosophy as being a waste of time. Things like "if I am cold and wet, then I am cold" don't seem to contain any new information, and have little value. But, the philosophers wonder, why is mathematics, which traditionally is 100% tautology, so non-trivial and produces unexpected results?



    Well, I'm sure there are many answers to this, but the way I see it, it's finding a path from premises to conclusions that can be new information. Human beings aren't perfect; they cannot instantly account for every statement they hold to be true, and combine them in every possible way, to effortlessly see every consequence one can derive from them.



    This is the point of proofs/arguments. I can read over and properly comprehend the axioms of ZFC, the definition of $mathbbR^3$ and its Euclidean unit sphere, but that doesn't mean I instantly know how to prove the Banach-Tarski paradox!



    Alice's reply seems to take the opposite stance. She seems to be assuming, implicitly, that there is no such gap between premises, consequences, and hence conclusions, rendering arguments useless. It's a view that I think most people would consider extreme (and wrong).






    share|cite|improve this answer




























      up vote
      2
      down vote













      Supposing that Alice tells the truth about using circular reasoning, it can get demonstrated that Alice has made an error. Alice says:



      "Of course my proof contains its thesis within its assumptions. Each and every proof must be based on axioms, which are assumptions that are not to be proved. Thus each set of axioms implicite contains all thesis that can be proven from this set of axioms."



      Alright, let's suppose the first two sentences correct. The third is false though. Why? Because without rules of inference we can't conclude anything from any axioms. So, we can't conclude that each set of axioms implies all of the theses, because axioms don't imply theses in the first place. Ever since Frege it has been clear that rules of inference and axioms are not the same thing. Only axiom and rules of inference taken together imply a thesis. But then, the set of axioms doesn't implicitly contain all theses, because it's axioms and rules of inference that imply all theses provable in the theory.



      Edit: Also, it really doesn't work out that "logic is little more than a tautology" or "logic is little more than a collection of tautologies". Logic often involves showing something like A $vdash$ B, where A is not a tautology, nor is B, and A $vdash$ B is not a tautology.






      share|cite|improve this answer























      • So what you mean is that a set of axioms does not contain the rules of inference, without which no conclusions will follow anyways (Rules of inference + Axioms -> theses)?
        – Pieter Rousseau
        Jul 30 at 6:53











      • @PieterRousseau Yes, that's it.
        – Doug Spoonwood
        Jul 30 at 6:57






      • 1




        So what if Alice rephrased her statement: "Of course my proof contains its thesis within its assumptions. Each and every proof must be based on rules of inference and axioms, which are assumptions that are not to be proved. Thus each set of rules and axioms implicitly contains all thesis that can be proven from this set."
        – Pieter Rousseau
        Jul 30 at 7:00










      • @PieterRousseau I don't think that a rule of inference can accurately get called an assumption. Rules of inference don't bear truth, while assumptions do. You also have seemed to have dropped Alice's "implicite".
        – Doug Spoonwood
        Jul 30 at 7:04











      • "Rules of inference don't bear truth, while assumptions do." What do mean? Point of clarification: I am assuming with rules of inference that you are talking about rules of logic, such as A is A; A is not not A and if A is B and B is C then A is C. (sorry about dropping the "implicite" - I actually thought it was a typo, or I am misunderstanding what you mean - would you mind if we get back to that once I understand what you mean about assumptions.)
        – Pieter Rousseau
        Jul 30 at 7:35

















      up vote
      1
      down vote













      We can take the extreme case, where the axioms not only imply the conclusion, but contain the conclusion. Suppose I'm trying to prove it's raining outside. The following piece of reasoning is perfectly valid:




      It's raining, therefore it's raining.




      Nothing wrong with that, and no one would call it circular. It's just pointless. But suppose someone skeptical, without access to a window to look outside, were to challenge me to prove it's raining. If I now start my reasoning with "Well, we know that it's raining, so...", now I'm committing circular reasoning.



      Notice that in both cases my proof and my axioms were the same, only the context changes. Circularity is not a property of a proof, it's a property of the context in which that proof is given. When we prove something from axioms, we should choose the axioms to be statements that are known to be true. If they're not known to be true, this is a Bad Thing. A special case of this kind of Bad Thing is where one of the axioms is the conclusion we're trying to prove (which is not known to be true): this special case is called circular reasoning.






      share|cite|improve this answer




























        up vote
        -1
        down vote













        The apparent dilemma arises from two words which do not mean the same thing.



        You are talking about proofs. Alice is talking about truth. These are not the same thing.



        A statement which is always true is a tautology, so in a sense, every such statement, including a true theorem, is a tautology.



        But truth is not a proof.



        Proofs are simply the re-expression of statements as other statements without relying on other statements (i.e., no circular reasoning).



        But the result of a correct proof is no more true than the original statements, so a proof is likewise not always the truth.






        share|cite|improve this answer



















        • 1




          "So in a sense, every true statement, including a true theorem, is a tautology." The statement "it is raining withing 100 feet of me" is sometimes true and sometimes not true. In mathematics, the statement "a = b" is only sometimes true, such as where 'a' and 'b' have particular, known computations, such as a = (2 + 2) and b = (3 + 1), or in say the case where (a + c) = (b + c). So, I don't agree that every true statement is a tautology.
          – Doug Spoonwood
          Jul 30 at 18:50










        • @DougSpoonwood You have proposed a sentence which depends on outside values to be true or false. This kind of statement is fine. It is called a conditional statement. I stated, "a statement which is always true is a tautology." I will edit my answer to make the phrase you quoted part of the same sentence so it is more clear.
          – Joseph Myers
          Aug 3 at 23:17


















        up vote
        -2
        down vote













        Circular reasoning is when two statements depend on each other in order to be true (consistent with the model).



        • The inside angles of a triangles are supplementary

        • The co-interior angles of a line intersecting parallel lines are supplementary

        Both statements can be used to prove the other but neither of the above statements can be proven from the existing set of axioms in Geometry unless one of them is assumed as true without proof (an axiom). This "straightens" the argument so as to begin at this assumption. This is not fallacious at all unless it produces a contradiction with existing assumptions. It just limits or rather refines the set of statements that can follow as a logical consequences of the additional assumption.



        Alice's Argument that Mathematical Proofs are Circular can be understood as:



        • Each and every proof must be based on axioms.


        • Axioms implicitly contains all theses that can be proven from the set of axioms.


        To prove any one of these two statements will require the other one. This is circular. To "straighten" it we must assume one of the two to be true and the other can follow by the rules of inference/logic.



        Is Mathematics then a tautology? If you define a tautology as a system of statements that is true by necessity or by virtue of its logical form, then I think it unashamedly is, and has to be based on the rules of inference/logic and the assumption just made: Each and every proof must be based on axioms or restated: All theses must follow by the rules of inference (proof) from the set of axioms.



        Is Alice's argument valid that, in form, it is equivalent to that of axiomatic system of Mathematics? Is it consistent with the model produced by the assumption: all theses must follow by the rules of inference (proof) from the set of axioms.



        Proof by contradiction:
        Assumed it is true that a proof contains its thesis within its assumptions.



        Two situations,
        1) The thesis is an existing axiom (assumption without proof).



        If the thesis is an existing axiom, then of course her model is equivalent. A leads to A.



        2) The thesis is not an existing axiom (assumption without proof).



        If the thesis is not an existing axiom but it is an axiom because it is assumed without a proof, then is leads to a logical contradiction.



        Which means her proof is only valid if her thesis is indeed an existing axiom.



        Alice's solution:
        So if her argument is indeed circular, then her solution is to admit that one of the statements that she is making must be is an necessary assumption to develop the model/argument/worldview etc. Then it could be equivalent to the axiomatic system of Mathematics if it does not contradict any existing assumptions/axioms.






        share|cite|improve this answer





















          Your Answer




          StackExchange.ifUsing("editor", function ()
          return StackExchange.using("mathjaxEditing", function ()
          StackExchange.MarkdownEditor.creationCallbacks.add(function (editor, postfix)
          StackExchange.mathjaxEditing.prepareWmdForMathJax(editor, postfix, [["$", "$"], ["\\(","\\)"]]);
          );
          );
          , "mathjax-editing");

          StackExchange.ready(function()
          var channelOptions =
          tags: "".split(" "),
          id: "69"
          ;
          initTagRenderer("".split(" "), "".split(" "), channelOptions);

          StackExchange.using("externalEditor", function()
          // Have to fire editor after snippets, if snippets enabled
          if (StackExchange.settings.snippets.snippetsEnabled)
          StackExchange.using("snippets", function()
          createEditor();
          );

          else
          createEditor();

          );

          function createEditor()
          StackExchange.prepareEditor(
          heartbeatType: 'answer',
          convertImagesToLinks: true,
          noModals: false,
          showLowRepImageUploadWarning: true,
          reputationToPostImages: 10,
          bindNavPrevention: true,
          postfix: "",
          noCode: true, onDemand: true,
          discardSelector: ".discard-answer"
          ,immediatelyShowMarkdownHelp:true
          );



          );








           

          draft saved


          draft discarded


















          StackExchange.ready(
          function ()
          StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmath.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f2865677%2fwhat-exactly-is-circular-reasoning%23new-answer', 'question_page');

          );

          Post as a guest






























          10 Answers
          10






          active

          oldest

          votes








          10 Answers
          10






          active

          oldest

          votes









          active

          oldest

          votes






          active

          oldest

          votes








          up vote
          29
          down vote














          Of course my proof contains its thesis within its assumptions. Each and every proof must be based on axioms, which are assumptions that are not to be proved.




          Hold it right there, Alice. These specific axioms are to be accepted without proof but nothing else is. For anything that is true that is not one of these axioms, the role of proof must be to demonstrate that such a truth can be derived from these axioms and how it would be so derived.




          Thus each set of axioms implicite contains all thesis that can be proven from this set of axioms.




          Implicit. But the role of a proof is to make the implicit explicit. I can claim that Fermat's last theorem is true. That is a true statement. But merely claiming it is not the same as a proof. I can claim the axioms of mathematics imply Fermat's last theorem and that would be true. But that's still not a proof. To prove it, I must demonstrate how the axioms imply it. And in doing so I can not base any of my demonstration implications upon the knowledge that I know it to be true.




          As we know, each theorem in mathematics and logics is little more than a tautology:




          That's not actually what a tautology is. But I'll assume you mean a true statement.




          so is mine.




          No one cares if your statement is true. We care if you can demonstrate how it is true. You did not do that.






          share|cite|improve this answer



















          • 3




            To quote Google, a tautology (in logic) is "a statement that is true by necessity or by virtue of its logical form". That describes mathematics in a nutshell.
            – Theo Bendit
            Jul 29 at 3:49






          • 2




            "Thus each set of axioms implicite contains all thesis that can be proven from this set of axioms." No, that's not true. At least not if rules of inference are not axioms, and axioms are not rules of inference. Axioms don't imply anything at all without rules of inference.
            – Doug Spoonwood
            Jul 29 at 4:18










          • @DougSpoonwood I'd agree with that. But Alice wouldn't. Alice would say rules of inference and all potentially inferred statements (even those which haven't yet been inferred) are in the .... whatever it is that Alice is calling th body of math. This can be one way of looking at it, but it has nothing to do with proofs and how we know things are true or not. I'd say Alice is wrong but, I can't just say "she's stupid; ignore her"
            – fleablood
            Jul 29 at 5:06







          • 1




            @TheoBendit I think google isn't correct about that, or maybe they are using some colloquial definition. Most people who study formal logic use "tautology" to mean exactly that a statement is true under all possible assignments to the variables. What "all possible assignments" and "variables" means depends on the logic. So $a + b = b + a$ is a tautology in quantified arithmetic logic, but not if you are reasoning about strings with $+$ being string concatenation. $forall x. P(x) to P(x)$ is a tautology in First Order Logic, letting $P$ range over all possible relations.
            – DanielV
            Jul 30 at 0:18






          • 1




            In my head, $1+1= 2$ is the definition of $2$. Not a theorem, not an axiom. Simply stating that 'whenever I use the squggle "$2$", take that to be shorthand for "$1+1$"'.
            – Arthur
            Jul 30 at 9:31















          up vote
          29
          down vote














          Of course my proof contains its thesis within its assumptions. Each and every proof must be based on axioms, which are assumptions that are not to be proved.




