Why is the “root field” premise necessary in this theorem about field extensions?

The name of the pictureThe name of the pictureThe name of the pictureClash Royale CLAN TAG#URR8PPP











up vote
0
down vote

favorite












In Charles Pinter's "A Book of Abstract Algebra," chapter 31, Theorem 8 (p316-17), he states:




Suppose $I subseteq E subseteq K$, where $E$ is a finite extension of $I$ and $K$ is a finite extension of $E$. If $K$ is the root field of some polynomial over $E$, then $K$ is also the root field of some polynomial over $I$.




His short proof is then:




Suppose $K$ is a root field of some polynomial over $E$, and let $K = I(a)$. If $p(x)$ is the minimum polynomial of $a$ over $I$, its coefficients are certainly in $E$ and it has a root $a$ in $K$, so by Theorem 7, all its roots are in $K$. Therefore, $K$ is the root field of $p(x)$ over $I$.




I think "certainly in $E$" is a typo that should read "certainly in $I$," but here's my question:



Why is it required as a premise that $K$ be a root field of some polynomial over $E$?



Since $K$ is a finite extension of $E$ which is a finite extension of $I$, $K$ must also be a finite extension of $I$ (by Ch29 Th2). Therefore it must also be a simple extension (by Ch31 Th2). So we can write $K=I(a)$ for some $a in K$, and be certain a minimum polynomial of $a$ over $I$ exists (since finite and simple extensions are defined to be in terms of algebraic elements). And from here, Pinter's argument (starting at sentence 2) still seems to hold. Am I missing something?







share|cite|improve this question



















  • For reference, here is Ch31 Th7, which he refers to: Let $K$ be the root field of some polynomial over $F$. For every irreducible polynomial $p(x)$ in $F[x]$, if $p(x)$ has one root in $K$, then $p(x)$ must have all of its roots in $K$.
    – WillG
    Jul 18 at 16:45















up vote
0
down vote

favorite












In Charles Pinter's "A Book of Abstract Algebra," chapter 31, Theorem 8 (p316-17), he states:




Suppose $I subseteq E subseteq K$, where $E$ is a finite extension of $I$ and $K$ is a finite extension of $E$. If $K$ is the root field of some polynomial over $E$, then $K$ is also the root field of some polynomial over $I$.




His short proof is then:




Suppose $K$ is a root field of some polynomial over $E$, and let $K = I(a)$. If $p(x)$ is the minimum polynomial of $a$ over $I$, its coefficients are certainly in $E$ and it has a root $a$ in $K$, so by Theorem 7, all its roots are in $K$. Therefore, $K$ is the root field of $p(x)$ over $I$.




I think "certainly in $E$" is a typo that should read "certainly in $I$," but here's my question:



Why is it required as a premise that $K$ be a root field of some polynomial over $E$?



Since $K$ is a finite extension of $E$ which is a finite extension of $I$, $K$ must also be a finite extension of $I$ (by Ch29 Th2). Therefore it must also be a simple extension (by Ch31 Th2). So we can write $K=I(a)$ for some $a in K$, and be certain a minimum polynomial of $a$ over $I$ exists (since finite and simple extensions are defined to be in terms of algebraic elements). And from here, Pinter's argument (starting at sentence 2) still seems to hold. Am I missing something?







share|cite|improve this question



















  • For reference, here is Ch31 Th7, which he refers to: Let $K$ be the root field of some polynomial over $F$. For every irreducible polynomial $p(x)$ in $F[x]$, if $p(x)$ has one root in $K$, then $p(x)$ must have all of its roots in $K$.
    – WillG
    Jul 18 at 16:45













up vote
0
down vote

favorite









up vote
0
down vote

favorite











In Charles Pinter's "A Book of Abstract Algebra," chapter 31, Theorem 8 (p316-17), he states:




Suppose $I subseteq E subseteq K$, where $E$ is a finite extension of $I$ and $K$ is a finite extension of $E$. If $K$ is the root field of some polynomial over $E$, then $K$ is also the root field of some polynomial over $I$.