          Hold it right there, Alice. These specific axioms are to be accepted without proof but nothing else is. For anything that is true that is not one of these axioms, the role of proof must be to demonstrate that such a truth can be derived from these axioms and how it would be so derived.




          Thus each set of axioms implicite contains all thesis that can be proven from this set of axioms.




          Implicit. But the role of a proof is to make the implicit explicit. I can claim that Fermat's last theorem is true. That is a true statement. But merely claiming it is not the same as a proof. I can claim the axioms of mathematics imply Fermat's last theorem and that would be true. But that's still not a proof. To prove it, I must demonstrate how the axioms imply it. And in doing so I can not base any of my demonstration implications upon the knowledge that I know it to be true.




          As we know, each theorem in mathematics and logics is little more than a tautology:




          That's not actually what a tautology is. But I'll assume you mean a true statement.




          so is mine.




          No one cares if your statement is true. We care if you can demonstrate how it is true. You did not do that.






          share|cite|improve this answer



















          • 3




            To quote Google, a tautology (in logic) is "a statement that is true by necessity or by virtue of its logical form". That describes mathematics in a nutshell.
            – Theo Bendit
            Jul 29 at 3:49






          • 2




            "Thus each set of axioms implicite contains all thesis that can be proven from this set of axioms." No, that's not true. At least not if rules of inference are not axioms, and axioms are not rules of inference. Axioms don't imply anything at all without rules of inference.
            – Doug Spoonwood
            Jul 29 at 4:18










          • @DougSpoonwood I'd agree with that. But Alice wouldn't. Alice would say rules of inference and all potentially inferred statements (even those which haven't yet been inferred) are in the .... whatever it is that Alice is calling th body of math. This can be one way of looking at it, but it has nothing to do with proofs and how we know things are true or not. I'd say Alice is wrong but, I can't just say "she's stupid; ignore her"
            – fleablood
            Jul 29 at 5:06







          • 1




            @TheoBendit I think google isn't correct about that, or maybe they are using some colloquial definition. Most people who study formal logic use "tautology" to mean exactly that a statement is true under all possible assignments to the variables. What "all possible assignments" and "variables" means depends on the logic. So $a + b = b + a$ is a tautology in quantified arithmetic logic, but not if you are reasoning about strings with $+$ being string concatenation. $forall x. P(x) to P(x)$ is a tautology in First Order Logic, letting $P$ range over all possible relations.
            – DanielV
            Jul 30 at 0:18






          • 1




            In my head, $1+1= 2$ is the definition of $2$. Not a theorem, not an axiom. Simply stating that 'whenever I use the squggle "$2$", take that to be shorthand for "$1+1$"'.
            – Arthur
            Jul 30 at 9:31













          up vote
          29
          down vote










          up vote
          29
          down vote










          Of course my proof contains its thesis within its assumptions. Each and every proof must be based on axioms, which are assumptions that are not to be proved.




          Hold it right there, Alice. These specific axioms are to be accepted without proof but nothing else is. For anything that is true that is not one of these axioms, the role of proof must be to demonstrate that such a truth can be derived from these axioms and how it would be so derived.




          Thus each set of axioms implicite contains all thesis that can be proven from this set of axioms.




          Implicit. But the role of a proof is to make the implicit explicit. I can claim that Fermat's last theorem is true. That is a true statement. But merely claiming it is not the same as a proof. I can claim the axioms of mathematics imply Fermat's last theorem and that would be true. But that's still not a proof. To prove it, I must demonstrate how the axioms imply it. And in doing so I can not base any of my demonstration implications upon the knowledge that I know it to be true.




          As we know, each theorem in mathematics and logics is little more than a tautology:




          That's not actually what a tautology is. But I'll assume you mean a true statement.




          so is mine.




          No one cares if your statement is true. We care if you can demonstrate how it is true. You did not do that.






          share|cite|improve this answer
















          Of course my proof contains its thesis within its assumptions. Each and every proof must be based on axioms, which are assumptions that are not to be proved.




          Hold it right there, Alice. These specific axioms are to be accepted without proof but nothing else is. For anything that is true that is not one of these axioms, the role of proof must be to demonstrate that such a truth can be derived from these axioms and how it would be so derived.




          Thus each set of axioms implicite contains all thesis that can be proven from this set of axioms.




          Implicit. But the role of a proof is to make the implicit explicit. I can claim that Fermat's last theorem is true. That is a true statement. But merely claiming it is not the same as a proof. I can claim the axioms of mathematics imply Fermat's last theorem and that would be true. But that's still not a proof. To prove it, I must demonstrate how the axioms imply it. And in doing so I can not base any of my demonstration implications upon the knowledge that I know it to be true.




          As we know, each theorem in mathematics and logics is little more than a tautology:




          That's not actually what a tautology is. But I'll assume you mean a true statement.




          so is mine.




          No one cares if your statement is true. We care if you can demonstrate how it is true. You did not do that.







          share|cite|improve this answer















          share|cite|improve this answer



          share|cite|improve this answer








          edited Jul 29 at 18:00









          Community♦

          1




          1











          answered Jul 29 at 2:28









          fleablood

          60.2k22575




          60.2k22575







          • 3




            To quote Google, a tautology (in logic) is "a statement that is true by necessity or by virtue of its logical form". That describes mathematics in a nutshell.
            – Theo Bendit
            Jul 29 at 3:49






          • 2




            "Thus each set of axioms implicite contains all thesis that can be proven from this set of axioms." No, that's not true. At least not if rules of inference are not axioms, and axioms are not rules of inference. Axioms don't imply anything at all without rules of inference.
            – Doug Spoonwood
            Jul 29 at 4:18










          • @DougSpoonwood I'd agree with that. But Alice wouldn't. Alice would say rules of inference and all potentially inferred statements (even those which haven't yet been inferred) are in the .... whatever it is that Alice is calling th body of math. This can be one way of looking at it, but it has nothing to do with proofs and how we know things are true or not. I'd say Alice is wrong but, I can't just say "she's stupid; ignore her"
            – fleablood
            Jul 29 at 5:06







          • 1




            @TheoBendit I think google isn't correct about that, or maybe they are using some colloquial definition. Most people who study formal logic use "tautology" to mean exactly that a statement is true under all possible assignments to the variables. What "all possible assignments" and "variables" means depends on the logic. So $a + b = b + a$ is a tautology in quantified arithmetic logic, but not if you are reasoning about strings with $+$ being string concatenation. $forall x. P(x) to P(x)$ is a tautology in First Order Logic, letting $P$ range over all possible relations.
            – DanielV
            Jul 30 at 0:18






          • 1




            In my head, $1+1= 2$ is the definition of $2$. Not a theorem, not an axiom. Simply stating that 'whenever I use the squggle "$2$", take that to be shorthand for "$1+1$"'.
            – Arthur
            Jul 30 at 9:31













          • 3




            To quote Google, a tautology (in logic) is "a statement that is true by necessity or by virtue of its logical form". That describes mathematics in a nutshell.
            – Theo Bendit
            Jul 29 at 3:49






          • 2




            "Thus each set of axioms implicite contains all thesis that can be proven from this set of axioms." No, that's not true. At least not if rules of inference are not axioms, and axioms are not rules of inference. Axioms don't imply anything at all without rules of inference.
            – Doug Spoonwood
            Jul 29 at 4:18










          • @DougSpoonwood I'd agree with that. But Alice wouldn't. Alice would say rules of inference and all potentially inferred statements (even those which haven't yet been inferred) are in the .... whatever it is that Alice is calling th body of math. This can be one way of looking at it, but it has nothing to do with proofs and how we know things are true or not. I'd say Alice is wrong but, I can't just say "she's stupid; ignore her"
            – fleablood
            Jul 29 at 5:06







          • 1




            @TheoBendit I think google isn't correct about that, or maybe they are using some colloquial definition. Most people who study formal logic use "tautology" to mean exactly that a statement is true under all possible assignments to the variables. What "all possible assignments" and "variables" means depends on the logic. So $a + b = b + a$ is a tautology in quantified arithmetic logic, but not if you are reasoning about strings with $+$ being string concatenation. $forall x. P(x) to P(x)$ is a tautology in First Order Logic, letting $P$ range over all possible relations.
            – DanielV
            Jul 30 at 0:18






          • 1




            In my head, $1+1= 2$ is the definition of $2$. Not a theorem, not an axiom. Simply stating that 'whenever I use the squggle "$2$", take that to be shorthand for "$1+1$"'.
            – Arthur
            Jul 30 at 9:31








          3




          3




          To quote Google, a tautology (in logic) is "a statement that is true by necessity or by virtue of its logical form". That describes mathematics in a nutshell.
          – Theo Bendit
          Jul 29 at 3:49




          To quote Google, a tautology (in logic) is "a statement that is true by necessity or by virtue of its logical form". That describes mathematics in a nutshell.
          – Theo Bendit
          Jul 29 at 3:49




          2




          2




          "Thus each set of axioms implicite contains all thesis that can be proven from this set of axioms." No, that's not true. At least not if rules of inference are not axioms, and axioms are not rules of inference. Axioms don't imply anything at all without rules of inference.
          – Doug Spoonwood
          Jul 29 at 4:18




          "Thus each set of axioms implicite contains all thesis that can be proven from this set of axioms." No, that's not true. At least not if rules of inference are not axioms, and axioms are not rules of inference. Axioms don't imply anything at all without rules of inference.
          – Doug Spoonwood
          Jul 29 at 4:18












          @DougSpoonwood I'd agree with that. But Alice wouldn't. Alice would say rules of inference and all potentially inferred statements (even those which haven't yet been inferred) are in the .... whatever it is that Alice is calling th body of math. This can be one way of looking at it, but it has nothing to do with proofs and how we know things are true or not. I'd say Alice is wrong but, I can't just say "she's stupid; ignore her"
          – fleablood
          Jul 29 at 5:06





          @DougSpoonwood I'd agree with that. But Alice wouldn't. Alice would say rules of inference and all potentially inferred statements (even those which haven't yet been inferred) are in the .... whatever it is that Alice is calling th body of math. This can be one way of looking at it, but it has nothing to do with proofs and how we know things are true or not. I'd say Alice is wrong but, I can't just say "she's stupid; ignore her"
          – fleablood
          Jul 29 at 5:06





          1




          1




          @TheoBendit I think google isn't correct about that, or maybe they are using some colloquial definition. Most people who study formal logic use "tautology" to mean exactly that a statement is true under all possible assignments to the variables. What "all possible assignments" and "variables" means depends on the logic. So $a + b = b + a$ is a tautology in quantified arithmetic logic, but not if you are reasoning about strings with $+$ being string concatenation. $forall x. P(x) to P(x)$ is a tautology in First Order Logic, letting $P$ range over all possible relations.
          – DanielV
          Jul 30 at 0:18




          @TheoBendit I think google isn't correct about that, or maybe they are using some colloquial definition. Most people who study formal logic use "tautology" to mean exactly that a statement is true under all possible assignments to the variables. What "all possible assignments" and "variables" means depends on the logic. So $a + b = b + a$ is a tautology in quantified arithmetic logic, but not if you are reasoning about strings with $+$ being string concatenation. $forall x. P(x) to P(x)$ is a tautology in First Order Logic, letting $P$ range over all possible relations.
          – DanielV
          Jul 30 at 0:18




          1




          1




          In my head, $1+1= 2$ is the definition of $2$. Not a theorem, not an axiom. Simply stating that 'whenever I use the squggle "$2$", take that to be shorthand for "$1+1$"'.
          – Arthur
          Jul 30 at 9:31





          In my head, $1+1= 2$ is the definition of $2$. Not a theorem, not an axiom. Simply stating that 'whenever I use the squggle "$2$", take that to be shorthand for "$1+1$"'.
          – Arthur
          Jul 30 at 9:31











          up vote
          10
          down vote













          I believe this has a simple resolution:



          When we say informally that Alice is required to prove a result, it is sloppy language; she is actually required to prove the implication axioms $implies$ result. So of course, she can have the axioms in her premises. However, she cannon have axioms $implies$ result as one of her premises; that would be circular reasoning.






          share|cite|improve this answer





















          • Are you defining circular reasoning, as making a statement that a certain conclusion (result) follows from a set of axioms, without proof?
            – Pieter Rousseau
            Jul 30 at 6:45










          • @PieterRousseau I would say yes, at least as a practical definition that we use informally. However, if you back me into a corner, I would retreat to saying that a circular argument is any argument which has anything else other than axioms as premises (I would have to phrase it much more carefully m of course since that definition clearly encompasses more arguments than just the ones we would like to call circular.
            – Ovi
            Jul 30 at 7:48











          • " she is actually required to prove the implication axioms ⟹ result. " For clarification, you're saying that basically Alice has to show "axioms $vdash$ result" instead of "$vdash$ (axioms $rightarrow$ result)", correct? Also, you said "However, she cannon..." I think you meant 'cannot'... though maybe Alice is a cannon shrugs and laughs.
            – Doug Spoonwood
            Jul 30 at 7:52











          • @Ovi. Thanks for the clarification, I think I can agree with your more formal definition, because the premise (axioms ⟹ result) without proof is simply that: an unproven premise, nothing circular (I think). Unless I really misunderstood your answer.
            – Pieter Rousseau
            Jul 30 at 8:19










          • @DougSpoonwood Yes, I think so. I'm just a student so honestly I wasn't even familiar with the sideways T. I looked it up and it seems to mean "RHS is provable from LHS", but then I'm not sure what just "$vdash P$ means without a LHS
            – Ovi
            Jul 30 at 9:42














          up vote
          10
          down vote













          I believe this has a simple resolution:



          When we say informally that Alice is required to prove a result, it is sloppy language; she is actually required to prove the implication axioms $implies$ result. So of course, she can have the axioms in her premises. However, she cannon have axioms $implies$ result as one of her premises; that would be circular reasoning.






          share|cite|improve this answer





















          • Are you defining circular reasoning, as making a statement that a certain conclusion (result) follows from a set of axioms, without proof?
            – Pieter Rousseau
            Jul 30 at 6:45










          • @PieterRousseau I would say yes, at least as a practical definition that we use informally. However, if you back me into a corner, I would retreat to saying that a circular argument is any argument which has anything else other than axioms as premises (I would have to phrase it much more carefully m of course since that definition clearly encompasses more arguments than just the ones we would like to call circular.
            – Ovi
            Jul 30 at 7:48











          • " she is actually required to prove the implication axioms ⟹ result. " For clarification, you're saying that basically Alice has to show "axioms $vdash$ result" instead of "$vdash$ (axioms $rightarrow$ result)", correct? Also, you said "However, she cannon..." I think you meant 'cannot'... though maybe Alice is a cannon shrugs and laughs.
            – Doug Spoonwood
            Jul 30 at 7:52











          • @Ovi. Thanks for the clarification, I think I can agree with your more formal definition, because the premise (axioms ⟹ result) without proof is simply that: an unproven premise, nothing circular (I think). Unless I really misunderstood your answer.
            – Pieter Rousseau
            Jul 30 at 8:19










          • @DougSpoonwood Yes, I think so. I'm just a student so honestly I wasn't even familiar with the sideways T. I looked it up and it seems to mean "RHS is provable from LHS", but then I'm not sure what just "$vdash P$ means without a LHS
            – Ovi
            Jul 30 at 9:42












          up vote
          10
          down vote










          up vote
          10
          down vote









          I believe this has a simple resolution:



          When we say informally that Alice is required to prove a result, it is sloppy language; she is actually required to prove the implication axioms $implies$ result. So of course, she can have the axioms in her premises. However, she cannon have axioms $implies$ result as one of her premises; that would be circular reasoning.






          share|cite|improve this answer













          I believe this has a simple resolution:



          When we say informally that Alice is required to prove a result, it is sloppy language; she is actually required to prove the implication axioms $implies$ result. So of course, she can have the axioms in her premises. However, she cannon have axioms $implies$ result as one of her premises; that would be circular reasoning.







          share|cite|improve this answer













          share|cite|improve this answer



          share|cite|improve this answer











          answered Jul 29 at 6:00









          Ovi

          11.3k935105




          11.3k935105











          • Are you defining circular reasoning, as making a statement that a certain conclusion (result) follows from a set of axioms, without proof?
            – Pieter Rousseau
            Jul 30 at 6:45










          • @PieterRousseau I would say yes, at least as a practical definition that we use informally. However, if you back me into a corner, I would retreat to saying that a circular argument is any argument which has anything else other than axioms as premises (I would have to phrase it much more carefully m of course since that definition clearly encompasses more arguments than just the ones we would like to call circular.
            – Ovi
            Jul 30 at 7:48











          • " she is actually required to prove the implication axioms ⟹ result. " For clarification, you're saying that basically Alice has to show "axioms $vdash$ result" instead of "$vdash$ (axioms $rightarrow$ result)", correct? Also, you said "However, she cannon..." I think you meant 'cannot'... though maybe Alice is a cannon shrugs and laughs.
            – Doug Spoonwood
            Jul 30 at 7:52











          • @Ovi. Thanks for the clarification, I think I can agree with your more formal definition, because the premise (axioms ⟹ result) without proof is simply that: an unproven premise, nothing circular (I think). Unless I really misunderstood your answer.
            – Pieter Rousseau
            Jul 30 at 8:19










          • @DougSpoonwood Yes, I think so. I'm just a student so honestly I wasn't even familiar with the sideways T. I looked it up and it seems to mean "RHS is provable from LHS", but then I'm not sure what just "$vdash P$ means without a LHS
            – Ovi
            Jul 30 at 9:42
















          • Are you defining circular reasoning, as making a statement that a certain conclusion (result) follows from a set of axioms, without proof?
            – Pieter Rousseau
            Jul 30 at 6:45










          • @PieterRousseau I would say yes, at least as a practical definition that we use informally. However, if you back me into a corner, I would retreat to saying that a circular argument is any argument which has anything else other than axioms as premises (I would have to phrase it much more carefully m of course since that definition clearly encompasses more arguments than just the ones we would like to call circular.
            – Ovi
            Jul 30 at 7:48











          • " she is actually required to prove the implication axioms ⟹ result. " For clarification, you're saying that basically Alice has to show "axioms $vdash$ result" instead of "$vdash$ (axioms $rightarrow$ result)", correct? Also, you said "However, she cannon..." I think you meant 'cannot'... though maybe Alice is a cannon shrugs and laughs.
            – Doug Spoonwood
            Jul 30 at 7:52











          • @Ovi. Thanks for the clarification, I think I can agree with your more formal definition, because the premise (axioms ⟹ result) without proof is simply that: an unproven premise, nothing circular (I think). Unless I really misunderstood your answer.
            – Pieter Rousseau
            Jul 30 at 8:19










          • @DougSpoonwood Yes, I think so. I'm just a student so honestly I wasn't even familiar with the sideways T. I looked it up and it seems to mean "RHS is provable from LHS", but then I'm not sure what just "$vdash P$ means without a LHS
            – Ovi
            Jul 30 at 9:42















          Are you defining circular reasoning, as making a statement that a certain conclusion (result) follows from a set of axioms, without proof?
          – Pieter Rousseau
          Jul 30 at 6:45




          Are you defining circular reasoning, as making a statement that a certain conclusion (result) follows from a set of axioms, without proof?
          – Pieter Rousseau
          Jul 30 at 6:45












          @PieterRousseau I would say yes, at least as a practical definition that we use informally. However, if you back me into a corner, I would retreat to saying that a circular argument is any argument which has anything else other than axioms as premises (I would have to phrase it much more carefully m of course since that definition clearly encompasses more arguments than just the ones we would like to call circular.
          – Ovi
          Jul 30 at 7:48





          @PieterRousseau I would say yes, at least as a practical definition that we use informally. However, if you back me into a corner, I would retreat to saying that a circular argument is any argument which has anything else other than axioms as premises (I would have to phrase it much more carefully m of course since that definition clearly encompasses more arguments than just the ones we would like to call circular.
          – Ovi
          Jul 30 at 7:48













          " she is actually required to prove the implication axioms ⟹ result. " For clarification, you're saying that basically Alice has to show "axioms $vdash$ result" instead of "$vdash$ (axioms $rightarrow$ result)", correct? Also, you said "However, she cannon..." I think you meant 'cannot'... though maybe Alice is a cannon shrugs and laughs.
          – Doug Spoonwood
          Jul 30 at 7:52





          " she is actually required to prove the implication axioms ⟹ result. " For clarification, you're saying that basically Alice has to show "axioms $vdash$ result" instead of "$vdash$ (axioms $rightarrow$ result)", correct? Also, you said "However, she cannon..." I think you meant 'cannot'... though maybe Alice is a cannon shrugs and laughs.
          – Doug Spoonwood
          Jul 30 at 7:52













          @Ovi. Thanks for the clarification, I think I can agree with your more formal definition, because the premise (axioms ⟹ result) without proof is simply that: an unproven premise, nothing circular (I think). Unless I really misunderstood your answer.
          – Pieter Rousseau
          Jul 30 at 8:19




          @Ovi. Thanks for the clarification, I think I can agree with your more formal definition, because the premise (axioms ⟹ result) without proof is simply that: an unproven premise, nothing circular (I think). Unless I really misunderstood your answer.
          – Pieter Rousseau
          Jul 30 at 8:19












          @DougSpoonwood Yes, I think so. I'm just a student so honestly I wasn't even familiar with the sideways T. I looked it up and it seems to mean "RHS is provable from LHS", but then I'm not sure what just "$vdash P$ means without a LHS
          – Ovi
          Jul 30 at 9:42




          @DougSpoonwood Yes, I think so. I'm just a student so honestly I wasn't even familiar with the sideways T. I looked it up and it seems to mean "RHS is provable from LHS", but then I'm not sure what just "$vdash P$ means without a LHS
          – Ovi
          Jul 30 at 9:42










          up vote
          10
          down vote













          All reasoning (whether formal or informal, mathematical, scientific, every-day-life, etc.) needs to satisfy two basic criteria in order to be considered good (sound) reasoning:



          1. The steps in the argument need to be logical (valid .. the conclusion follows from the premises)


          2. The assumptions (premises) need to be acceptable (true or at least agreed upon by the parties involved in the debate within which the argument is offered)


          Now, what Alice is pointing out is that in the domain of deductive reasoning (which includes mathematical reasoning), the information contained in the conclusion is already contained in the premises ... in a way, the conclusion thus 'merely' pulls this out. .. Alice thus seems to be saying: "all mathematical reasoning is circular .. so why attack my argument on being circular?"



          However, this is not a good defense against the charge of circular reasoning. First of all, there is a big difference between 'pulling out', say, some complicated theorem of arithmetic out of the Peano Axioms on the one hand, and simply assuming that very theorem as an assumption proven on the other:



          In the former scenario, contrary to Alice's claim, we really do not say that circular reasoning is taking place: as long as the assumptions of the argument are nothing more than the agreed upon Peano Axioms, and as long as each inference leading up the the theorem is logically valid, then such an argument satisfied the two forementioned criteria, and is therefore perfectly acceptable.