His short proof is then:




Suppose $K$ is a root field of some polynomial over $E$, and let $K = I(a)$. If $p(x)$ is the minimum polynomial of $a$ over $I$, its coefficients are certainly in $E$ and it has a root $a$ in $K$, so by Theorem 7, all its roots are in $K$. Therefore, $K$ is the root field of $p(x)$ over $I$.




I think "certainly in $E$" is a typo that should read "certainly in $I$," but here's my question:



Why is it required as a premise that $K$ be a root field of some polynomial over $E$?



Since $K$ is a finite extension of $E$ which is a finite extension of $I$, $K$ must also be a finite extension of $I$ (by Ch29 Th2). Therefore it must also be a simple extension (by Ch31 Th2). So we can write $K=I(a)$ for some $a in K$, and be certain a minimum polynomial of $a$ over $I$ exists (since finite and simple extensions are defined to be in terms of algebraic elements). And from here, Pinter's argument (starting at sentence 2) still seems to hold. Am I missing something?







share|cite|improve this question











In Charles Pinter's "A Book of Abstract Algebra," chapter 31, Theorem 8 (p316-17), he states:




Suppose $I subseteq E subseteq K$, where $E$ is a finite extension of $I$ and $K$ is a finite extension of $E$. If $K$ is the root field of some polynomial over $E$, then $K$ is also the root field of some polynomial over $I$.




His short proof is then:




Suppose $K$ is a root field of some polynomial over $E$, and let $K = I(a)$. If $p(x)$ is the minimum polynomial of $a$ over $I$, its coefficients are certainly in $E$ and it has a root $a$ in $K$, so by Theorem 7, all its roots are in $K$. Therefore, $K$ is the root field of $p(x)$ over $I$.




I think "certainly in $E$" is a typo that should read "certainly in $I$," but here's my question:



Why is it required as a premise that $K$ be a root field of some polynomial over $E$?



Since $K$ is a finite extension of $E$ which is a finite extension of $I$, $K$ must also be a finite extension of $I$ (by Ch29 Th2). Therefore it must also be a simple extension (by Ch31 Th2). So we can write $K=I(a)$ for some $a in K$, and be certain a minimum polynomial of $a$ over $I$ exists (since finite and simple extensions are defined to be in terms of algebraic elements). And from here, Pinter's argument (starting at sentence 2) still seems to hold. Am I missing something?









share|cite|improve this question










share|cite|improve this question




share|cite|improve this question









asked Jul 18 at 16:40









WillG

40128




40128











  • For reference, here is Ch31 Th7, which he refers to: Let $K$ be the root field of some polynomial over $F$. For every irreducible polynomial $p(x)$ in $F[x]$, if $p(x)$ has one root in $K$, then $p(x)$ must have all of its roots in $K$.
    – WillG
    Jul 18 at 16:45

















  • For reference, here is Ch31 Th7, which he refers to: Let $K$ be the root field of some polynomial over $F$. For every irreducible polynomial $p(x)$ in $F[x]$, if $p(x)$ has one root in $K$, then $p(x)$ must have all of its roots in $K$.
    – WillG
    Jul 18 at 16:45
















For reference, here is Ch31 Th7, which he refers to: Let $K$ be the root field of some polynomial over $F$. For every irreducible polynomial $p(x)$ in $F[x]$, if $p(x)$ has one root in $K$, then $p(x)$ must have all of its roots in $K$.
– WillG
Jul 18 at 16:45





For reference, here is Ch31 Th7, which he refers to: Let $K$ be the root field of some polynomial over $F$. For every irreducible polynomial $p(x)$ in $F[x]$, if $p(x)$ has one root in $K$, then $p(x)$ must have all of its roots in $K$.
– WillG
Jul 18 at 16:45











2 Answers
2






active

oldest

votes

















up vote
2
down vote













This answer refers to the theorem as written in the 2nd. edition of Pinter's book:



"Root field" seems to be the same of what many of us call "splitting field": $;K;$ is a root field of some polynomial $;f(x)in I[x];$ means $;K=I(a_1,...,a_n);,;a_1,...,a_n;$ all the roots of $;f(x);$ (in some algebraic closure of $;I;$) and any subfield $;Ile Llneq K;$ fulfills that there exists at least one root $;a_n;$ such that $;a_nnotin L;$.