          In the latter case, however, circular reasoning is taking place: if all we agreed upon were the Peano axioms, but if the argument uses the conclusion (which is not part of those axioms) as an assumption, then that argument violates the second criterion. It can be said to 'beg the question' ... as it 'begs' the answer to the very question (is the theorem true?) we had in the first place.






          share|cite|improve this answer























          • "Alice is correct that every proof relies on a set of axioms to which Alice and Bob have to agree beforehand." Alice said: "As we know, each theorem in mathematics and logics is little more than a tautology" Since she says all theorems are contained in the axioms, it seems that she would say that all axioms are tautologies. But, natural deduction proofs exist which don't use any tautologies at all, nor any axioms. Why need Alice and Bob agree on axioms instead of using a pure natural deduction system?
            – Doug Spoonwood
            Jul 29 at 5:45







          • 1




            @DougSpoonwood, while your point is quite sensible in non-mathematical contexts, the mathematical answer is: natural deductions from what? Whatever starting point for reasoning that you have, must, from a mathematical standpoint, be an assumption. (In logical reasoning applied to life this is not so: your starting point can be an assumption, or a concrete observation. Mathematics has no concrete observations not based on other assumptions.)
            – Wildcard
            Jul 29 at 8:26






          • 1




            @DougSpoonwood Natural deduction systems tend to minimize or even eliminate logical axioms. The non-logical axioms that discuss the actual domain subject matter, e.g. real numbers, remain unless you go full type theory. In that latter case (and the former case to a lesser extent), instead of agreeing about axioms, you have to agree on what constitutes a valid rule of inference/construction. At any rate, the (usual, semantic) definition of "tautology" doesn't depend on the deductive system.
            – Derek Elkins
            Jul 29 at 22:48










          • I feel it's important (albeit probably obvious) to note that, while we mustn't use our thesis as assumption in our proof, we must assume the negation of our thesis if we want to proof our thesis via contradiction.
            – Sudix
            Jul 29 at 23:10











          • It seems to me though that in defining good reasoning, you are using good reasoning. Is this not circular?
            – Pieter Rousseau
            Jul 30 at 6:35














          up vote
          10
          down vote













          All reasoning (whether formal or informal, mathematical, scientific, every-day-life, etc.) needs to satisfy two basic criteria in order to be considered good (sound) reasoning:



          1. The steps in the argument need to be logical (valid .. the conclusion follows from the premises)


          2. The assumptions (premises) need to be acceptable (true or at least agreed upon by the parties involved in the debate within which the argument is offered)


          Now, what Alice is pointing out is that in the domain of deductive reasoning (which includes mathematical reasoning), the information contained in the conclusion is already contained in the premises ... in a way, the conclusion thus 'merely' pulls this out. .. Alice thus seems to be saying: "all mathematical reasoning is circular .. so why attack my argument on being circular?"



          However, this is not a good defense against the charge of circular reasoning. First of all, there is a big difference between 'pulling out', say, some complicated theorem of arithmetic out of the Peano Axioms on the one hand, and simply assuming that very theorem as an assumption proven on the other:



          In the former scenario, contrary to Alice's claim, we really do not say that circular reasoning is taking place: as long as the assumptions of the argument are nothing more than the agreed upon Peano Axioms, and as long as each inference leading up the the theorem is logically valid, then such an argument satisfied the two forementioned criteria, and is therefore perfectly acceptable.



          In the latter case, however, circular reasoning is taking place: if all we agreed upon were the Peano axioms, but if the argument uses the conclusion (which is not part of those axioms) as an assumption, then that argument violates the second criterion. It can be said to 'beg the question' ... as it 'begs' the answer to the very question (is the theorem true?) we had in the first place.






          share|cite|improve this answer























          • "Alice is correct that every proof relies on a set of axioms to which Alice and Bob have to agree beforehand." Alice said: "As we know, each theorem in mathematics and logics is little more than a tautology" Since she says all theorems are contained in the axioms, it seems that she would say that all axioms are tautologies. But, natural deduction proofs exist which don't use any tautologies at all, nor any axioms. Why need Alice and Bob agree on axioms instead of using a pure natural deduction system?
            – Doug Spoonwood
            Jul 29 at 5:45







          • 1




            @DougSpoonwood, while your point is quite sensible in non-mathematical contexts, the mathematical answer is: natural deductions from what? Whatever starting point for reasoning that you have, must, from a mathematical standpoint, be an assumption. (In logical reasoning applied to life this is not so: your starting point can be an assumption, or a concrete observation. Mathematics has no concrete observations not based on other assumptions.)
            – Wildcard
            Jul 29 at 8:26






          • 1




            @DougSpoonwood Natural deduction systems tend to minimize or even eliminate logical axioms. The non-logical axioms that discuss the actual domain subject matter, e.g. real numbers, remain unless you go full type theory. In that latter case (and the former case to a lesser extent), instead of agreeing about axioms, you have to agree on what constitutes a valid rule of inference/construction. At any rate, the (usual, semantic) definition of "tautology" doesn't depend on the deductive system.
            – Derek Elkins
            Jul 29 at 22:48










          • I feel it's important (albeit probably obvious) to note that, while we mustn't use our thesis as assumption in our proof, we must assume the negation of our thesis if we want to proof our thesis via contradiction.
            – Sudix
            Jul 29 at 23:10











          • It seems to me though that in defining good reasoning, you are using good reasoning. Is this not circular?
            – Pieter Rousseau
            Jul 30 at 6:35












          up vote
          10
          down vote










          up vote
          10
          down vote









          All reasoning (whether formal or informal, mathematical, scientific, every-day-life, etc.) needs to satisfy two basic criteria in order to be considered good (sound) reasoning:



          1. The steps in the argument need to be logical (valid .. the conclusion follows from the premises)


          2. The assumptions (premises) need to be acceptable (true or at least agreed upon by the parties involved in the debate within which the argument is offered)


          Now, what Alice is pointing out is that in the domain of deductive reasoning (which includes mathematical reasoning), the information contained in the conclusion is already contained in the premises ... in a way, the conclusion thus 'merely' pulls this out. .. Alice thus seems to be saying: "all mathematical reasoning is circular .. so why attack my argument on being circular?"



          However, this is not a good defense against the charge of circular reasoning. First of all, there is a big difference between 'pulling out', say, some complicated theorem of arithmetic out of the Peano Axioms on the one hand, and simply assuming that very theorem as an assumption proven on the other:



          In the former scenario, contrary to Alice's claim, we really do not say that circular reasoning is taking place: as long as the assumptions of the argument are nothing more than the agreed upon Peano Axioms, and as long as each inference leading up the the theorem is logically valid, then such an argument satisfied the two forementioned criteria, and is therefore perfectly acceptable.



          In the latter case, however, circular reasoning is taking place: if all we agreed upon were the Peano axioms, but if the argument uses the conclusion (which is not part of those axioms) as an assumption, then that argument violates the second criterion. It can be said to 'beg the question' ... as it 'begs' the answer to the very question (is the theorem true?) we had in the first place.






          share|cite|improve this answer















          All reasoning (whether formal or informal, mathematical, scientific, every-day-life, etc.) needs to satisfy two basic criteria in order to be considered good (sound) reasoning:



          1. The steps in the argument need to be logical (valid .. the conclusion follows from the premises)


          2. The assumptions (premises) need to be acceptable (true or at least agreed upon by the parties involved in the debate within which the argument is offered)


          Now, what Alice is pointing out is that in the domain of deductive reasoning (which includes mathematical reasoning), the information contained in the conclusion is already contained in the premises ... in a way, the conclusion thus 'merely' pulls this out. .. Alice thus seems to be saying: "all mathematical reasoning is circular .. so why attack my argument on being circular?"



          However, this is not a good defense against the charge of circular reasoning. First of all, there is a big difference between 'pulling out', say, some complicated theorem of arithmetic out of the Peano Axioms on the one hand, and simply assuming that very theorem as an assumption proven on the other:



          In the former scenario, contrary to Alice's claim, we really do not say that circular reasoning is taking place: as long as the assumptions of the argument are nothing more than the agreed upon Peano Axioms, and as long as each inference leading up the the theorem is logically valid, then such an argument satisfied the two forementioned criteria, and is therefore perfectly acceptable.



          In the latter case, however, circular reasoning is taking place: if all we agreed upon were the Peano axioms, but if the argument uses the conclusion (which is not part of those axioms) as an assumption, then that argument violates the second criterion. It can be said to 'beg the question' ... as it 'begs' the answer to the very question (is the theorem true?) we had in the first place.







          share|cite|improve this answer















          share|cite|improve this answer



          share|cite|improve this answer








          edited Jul 29 at 14:42


























          answered Jul 29 at 1:17









          Bram28

          54.8k33881




          54.8k33881











          • "Alice is correct that every proof relies on a set of axioms to which Alice and Bob have to agree beforehand." Alice said: "As we know, each theorem in mathematics and logics is little more than a tautology" Since she says all theorems are contained in the axioms, it seems that she would say that all axioms are tautologies. But, natural deduction proofs exist which don't use any tautologies at all, nor any axioms. Why need Alice and Bob agree on axioms instead of using a pure natural deduction system?
            – Doug Spoonwood
            Jul 29 at 5:45







          • 1




            @DougSpoonwood, while your point is quite sensible in non-mathematical contexts, the mathematical answer is: natural deductions from what? Whatever starting point for reasoning that you have, must, from a mathematical standpoint, be an assumption. (In logical reasoning applied to life this is not so: your starting point can be an assumption, or a concrete observation. Mathematics has no concrete observations not based on other assumptions.)
            – Wildcard
            Jul 29 at 8:26






          • 1




            @DougSpoonwood Natural deduction systems tend to minimize or even eliminate logical axioms. The non-logical axioms that discuss the actual domain subject matter, e.g. real numbers, remain unless you go full type theory. In that latter case (and the former case to a lesser extent), instead of agreeing about axioms, you have to agree on what constitutes a valid rule of inference/construction. At any rate, the (usual, semantic) definition of "tautology" doesn't depend on the deductive system.
            – Derek Elkins
            Jul 29 at 22:48










          • I feel it's important (albeit probably obvious) to note that, while we mustn't use our thesis as assumption in our proof, we must assume the negation of our thesis if we want to proof our thesis via contradiction.
            – Sudix
            Jul 29 at 23:10











          • It seems to me though that in defining good reasoning, you are using good reasoning. Is this not circular?
            – Pieter Rousseau
            Jul 30 at 6:35
















          • "Alice is correct that every proof relies on a set of axioms to which Alice and Bob have to agree beforehand." Alice said: "As we know, each theorem in mathematics and logics is little more than a tautology" Since she says all theorems are contained in the axioms, it seems that she would say that all axioms are tautologies. But, natural deduction proofs exist which don't use any tautologies at all, nor any axioms. Why need Alice and Bob agree on axioms instead of using a pure natural deduction system?
            – Doug Spoonwood
            Jul 29 at 5:45







          • 1




            @DougSpoonwood, while your point is quite sensible in non-mathematical contexts, the mathematical answer is: natural deductions from what? Whatever starting point for reasoning that you have, must, from a mathematical standpoint, be an assumption. (In logical reasoning applied to life this is not so: your starting point can be an assumption, or a concrete observation. Mathematics has no concrete observations not based on other assumptions.)
            – Wildcard
            Jul 29 at 8:26






          • 1




            @DougSpoonwood Natural deduction systems tend to minimize or even eliminate logical axioms. The non-logical axioms that discuss the actual domain subject matter, e.g. real numbers, remain unless you go full type theory. In that latter case (and the former case to a lesser extent), instead of agreeing about axioms, you have to agree on what constitutes a valid rule of inference/construction. At any rate, the (usual, semantic) definition of "tautology" doesn't depend on the deductive system.
            – Derek Elkins
            Jul 29 at 22:48










          • I feel it's important (albeit probably obvious) to note that, while we mustn't use our thesis as assumption in our proof, we must assume the negation of our thesis if we want to proof our thesis via contradiction.
            – Sudix
            Jul 29 at 23:10











          • It seems to me though that in defining good reasoning, you are using good reasoning. Is this not circular?
            – Pieter Rousseau
            Jul 30 at 6:35















          "Alice is correct that every proof relies on a set of axioms to which Alice and Bob have to agree beforehand." Alice said: "As we know, each theorem in mathematics and logics is little more than a tautology" Since she says all theorems are contained in the axioms, it seems that she would say that all axioms are tautologies. But, natural deduction proofs exist which don't use any tautologies at all, nor any axioms. Why need Alice and Bob agree on axioms instead of using a pure natural deduction system?
          – Doug Spoonwood
          Jul 29 at 5:45





          "Alice is correct that every proof relies on a set of axioms to which Alice and Bob have to agree beforehand." Alice said: "As we know, each theorem in mathematics and logics is little more than a tautology" Since she says all theorems are contained in the axioms, it seems that she would say that all axioms are tautologies. But, natural deduction proofs exist which don't use any tautologies at all, nor any axioms. Why need Alice and Bob agree on axioms instead of using a pure natural deduction system?
          – Doug Spoonwood
          Jul 29 at 5:45





          1




          1




          @DougSpoonwood, while your point is quite sensible in non-mathematical contexts, the mathematical answer is: natural deductions from what? Whatever starting point for reasoning that you have, must, from a mathematical standpoint, be an assumption. (In logical reasoning applied to life this is not so: your starting point can be an assumption, or a concrete observation. Mathematics has no concrete observations not based on other assumptions.)
          – Wildcard
          Jul 29 at 8:26




          @DougSpoonwood, while your point is quite sensible in non-mathematical contexts, the mathematical answer is: natural deductions from what? Whatever starting point for reasoning that you have, must, from a mathematical standpoint, be an assumption. (In logical reasoning applied to life this is not so: your starting point can be an assumption, or a concrete observation. Mathematics has no concrete observations not based on other assumptions.)
          – Wildcard
          Jul 29 at 8:26




          1




          1




          @DougSpoonwood Natural deduction systems tend to minimize or even eliminate logical axioms. The non-logical axioms that discuss the actual domain subject matter, e.g. real numbers, remain unless you go full type theory. In that latter case (and the former case to a lesser extent), instead of agreeing about axioms, you have to agree on what constitutes a valid rule of inference/construction. At any rate, the (usual, semantic) definition of "tautology" doesn't depend on the deductive system.
          – Derek Elkins
          Jul 29 at 22:48




          @DougSpoonwood Natural deduction systems tend to minimize or even eliminate logical axioms. The non-logical axioms that discuss the actual domain subject matter, e.g. real numbers, remain unless you go full type theory. In that latter case (and the former case to a lesser extent), instead of agreeing about axioms, you have to agree on what constitutes a valid rule of inference/construction. At any rate, the (usual, semantic) definition of "tautology" doesn't depend on the deductive system.
          – Derek Elkins
          Jul 29 at 22:48












          I feel it's important (albeit probably obvious) to note that, while we mustn't use our thesis as assumption in our proof, we must assume the negation of our thesis if we want to proof our thesis via contradiction.
          – Sudix
          Jul 29 at 23:10





          I feel it's important (albeit probably obvious) to note that, while we mustn't use our thesis as assumption in our proof, we must assume the negation of our thesis if we want to proof our thesis via contradiction.
          – Sudix
          Jul 29 at 23:10













          It seems to me though that in defining good reasoning, you are using good reasoning. Is this not circular?
          – Pieter Rousseau
          Jul 30 at 6:35




          It seems to me though that in defining good reasoning, you are using good reasoning. Is this not circular?
          – Pieter Rousseau
          Jul 30 at 6:35










          up vote
          5
          down vote













          The fallacious version of circular reasoning is an appeal to the proposition



          $$(A to A) to A tagC$$



          That is, to establish a proposition $A$ from no premises, you first establish the proposition $A$ under an assumption of $A$. Example:



          • Accuser: "You stole that."

          • Defendant: "No I didn't, it was mine."

          • Accuser: "It couldn't have been yours because you can't steal something you own."

          In that case the accuser is correct as far as pointing out that "stealing" implies "not yours" which implies "stealing", the $A to A$ part, but the fallacy comes from dropping the assumption and concluding "stealing" under no assumptions, which is the final $to A$.



          Guessing what Bob's side of the argument was : "Because the semantic meaning of a theorem is contained in the semantic meaning of the assumptions, you used circular reasoning". Here Bob is making 2 mistakes. First, he is equating circular reasoning with the proposition $A to A$. But that isn't what circular reasoning is, because $A to A$ always holds, how can you object to that?



          Second, he is not addressing the argument that Alice made. Even if $(A to A) to A$ (for her specific claim) applies to the assumptions and conclusions of her argument: unless she appealed to that theorem as an inference, she hasn't made any mistake. $(A to A) to A$ does hold in the case that $A$ itself is provable, such as when $A$ is a tautology. Observing this isn't deductively equivalent to assuming $(A to A) to A$ holds in all cases and using that as an inference.






          share|cite|improve this answer

























            up vote
            5
            down vote













            The fallacious version of circular reasoning is an appeal to the proposition



            $$(A to A) to A tagC$$



            That is, to establish a proposition $A$ from no premises, you first establish the proposition $A$ under an assumption of $A$. Example:



            • Accuser: "You stole that."

            • Defendant: "No I didn't, it was mine."

            • Accuser: "It couldn't have been yours because you can't steal something you own."

            In that case the accuser is correct as far as pointing out that "stealing" implies "not yours" which implies "stealing", the $A to A$ part, but the fallacy comes from dropping the assumption and concluding "stealing" under no assumptions, which is the final $to A$.



            Guessing what Bob's side of the argument was : "Because the semantic meaning of a theorem is contained in the semantic meaning of the assumptions, you used circular reasoning". Here Bob is making 2 mistakes. First, he is equating circular reasoning with the proposition $A to A$. But that isn't what circular reasoning is, because $A to A$ always holds, how can you object to that?



            Second, he is not addressing the argument that Alice made. Even if $(A to A) to A$ (for her specific claim) applies to the assumptions and conclusions of her argument: unless she appealed to that theorem as an inference, she hasn't made any mistake. $(A to A) to A$ does hold in the case that $A$ itself is provable, such as when $A$ is a tautology. Observing this isn't deductively equivalent to assuming $(A to A) to A$ holds in all cases and using that as an inference.






            share|cite|improve this answer























              up vote
              5
              down vote










              up vote
              5
              down vote









              The fallacious version of circular reasoning is an appeal to the proposition



              $$(A to A) to A tagC$$



              That is, to establish a proposition $A$ from no premises, you first establish the proposition $A$ under an assumption of $A$. Example:



              • Accuser: "You stole that."

              • Defendant: "No I didn't, it was mine."

              • Accuser: "It couldn't have been yours because you can't steal something you own."

              In that case the accuser is correct as far as pointing out that "stealing" implies "not yours" which implies "stealing", the $A to A$ part, but the fallacy comes from dropping the assumption and concluding "stealing" under no assumptions, which is the final $to A$.



              Guessing what Bob's side of the argument was : "Because the semantic meaning of a theorem is contained in the semantic meaning of the assumptions, you used circular reasoning". Here Bob is making 2 mistakes. First, he is equating circular reasoning with the proposition $A to A$. But that isn't what circular reasoning is, because $A to A$ always holds, how can you object to that?



              Second, he is not addressing the argument that Alice made. Even if $(A to A) to A$ (for her specific claim) applies to the assumptions and conclusions of her argument: unless she appealed to that theorem as an inference, she hasn't made any mistake. $(A to A) to A$ does hold in the case that $A$ itself is provable, such as when $A$ is a tautology. Observing this isn't deductively equivalent to assuming $(A to A) to A$ holds in all cases and using that as an inference.






              share|cite|improve this answer













              The fallacious version of circular reasoning is an appeal to the proposition



              $$(A to A) to A tagC$$



              That is, to establish a proposition $A$ from no premises, you first establish the proposition $A$ under an assumption of $A$. Example:



              • Accuser: "You stole that."

              • Defendant: "No I didn't, it was mine."

              • Accuser: "It couldn't have been yours because you can't steal something you own."

              In that case the accuser is correct as far as pointing out that "stealing" implies "not yours" which implies "stealing", the $A to A$ part, but the fallacy comes from dropping the assumption and concluding "stealing" under no assumptions, which is the final $to A$.



              Guessing what Bob's side of the argument was : "Because the semantic meaning of a theorem is contained in the semantic meaning of the assumptions, you used circular reasoning". Here Bob is making 2 mistakes. First, he is equating circular reasoning with the proposition $A to A$. But that isn't what circular reasoning is, because $A to A$ always holds, how can you object to that?



              Second, he is not addressing the argument that Alice made. Even if $(A to A) to A$ (for her specific claim) applies to the assumptions and conclusions of her argument: unless she appealed to that theorem as an inference, she hasn't made any mistake. $(A to A) to A$ does hold in the case that $A$ itself is provable, such as when $A$ is a tautology. Observing this isn't deductively equivalent to assuming $(A to A) to A$ holds in all cases and using that as an inference.







              share|cite|improve this answer













              share|cite|improve this answer



              share|cite|improve this answer











              answered Jul 30 at 0:14









              DanielV

              17.4k42651




              17.4k42651




















                  up vote
                  4
                  down vote













                  If her thesis is true, you could argue she is somehow right. But we dont know that her thesis is true. Lets say A is the set of axioms, and S(A) all true statements derivable from this set, and t her thesis. Then she wants to show that t in S(A). Only if this were true she could use that t is in S(A). But she doesnt know it.



                  To make it clear to her: you could ask why not use also not t to show that the axiom system is contradictory. How does she know not t is not in S(A)






                  share|cite|improve this answer





















                  • This hits the nail right on the head.
                    – Vincent
                    Jul 30 at 15:27














                  up vote
                  4
                  down vote













                  If her thesis is true, you could argue she is somehow right. But we dont know that her thesis is true. Lets say A is the set of axioms, and S(A) all true statements derivable from this set, and t her thesis. Then she wants to show that t in S(A). Only if this were true she could use that t is in S(A). But she doesnt know it.



                  To make it clear to her: you could ask why not use also not t to show that the axiom system is contradictory. How does she know not t is not in S(A)






                  share|cite|improve this answer





















                  • This hits the nail right on the head.
                    – Vincent
                    Jul 30 at 15:27












                  up vote
                  4
                  down vote










                  up vote
                  4
                  down vote









                  If her thesis is true, you could argue she is somehow right. But we dont know that her thesis is true. Lets say A is the set of axioms, and S(A) all true statements derivable from this set, and t her thesis. Then she wants to show that t in S(A). Only if this were true she could use that t is in S(A). But she doesnt know it.



                  To make it clear to her: you could ask why not use also not t to show that the axiom system is contradictory. How does she know not t is not in S(A)






                  share|cite|improve this answer













                  If her thesis is true, you could argue she is somehow right. But we dont know that her thesis is true. Lets say A is the set of axioms, and S(A) all true statements derivable from this set, and t her thesis. Then she wants to show that t in S(A). Only if this were true she could use that t is in S(A). But she doesnt know it.



                  To make it clear to her: you could ask why not use also not t to show that the axiom system is contradictory. How does she know not t is not in S(A)







                  share|cite|improve this answer













                  share|cite|improve this answer



                  share|cite|improve this answer











                  answered Jul 29 at 15:17









                  lalala

                  17710




                  17710











                  • This hits the nail right on the head.
                    – Vincent
                    Jul 30 at 15:27
















                  • This hits the nail right on the head.
                    – Vincent
                    Jul 30 at 15:27















                  This hits the nail right on the head.
                  – Vincent
                  Jul 30 at 15:27




                  This hits the nail right on the head.
                  – Vincent
                  Jul 30 at 15:27










                  up vote
                  3
                  down vote













                  (Not really an answer, but too long for a comment. Refer to amWhy's comment and Bram28's answer for a direct answer to your question.)



                  From what I understand, tautologies have a reputation in philosophy as being a waste of time. Things like "if I am cold and wet, then I am cold" don't seem to contain any new information, and have little value. But, the philosophers wonder, why is mathematics, which traditionally is 100% tautology, so non-trivial and produces unexpected results?



                  Well, I'm sure there are many answers to this, but the way I see it, it's finding a path from premises to conclusions that can be new information. Human beings aren't perfect; they cannot instantly account for every statement they hold to be true, and combine them in every possible way, to effortlessly see every consequence one can derive from them.



                  This is the point of proofs/arguments. I can read over and properly comprehend the axioms of ZFC, the definition of $mathbbR^3$ and its Euclidean unit sphere, but that doesn't mean I instantly know how to prove the Banach-Tarski paradox!



                  Alice's reply seems to take the opposite stance. She seems to be assuming, implicitly, that there is no such gap between premises, consequences, and hence conclusions, rendering arguments useless. It's a view that I think most people would consider extreme (and wrong).






                  share|cite|improve this answer

























                    up vote
                    3
                    down vote













                    (Not really an answer, but too long for a comment. Refer to amWhy's comment and Bram28's answer for a direct answer to your question.)



                    From what I understand, tautologies have a reputation in philosophy as being a waste of time. Things like "if I am cold and wet, then I am cold" don't seem to contain any new information, and have little value. But, the philosophers wonder, why is mathematics, which traditionally is 100% tautology, so non-trivial and produces unexpected results?



                    Well, I'm sure there are many answers to this, but the way I see it, it's finding a path from premises to conclusions that can be new information. Human beings aren't perfect; they cannot instantly account for every statement they hold to be true, and combine them in every possible way, to effortlessly see every consequence one can derive from them.



                    This is the point of proofs/arguments. I can read over and properly comprehend the axioms of ZFC, the definition of $mathbbR^3$ and its Euclidean unit sphere, but that doesn't mean I instantly know how to prove the Banach-Tarski paradox!



                    Alice's reply seems to take the opposite stance. She seems to be assuming, implicitly, that there is no such gap between premises, consequences, and hence conclusions, rendering arguments useless. It's a view that I think most people would consider extreme (and wrong).






                    share|cite|improve this answer























                      up vote
                      3
                      down vote










                      up vote
                      3
                      down vote









                      (Not really an answer, but too long for a comment. Refer to amWhy's comment and Bram28's answer for a direct answer to your question.)



                      From what I understand, tautologies have a reputation in philosophy as being a waste of time. Things like "if I am cold and wet, then I am cold" don't seem to contain any new information, and have little value. But, the philosophers wonder, why is mathematics, which traditionally is 100% tautology, so non-trivial and produces unexpected results?



                      Well, I'm sure there are many answers to this, but the way I see it, it's finding a path from premises to conclusions that can be new information. Human beings aren't perfect; they cannot instantly account for every statement they hold to be true, and combine them in every possible way, to effortlessly see every consequence one can derive from them.



                      This is the point of proofs/arguments. I can read over and properly comprehend the axioms of ZFC, the definition of $mathbbR^3$ and its Euclidean unit sphere, but that doesn't mean I instantly know how to prove the Banach-Tarski paradox!



                      Alice's reply seems to take the opposite stance. She seems to be assuming, implicitly, that there is no such gap between premises, consequences, and hence conclusions, rendering arguments useless. It's a view that I think most people would consider extreme (and wrong).






                      share|cite|improve this answer













                      (Not really an answer, but too long for a comment. Refer to amWhy's comment and Bram28's answer for a direct answer to your question.)



                      From what I understand, tautologies have a reputation in philosophy as being a waste of time. Things like "if I am cold and wet, then I am cold" don't seem to contain any new information, and have little value. But, the philosophers wonder, why is mathematics, which traditionally is 100% tautology, so non-trivial and produces unexpected results?



                      Well, I'm sure there are many answers to this, but the way I see it, it's finding a path from premises to conclusions that can be new information. Human beings aren't perfect; they cannot instantly account for every statement they hold to be true, and combine them in every possible way, to effortlessly see every consequence one can derive from them.



                      This is the point of proofs/arguments. I can read over and properly comprehend the axioms of ZFC, the definition of $mathbbR^3$ and its Euclidean unit sphere, but that doesn't mean I instantly know how to prove the Banach-Tarski paradox!



                      Alice's reply seems to take the opposite stance. She seems to be assuming, implicitly, that there is no such gap between premises, consequences, and hence conclusions, rendering arguments useless. It's a view that I think most people would consider extreme (and wrong).







                      share|cite|improve this answer













                      share|cite|improve this answer



                      share|cite|improve this answer











                      answered Jul 29 at 1:51









                      Theo Bendit

                      11.8k1843




                      11.8k1843




















                          up vote
                          2
                          down vote













                          Supposing that Alice tells the truth about using circular reasoning, it can get demonstrated that Alice has made an error. Alice says:



                          "Of course my proof contains its thesis within its assumptions. Each and every proof must be based on axioms, which are assumptions that are not to be proved. Thus each set of axioms implicite contains all thesis that can be proven from this set of axioms."



                          Alright, let's suppose the first two sentences correct. The third is false though. Why? Because without rules of inference we can't conclude anything from any axioms. So, we can't conclude that each set of axioms implies all of the theses, because axioms don't imply theses in the first place. Ever since Frege it has been clear that rules of inference and axioms are not the same thing. Only axiom and rules of inference taken together imply a thesis. But then, the set of axioms doesn't implicitly contain all theses, because it's axioms and rules of inference that imply all theses provable in the theory.



                          Edit: Also, it really doesn't work out that "logic is little more than a tautology" or "logic is little more than a collection of tautologies". Logic often involves showing something like A $vdash$ B, where A is not a tautology, nor is B, and A $vdash$ B is not a tautology.






                          share|cite|improve this answer























                          • So what you mean is that a set of axioms does not contain the rules of inference, without which no conclusions will follow anyways (Rules of inference + Axioms -> theses)?
                            – Pieter Rousseau
                            Jul 30 at 6:53











                          • @PieterRousseau Yes, that's it.
                            – Doug Spoonwood
                            Jul 30 at 6:57






                          • 1




                            So what if Alice rephrased her statement: "Of course my proof contains its thesis within its assumptions. Each and every proof must be based on rules of inference and axioms, which are assumptions that are not to be proved. Thus each set of rules and axioms implicitly contains all thesis that can be proven from this set."
                            – Pieter Rousseau
                            Jul 30 at 7:00










                          • @PieterRousseau I don't think that a rule of inference can accurately get called an assumption. Rules of inference don't bear truth, while assumptions do. You also have seemed to have dropped Alice's "implicite".
                            – Doug Spoonwood
                            Jul 30 at 7:04











                          • "Rules of inference don't bear truth, while assumptions do." What do mean? Point of clarification: I am assuming with rules of inference that you are talking about rules of logic, such as A is A; A is not not A and if A is B and B is C then A is C. (sorry about dropping the "implicite" - I actually thought it was a typo, or I am misunderstanding what you mean - would you mind if we get back to that once I understand what you mean about assumptions.)
                            – Pieter Rousseau
                            Jul 30 at 7:35














                          up vote
                          2
                          down vote













                          Supposing that Alice tells the truth about using circular reasoning, it can get demonstrated that Alice has made an error. Alice says:



                          "Of course my proof contains its thesis within its assumptions. Each and every proof must be based on axioms, which are assumptions that are not to be proved. Thus each set of axioms implicite contains all thesis that can be proven from this set of axioms."



                          Alright, let's suppose the first two sentences correct. The third is false though. Why? Because without rules of inference we can't conclude anything from any axioms. So, we can't conclude that each set of axioms implies all of the theses, because axioms don't imply theses in the first place. Ever since Frege it has been clear that rules of inference and axioms are not the same thing. Only axiom and rules of inference taken together imply a thesis. But then, the set of axioms doesn't implicitly contain all theses, because it's axioms and rules of inference that imply all theses provable in the theory.



                          Edit: Also, it really doesn't work out that "logic is little more than a tautology" or "logic is little more than a collection of tautologies". Logic often involves showing something like A $vdash$ B, where A is not a tautology, nor is B, and A $vdash$ B is not a tautology.






                          share|cite|improve this answer























                          • So what you mean is that a set of axioms does not contain the rules of inference, without which no conclusions will follow anyways (Rules of inference + Axioms -> theses)?
                            – Pieter Rousseau
                            Jul 30 at 6:53











                          • @PieterRousseau Yes, that's it.
                            – Doug Spoonwood
                            Jul 30 at 6:57






                          • 1




                            So what if Alice rephrased her statement: "Of course my proof contains its thesis within its assumptions. Each and every proof must be based on rules of inference and axioms, which are assumptions that are not to be proved. Thus each set of rules and axioms implicitly contains all thesis that can be proven from this set."
                            – Pieter Rousseau
                            Jul 30 at 7:00










                          • @PieterRousseau I don't think that a rule of inference can accurately get called an assumption. Rules of inference don't bear truth, while assumptions do. You also have seemed to have dropped Alice's "implicite".
                            – Doug Spoonwood
                            Jul 30 at 7:04











                          • "Rules of inference don't bear truth, while assumptions do." What do mean? Point of clarification: I am assuming with rules of inference that you are talking about rules of logic, such as A is A; A is not not A and if A is B and B is C then A is C. (sorry about dropping the "implicite" - I actually thought it was a typo, or I am misunderstanding what you mean - would you mind if we get back to that once I understand what you mean about assumptions.)
                            – Pieter Rousseau
                            Jul 30 at 7:35












                          up vote
                          2
                          down vote










                          up vote
                          2
                          down vote









                          Supposing that Alice tells the truth about using circular reasoning, it can get demonstrated that Alice has made an error. Alice says:



                          "Of course my proof contains its thesis within its assumptions. Each and every proof must be based on axioms, which are assumptions that are not to be proved. Thus each set of axioms implicite contains all thesis that can be proven from this set of axioms."



                          Alright, let's suppose the first two sentences correct. The third is false though. Why? Because without rules of inference we can't conclude anything from any axioms. So, we can't conclude that each set of axioms implies all of the theses, because axioms don't imply theses in the first place. Ever since Frege it has been clear that rules of inference and axioms are not the same thing. Only axiom and rules of inference taken together imply a thesis. But then, the set of axioms doesn't implicitly contain all theses, because it's axioms and rules of inference that imply all theses provable in the theory.



                          Edit: Also, it really doesn't work out that "logic is little more than a tautology" or "logic is little more than a collection of tautologies". Logic often involves showing something like A $vdash$ B, where A is not a tautology, nor is B, and A $vdash$ B is not a tautology.






                          share|cite|improve this answer















                          Supposing that Alice tells the truth about using circular reasoning, it can get demonstrated that Alice has made an error. Alice says:



                          "Of course my proof contains its thesis within its assumptions. Each and every proof must be based on axioms, which are assumptions that are not to be proved. Thus each set of axioms implicite contains all thesis that can be proven from this set of axioms."



                          Alright, let's suppose the first two sentences correct. The third is false though. Why? Because without rules of inference we can't conclude anything from any axioms. So, we can't conclude that each set of axioms implies all of the theses, because axioms don't imply theses in the first place. Ever since Frege it has been clear that rules of inference and axioms are not the same thing. Only axiom and rules of inference taken together imply a thesis. But then, the set of axioms doesn't implicitly contain all theses, because it's axioms and rules of inference that imply all theses provable in the theory.



                          Edit: Also, it really doesn't work out that "logic is little more than a tautology" or "logic is little more than a collection of tautologies". Logic often involves showing something like A $vdash$ B, where A is not a tautology, nor is B, and A $vdash$ B is not a tautology.







                          share|cite|improve this answer















                          share|cite|improve this answer



                          share|cite|improve this answer








                          edited Aug 1 at 0:35


























                          answered Jul 29 at 5:00









                          Doug Spoonwood

                          7,57012042




                          7,57012042











                          • So what you mean is that a set of axioms does not contain the rules of inference, without which no conclusions will follow anyways (Rules of inference + Axioms -> theses)?
                            – Pieter Rousseau
                            Jul 30 at 6:53











                          • @PieterRousseau Yes, that's it.
                            – Doug Spoonwood
                            Jul 30 at 6:57






                          • 1




                            So what if Alice rephrased her statement: "Of course my proof contains its thesis within its assumptions. Each and every proof must be based on rules of inference and axioms, which are assumptions that are not to be proved. Thus each set of rules and axioms implicitly contains all thesis that can be proven from this set."
                            – Pieter Rousseau
                            Jul 30 at 7:00










                          • @PieterRousseau I don't think that a rule of inference can accurately get called an assumption. Rules of inference don't bear truth, while assumptions do. You also have seemed to have dropped Alice's "implicite".
                            – Doug Spoonwood
                            Jul 30 at 7:04











                          • "Rules of inference don't bear truth, while assumptions do." What do mean? Point of clarification: I am assuming with rules of inference that you are talking about rules of logic, such as A is A; A is not not A and if A is B and B is C then A is C. (sorry about dropping the "implicite" - I actually thought it was a typo, or I am misunderstanding what you mean - would you mind if we get back to that once I understand what you mean about assumptions.)
                            – Pieter Rousseau
                            Jul 30 at 7:35
















                          • So what you mean is that a set of axioms does not contain the rules of inference, without which no conclusions will follow anyways (Rules of inference + Axioms -> theses)?
                            – Pieter Rousseau
                            Jul 30 at 6:53











                          • @PieterRousseau Yes, that's it.
                            – Doug Spoonwood
                            Jul 30 at 6:57






                          • 1




                            So what if Alice rephrased her statement: "Of course my proof contains its thesis within its assumptions. Each and every proof must be based on rules of inference and axioms, which are assumptions that are not to be proved. Thus each set of rules and axioms implicitly contains all thesis that can be proven from this set."
                            – Pieter Rousseau
                            Jul 30 at 7:00










                          • @PieterRousseau I don't think that a rule of inference can accurately get called an assumption. Rules of inference don't bear truth, while assumptions do. You also have seemed to have dropped Alice's "implicite".
                            – Doug Spoonwood
                            Jul 30 at 7:04











                          • "Rules of inference don't bear truth, while assumptions do." What do mean? Point of clarification: I am assuming with rules of inference that you are talking about rules of logic, such as A is A; A is not not A and if A is B and B is C then A is C. (sorry about dropping the "implicite" - I actually thought it was a typo, or I am misunderstanding what you mean - would you mind if we get back to that once I understand what you mean about assumptions.)
                            – Pieter Rousseau
                            Jul 30 at 7:35















                          So what you mean is that a set of axioms does not contain the rules of inference, without which no conclusions will follow anyways (Rules of inference + Axioms -> theses)?
                          – Pieter Rousseau
                          Jul 30 at 6:53





                          So what you mean is that a set of axioms does not contain the rules of inference, without which no conclusions will follow anyways (Rules of inference + Axioms -> theses)?
                          – Pieter Rousseau
                          Jul 30 at 6:53













                          @PieterRousseau Yes, that's it.
                          – Doug Spoonwood
                          Jul 30 at 6:57




                          @PieterRousseau Yes, that's it.
                          – Doug Spoonwood
                          Jul 30 at 6:57




                          1




                          1




                          So what if Alice rephrased her statement: "Of course my proof contains its thesis within its assumptions. Each and every proof must be based on rules of inference and axioms, which are assumptions that are not to be proved. Thus each set of rules and axioms implicitly contains all thesis that can be proven from this set."
                          – Pieter Rousseau
                          Jul 30 at 7:00




                          So what if Alice rephrased her statement: "Of course my proof contains its thesis within its assumptions. Each and every proof must be based on rules of inference and axioms, which are assumptions that are not to be proved. Thus each set of rules and axioms implicitly contains all thesis that can be proven from this set."
                          – Pieter Rousseau
                          Jul 30 at 7:00












                          @PieterRousseau I don't think that a rule of inference can accurately get called an assumption. Rules of inference don't bear truth, while assumptions do. You also have seemed to have dropped Alice's "implicite".
                          – Doug Spoonwood
                          Jul 30 at 7:04





                          @PieterRousseau I don't think that a rule of inference can accurately get called an assumption. Rules of inference don't bear truth, while assumptions do. You also have seemed to have dropped Alice's "implicite".
                          – Doug Spoonwood
                          Jul 30 at 7:04













                          "Rules of inference don't bear truth, while assumptions do." What do mean? Point of clarification: I am assuming with rules of inference that you are talking about rules of logic, such as A is A; A is not not A and if A is B and B is C then A is C. (sorry about dropping the "implicite" - I actually thought it was a typo, or I am misunderstanding what you mean - would you mind if we get back to that once I understand what you mean about assumptions.)
                          – Pieter Rousseau
                          Jul 30 at 7:35




                          "Rules of inference don't bear truth, while assumptions do." What do mean? Point of clarification: I am assuming with rules of inference that you are talking about rules of logic, such as A is A; A is not not A and if A is B and B is C then A is C. (sorry about dropping the "implicite" - I actually thought it was a typo, or I am misunderstanding what you mean - would you mind if we get back to that once I understand what you mean about assumptions.)
                          – Pieter Rousseau
                          Jul 30 at 7:35










                          up vote
                          1
                          down vote













                          We can take the extreme case, where the axioms not only imply the conclusion, but contain the conclusion. Suppose I'm trying to prove it's raining outside. The following piece of reasoning is perfectly valid:




                          It's raining, therefore it's raining.




                          Nothing wrong with that, and no one would call it circular. It's just pointless. But suppose someone skeptical, without access to a window to look outside, were to challenge me to prove it's raining. If I now start my reasoning with "Well, we know that it's raining, so...", now I'm committing circular reasoning.



                          Notice that in both cases my proof and my axioms were the same, only the context changes. Circularity is not a property of a proof, it's a property of the context in which that proof is given. When we prove something from axioms, we should choose the axioms to be statements that are known to be true. If they're not known to be true, this is a Bad Thing. A special case of this kind of Bad Thing is where one of the axioms is the conclusion we're trying to prove (which is not known to be true): this special case is called circular reasoning.






                          share|cite|improve this answer

























                            up vote
                            1
                            down vote













                            We can take the extreme case, where the axioms not only imply the conclusion, but contain the conclusion. Suppose I'm trying to prove it's raining outside. The following piece of reasoning is perfectly valid:




                            It's raining, therefore it's raining.




                            Nothing wrong with that, and no one would call it circular. It's just pointless. But suppose someone skeptical, without access to a window to look outside, were to challenge me to prove it's raining. If I now start my reasoning with "Well, we know that it's raining, so...", now I'm committing circular reasoning.



                            Notice that in both cases my proof and my axioms were the same, only the context changes. Circularity is not a property of a proof, it's a property of the context in which that proof is given. When we prove something from axioms, we should choose the axioms to be statements that are known to be true. If they're not known to be true, this is a Bad Thing. A special case of this kind of Bad Thing is where one of the axioms is the conclusion we're trying to prove (which is not known to be true): this special case is called circular reasoning.






                            share|cite|improve this answer























                              up vote
                              1
                              down vote










                              up vote
                              1
                              down vote









                              We can take the extreme case, where the axioms not only imply the conclusion, but contain the conclusion. Suppose I'm trying to prove it's raining outside. The following piece of reasoning is perfectly valid:




                              It's raining, therefore it's raining.




                              Nothing wrong with that, and no one would call it circular. It's just pointless. But suppose someone skeptical, without access to a window to look outside, were to challenge me to prove it's raining. If I now start my reasoning with "Well, we know that it's raining, so...", now I'm committing circular reasoning.



                              Notice that in both cases my proof and my axioms were the same, only the context changes. Circularity is not a property of a proof, it's a property of the context in which that proof is given. When we prove something from axioms, we should choose the axioms to be statements that are known to be true. If they're not known to be true, this is a Bad Thing. A special case of this kind of Bad Thing is where one of the axioms is the conclusion we're trying to prove (which is not known to be true): this special case is called circular reasoning.






                              share|cite|improve this answer













                              We can take the extreme case, where the axioms not only imply the conclusion, but contain the conclusion. Suppose I'm trying to prove it's raining outside. The following piece of reasoning is perfectly valid:




                              It's raining, therefore it's raining.




                              Nothing wrong with that, and no one would call it circular. It's just pointless. But suppose someone skeptical, without access to a window to look outside, were to challenge me to prove it's raining. If I now start my reasoning with "Well, we know that it's raining, so...", now I'm committing circular reasoning.



                              Notice that in both cases my proof and my axioms were the same, only the context changes. Circularity is not a property of a proof, it's a property of the context in which that proof is given. When we prove something from axioms, we should choose the axioms to be statements that are known to be true. If they're not known to be true, this is a Bad Thing. A special case of this kind of Bad Thing is where one of the axioms is the conclusion we're trying to prove (which is not known to be true): this special case is called circular reasoning.







                              share|cite|improve this answer













                              share|cite|improve this answer



                              share|cite|improve this answer











                              answered Jul 29 at 22:39









                              Jack M

                              16.9k33473




                              16.9k33473




















                                  up vote
                                  -1
                                  down vote













                                  The apparent dilemma arises from two words which do not mean the same thing.



                                  You are talking about proofs. Alice is talking about truth. These are not the same thing.



                                  A statement which is always true is a tautology, so in a sense, every such statement, including a true theorem, is a tautology.



                                  But truth is not a proof.



                                  Proofs are simply the re-expression of statements as other statements without relying on other statements (i.e., no circular reasoning).



                                  But the result of a correct proof is no more true than the original statements, so a proof is likewise not always the truth.






                                  share|cite|improve this answer



















                                  • 1




                                    "So in a sense, every true statement, including a true theorem, is a tautology." The statement "it is raining withing 100 feet of me" is sometimes true and sometimes not true. In mathematics, the statement "a = b" is only sometimes true, such as where 'a' and 'b' have particular, known computations, such as a = (2 + 2) and b = (3 + 1), or in say the case where (a + c) = (b + c). So, I don't agree that every true statement is a tautology.
                                    – Doug Spoonwood
                                    Jul 30 at 18:50










                                  • @DougSpoonwood You have proposed a sentence which depends on outside values to be true or false. This kind of statement is fine. It is called a conditional statement. I stated, "a statement which is always true is a tautology." I will edit my answer to make the phrase you quoted part of the same sentence so it is more clear.
                                    – Joseph Myers
                                    Aug 3 at 23:17















                                  up vote
                                  -1
                                  down vote













                                  The apparent dilemma arises from two words which do not mean the same thing.



                                  You are talking about proofs. Alice is talking about truth. These are not the same thing.



                                  A statement which is always true is a tautology, so in a sense, every such statement, including a true theorem, is a tautology.



                                  But truth is not a proof.



                                  Proofs are simply the re-expression of statements as other statements without relying on other statements (i.e., no circular reasoning).



                                  But the result of a correct proof is no more true than the original statements, so a proof is likewise not always the truth.






                                  share|cite|improve this answer



















                                  • 1




                                    "So in a sense, every true statement, including a true theorem, is a tautology." The statement "it is raining withing 100 feet of me" is sometimes true and sometimes not true. In mathematics, the statement "a = b" is only sometimes true, such as where 'a' and 'b' have particular, known computations, such as a = (2 + 2) and b = (3 + 1), or in say the case where (a + c) = (b + c). So, I don't agree that every true statement is a tautology.
                                    – Doug Spoonwood
                                    Jul 30 at 18:50










                                  • @DougSpoonwood You have proposed a sentence which depends on outside values to be true or false. This kind of statement is fine. It is called a conditional statement. I stated, "a statement which is always true is a tautology." I will edit my answer to make the phrase you quoted part of the same sentence so it is more clear.
                                    – Joseph Myers
                                    Aug 3 at 23:17













                                  up vote
                                  -1
                                  down vote










                                  up vote
                                  -1
                                  down vote









                                  The apparent dilemma arises from two words which do not mean the same thing.



                                  You are talking about proofs. Alice is talking about truth. These are not the same thing.



                                  A statement which is always true is a tautology, so in a sense, every such statement, including a true theorem, is a tautology.



                                  But truth is not a proof.



                                  Proofs are simply the re-expression of statements as other statements without relying on other statements (i.e., no circular reasoning).



                                  But the result of a correct proof is no more true than the original statements, so a proof is likewise not always the truth.






                                  share|cite|improve this answer















                                  The apparent dilemma arises from two words which do not mean the same thing.



                                  You are talking about proofs. Alice is talking about truth. These are not the same thing.



                                  A statement which is always true is a tautology, so in a sense, every such statement, including a true theorem, is a tautology.



                                  But truth is not a proof.



                                  Proofs are simply the re-expression of statements as other statements without relying on other statements (i.e., no circular reasoning).



                                  But the result of a correct proof is no more true than the original statements, so a proof is likewise not always the truth.







                                  share|cite|improve this answer















                                  share|cite|improve this answer



                                  share|cite|improve this answer








                                  edited Aug 3 at 23:18


























                                  answered Jul 30 at 4:36









                                  Joseph Myers

                                  29918




                                  29918







                                  • 1




                                    "So in a sense, every true statement, including a true theorem, is a tautology." The statement "it is raining withing 100 feet of me" is sometimes true and sometimes not true. In mathematics, the statement "a = b" is only sometimes true, such as where 'a' and 'b' have particular, known computations, such as a = (2 + 2) and b = (3 + 1), or in say the case where (a + c) = (b + c). So, I don't agree that every true statement is a tautology.
                                    – Doug Spoonwood
                                    Jul 30 at 18:50










                                  • @DougSpoonwood You have proposed a sentence which depends on outside values to be true or false. This kind of statement is fine. It is called a conditional statement. I stated, "a statement which is always true is a tautology." I will edit my answer to make the phrase you quoted part of the same sentence so it is more clear.
                                    – Joseph Myers
                                    Aug 3 at 23:17













                                  • 1




                                    "So in a sense, every true statement, including a true theorem, is a tautology." The statement "it is raining withing 100 feet of me" is sometimes true and sometimes not true. In mathematics, the statement "a = b" is only sometimes true, such as where 'a' and 'b' have particular, known computations, such as a = (2 + 2) and b = (3 + 1), or in say the case where (a + c) = (b + c). So, I don't agree that every true statement is a tautology.
                                    – Doug Spoonwood
                                    Jul 30 at 18:50










                                  • @DougSpoonwood You have proposed a sentence which depends on outside values to be true or false. This kind of statement is fine. It is called a conditional statement. I stated, "a statement which is always true is a tautology." I will edit my answer to make the phrase you quoted part of the same sentence so it is more clear.
                                    – Joseph Myers
                                    Aug 3 at 23:17








                                  1




                                  1




                                  "So in a sense, every true statement, including a true theorem, is a tautology." The statement "it is raining withing 100 feet of me" is sometimes true and sometimes not true. In mathematics, the statement "a = b" is only sometimes true, such as where 'a' and 'b' have particular, known computations, such as a = (2 + 2) and b = (3 + 1), or in say the case where (a + c) = (b + c). So, I don't agree that every true statement is a tautology.
                                  – Doug Spoonwood
                                  Jul 30 at 18:50




                                  "So in a sense, every true statement, including a true theorem, is a tautology." The statement "it is raining withing 100 feet of me" is sometimes true and sometimes not true. In mathematics, the statement "a = b" is only sometimes true, such as where 'a' and 'b' have particular, known computations, such as a = (2 + 2) and b = (3 + 1), or in say the case where (a + c) = (b + c). So, I don't agree that every true statement is a tautology.
                                  – Doug Spoonwood
                                  Jul 30 at 18:50












                                  @DougSpoonwood You have proposed a sentence which depends on outside values to be true or false. This kind of statement is fine. It is called a conditional statement. I stated, "a statement which is always true is a tautology." I will edit my answer to make the phrase you quoted part of the same sentence so it is more clear.
                                  – Joseph Myers
                                  Aug 3 at 23:17





                                  @DougSpoonwood You have proposed a sentence which depends on outside values to be true or false. This kind of statement is fine. It is called a conditional statement. I stated, "a statement which is always true is a tautology." I will edit my answer to make the phrase you quoted part of the same sentence so it is more clear.
                                  – Joseph Myers
                                  Aug 3 at 23:17











                                  up vote
                                  -2
                                  down vote













                                  Circular reasoning is when two statements depend on each other in order to be true (consistent with the model).



                                  • The inside angles of a triangles are supplementary

                                  • The co-interior angles of a line intersecting parallel lines are supplementary

                                  Both statements can be used to prove the other but neither of the above statements can be proven from the existing set of axioms in Geometry unless one of them is assumed as true without proof (an axiom). This "straightens" the argument so as to begin at this assumption. This is not fallacious at all unless it produces a contradiction with existing assumptions. It just limits or rather refines the set of statements that can follow as a logical consequences of the additional assumption.



                                  Alice's Argument that Mathematical Proofs are Circular can be understood as:



                                  • Each and every proof must be based on axioms.


                                  • Axioms implicitly contains all theses that can be proven from the set of axioms.


                                  To prove any one of these two statements will require the other one. This is circular. To "straighten" it we must assume one of the two to be true and the other can follow by the rules of inference/logic.



                                  Is Mathematics then a tautology? If you define a tautology as a system of statements that is true by necessity or by virtue of its logical form, then I think it unashamedly is, and has to be based on the rules of inference/logic and the assumption just made: Each and every proof must be based on axioms or restated: All theses must follow by the rules of inference (proof) from the set of axioms.



                                  Is Alice's argument valid that, in form, it is equivalent to that of axiomatic system of Mathematics? Is it consistent with the model produced by the assumption: all theses must follow by the rules of inference (proof) from the set of axioms.



                                  Proof by contradiction:
                                  Assumed it is true that a proof contains its thesis within its assumptions.



                                  Two situations,
                                  1) The thesis is an existing axiom (assumption without proof).



                                  If the thesis is an existing axiom, then of course her model is equivalent. A leads to A.



                                  2) The thesis is not an existing axiom (assumption without proof).



                                  If the thesis is not an existing axiom but it is an axiom because it is assumed without a proof, then is leads to a logical contradiction.



                                  Which means her proof is only valid if her thesis is indeed an existing axiom.



                                  Alice's solution:
                                  So if her argument is indeed circular, then her solution is to admit that one of the statements that she is making must be is an necessary assumption to develop the model/argument/worldview etc. Then it could be equivalent to the axiomatic system of Mathematics if it does not contradict any existing assumptions/axioms.






                                  share|cite|improve this answer

























                                    up vote
                                    -2
                                    down vote













                                    Circular reasoning is when two statements depend on each other in order to be true (consistent with the model).



                                    • The inside angles of a triangles are supplementary

                                    • The co-interior angles of a line intersecting parallel lines are supplementary

                                    Both statements can be used to prove the other but neither of the above statements can be proven from the existing set of axioms in Geometry unless one of them is assumed as true without proof (an axiom). This "straightens" the argument so as to begin at this assumption. This is not fallacious at all unless it produces a contradiction with existing assumptions. It just limits or rather refines the set of statements that can follow as a logical consequences of the additional assumption.



                                    Alice's Argument that Mathematical Proofs are Circular can be understood as:



                                    • Each and every proof must be based on axioms.


                                    • Axioms implicitly contains all theses that can be proven from the set of axioms.


                                    To prove any one of these two statements will require the other one. This is circular. To "straighten" it we must assume one of the two to be true and the other can follow by the rules of inference/logic.



                                    Is Mathematics then a tautology? If you define a tautology as a system of statements that is true by necessity or by virtue of its logical form, then I think it unashamedly is, and has to be based on the rules of inference/logic and the assumption just made: Each and every proof must be based on axioms or restated: All theses must follow by the rules of inference (proof) from the set of axioms.



                                    Is Alice's argument valid that, in form, it is equivalent to that of axiomatic system of Mathematics? Is it consistent with the model produced by the assumption: all theses must follow by the rules of inference (proof) from the set of axioms.



                                    Proof by contradiction:
                                    Assumed it is true that a proof contains its thesis within its assumptions.



                                    Two situations,
                                    1) The thesis is an existing axiom (assumption without proof).



                                    If the thesis is an existing axiom, then of course her model is equivalent. A leads to A.



                                    2) The thesis is not an existing axiom (assumption without proof).



                                    If the thesis is not an existing axiom but it is an axiom because it is assumed without a proof, then is leads to a logical contradiction.



                                    Which means her proof is only valid if her thesis is indeed an existing axiom.



                                    Alice's solution:
                                    So if her argument is indeed circular, then her solution is to admit that one of the statements that she is making must be is an necessary assumption to develop the model/argument/worldview etc. Then it could be equivalent to the axiomatic system of Mathematics if it does not contradict any existing assumptions/axioms.






                                    share|cite|improve this answer























                                      up vote
                                      -2
                                      down vote










                                      up vote
                                      -2
                                      down vote









                                      Circular reasoning is when two statements depend on each other in order to be true (consistent with the model).



                                      • The inside angles of a triangles are supplementary

                                      • The co-interior angles of a line intersecting parallel lines are supplementary

                                      Both statements can be used to prove the other but neither of the above statements can be proven from the existing set of axioms in Geometry unless one of them is assumed as true without proof (an axiom). This "straightens" the argument so as to begin at this assumption. This is not fallacious at all unless it produces a contradiction with existing assumptions. It just limits or rather refines the set of statements that can follow as a logical consequences of the additional assumption.



                                      Alice's Argument that Mathematical Proofs are Circular can be understood as:



                                      • Each and every proof must be based on axioms.


                                      • Axioms implicitly contains all theses that can be proven from the set of axioms.


                                      To prove any one of these two statements will require the other one. This is circular. To "straighten" it we must assume one of the two to be true and the other can follow by the rules of inference/logic.



                                      Is Mathematics then a tautology? If you define a tautology as a system of statements that is true by necessity or by virtue of its logical form, then I think it unashamedly is, and has to be based on the rules of inference/logic and the assumption just made: Each and every proof must be based on axioms or restated: All theses must follow by the rules of inference (proof) from the set of axioms.



                                      Is Alice's argument valid that, in form, it is equivalent to that of axiomatic system of Mathematics? Is it consistent with the model produced by the assumption: all theses must follow by the rules of inference (proof) from the set of axioms.



                                      Proof by contradiction:
                                      Assumed it is true that a proof contains its thesis within its assumptions.



                                      Two situations,
                                      1) The thesis is an existing axiom (assumption without proof).



                                      If the thesis is an existing axiom, then of course her model is equivalent. A leads to A.



                                      2) The thesis is not an existing axiom (assumption without proof).



                                      If the thesis is not an existing axiom but it is an axiom because it is assumed without a proof, then is leads to a logical contradiction.



                                      Which means her proof is only valid if her thesis is indeed an existing axiom.



                                      Alice's solution:
                                      So if her argument is indeed circular, then her solution is to admit that one of the statements that she is making must be is an necessary assumption to develop the model/argument/worldview etc. Then it could be equivalent to the axiomatic system of Mathematics if it does not contradict any existing assumptions/axioms.






                                      share|cite|improve this answer













                                      Circular reasoning is when two statements depend on each other in order to be true (consistent with the model).



                                      • The inside angles of a triangles are supplementary

                                      • The co-interior angles of a line intersecting parallel lines are supplementary

                                      Both statements can be used to prove the other but neither of the above statements can be proven from the existing set of axioms in Geometry unless one of them is assumed as true without proof (an axiom). This "straightens" the argument so as to begin at this assumption. This is not fallacious at all unless it produces a contradiction with existing assumptions. It just limits or rather refines the set of statements that can follow as a logical consequences of the additional assumption.



                                      Alice's Argument that Mathematical Proofs are Circular can be understood as:



                                      • Each and every proof must be based on axioms.


                                      • Axioms implicitly contains all theses that can be proven from the set of axioms.


                                      To prove any one of these two statements will require the other one. This is circular. To "straighten" it we must assume one of the two to be true and the other can follow by the rules of inference/logic.



                                      Is Mathematics then a tautology? If you define a tautology as a system of statements that is true by necessity or by virtue of its logical form, then I think it unashamedly is, and has to be based on the rules of inference/logic and the assumption just made: Each and every proof must be based on axioms or restated: All theses must follow by the rules of inference (proof) from the set of axioms.



                                      Is Alice's argument valid that, in form, it is equivalent to that of axiomatic system of Mathematics? Is it consistent with the model produced by the assumption: all theses must follow by the rules of inference (proof) from the set of axioms.



                                      Proof by contradiction:
                                      Assumed it is true that a proof contains its thesis within its assumptions.



                                      Two situations,
                                      1) The thesis is an existing axiom (assumption without proof).



                                      If the thesis is an existing axiom, then of course her model is equivalent. A leads to A.



                                      2) The thesis is not an existing axiom (assumption without proof).



                                      If the thesis is not an existing axiom but it is an axiom because it is assumed without a proof, then is leads to a logical contradiction.



                                      Which means her proof is only valid if her thesis is indeed an existing axiom.



                                      Alice's solution:
                                      So if her argument is indeed circular, then her solution is to admit that one of the statements that she is making must be is an necessary assumption to develop the model/argument/worldview etc. Then it could be equivalent to the axiomatic system of Mathematics if it does not contradict any existing assumptions/axioms.







                                      share|cite|improve this answer













                                      share|cite|improve this answer



                                      share|cite|improve this answer











                                      answered Jul 30 at 11:03









                                      Pieter Rousseau

                                      37516




                                      37516






















                                           

                                          draft saved


                                          draft discarded


























                                           


                                          draft saved


                                          draft discarded














                                          StackExchange.ready(
                                          function ()
                                          StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmath.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f2865677%2fwhat-exactly-is-circular-reasoning%23new-answer', 'question_page');

                                          );

                                          Post as a guest













































































                                          Comments

                                          Popular posts from this blog

                                          What is the equation of a 3D cone with generalised tilt?

                                          Color the edges and diagonals of a regular polygon

                                          Relationship between determinant of matrix and determinant of adjoint?