Observe then that $;f(x)in I[x]subset E[x];$ . Either $;E=K;$ and there's nothing to prove, or else $;Elneq K;$ and thus there is some root of $;f(x);$ whic is not in $;E;implies$ $;K;$ is the splitting field (root filed) of $;f(x);$ as polynomial in $;E[x];$ as $;K;$ contains all the roots of $;f;$ ...






share|cite|improve this answer























  • Doesn't the condition $K=I(a_1,...,a_n)$ already guarantee that any strict subfield of K lacks at least one of the $a_i$? My understanding was that $I(a_1,...,a_n)$ is the smallest field containing $I$ and $a_1, ..., a_n$, so that certainly if $L subsetneq I(a_1,...,a_n)$ then there exists an $a_i$ such that $a_i notin L$.
    – WillG
    Jul 18 at 18:08










  • @WillG Yes, of course...and that's the proof! Almost trivial.
    – DonAntonio
    Jul 18 at 19:34










  • I'm still confused then, as to what exactly goes wrong when we try to assert the same "theorem" but without the root field premise, i.e. "Suppose $I subseteq E subseteq K$, where $E$ is a finite extension of $I$ and $K$ is a finite extension of $E$. Then $K$ is the root field of some polynomial over $I$." Is this also true? If not, maybe a counterexample would help me understand what goes wrong...
    – WillG
    Jul 18 at 20:08










  • By all means: take for example $;I=E=Bbb Q;,;;K:=Bbb Q(sqrt[4]2);$ , and $; K;$ is not a splitting field of any irreducible rational polynomial.
    – DonAntonio
    Jul 18 at 21:09











  • Aha. That just blew my mind. I think my confusion was assuming all field extensions of a field $F$ had to be root fields of something over $F$, which clearly is not the case with $mathbbQ(sqrt[4]2)$. But there's one thing I'm still confused about: if $p(x)$ is the minimum polynomial of $a$ over $I$, then yes, its coefficients are in $E$ and it has a root in $K$. But is $p(x)$ necessarily irreducible in $E$? This seems to be required by Theorem 7 (in my comment above).
    – WillG
    Jul 19 at 18:55

















up vote
0
down vote



accepted










After reviewing this more, I believe the actual theorem from Pinter is wrong! Counterexample: Let $I=mathbbQ$ and $E=K=mathbbQ(sqrt[4]2)$.



I found the 2nd edition of the same book and discovered the theorem is different:




Suppose $Isubseteq Esubseteq K$ where $E$ is a finite extension of $I$ and $K$ is a finite extension of $E$. If $K$ is the root field of some polynomial over $I$, then $K$ is also the root field of some polynomial over $E$.




This makes much more sense now.






share|cite|improve this answer





















  • I honestly didn't even read your whole question. I simply went to Pinter's book and read from there the theorem, which is the one you mention here (2nd. Edition) and whose proof is pretty trivial. Indeed, the 1st. edition has this theorem wrongly written and, of course, it is false as it appears there.
    – DonAntonio
    Jul 20 at 9:01










Your Answer




StackExchange.ifUsing("editor", function ()
return StackExchange.using("mathjaxEditing", function ()
StackExchange.MarkdownEditor.creationCallbacks.add(function (editor, postfix)
StackExchange.mathjaxEditing.prepareWmdForMathJax(editor, postfix, [["$", "$"], ["\\(","\\)"]]);
);
);
, "mathjax-editing");

StackExchange.ready(function()
var channelOptions =
tags: "".split(" "),
id: "69"
;
initTagRenderer("".split(" "), "".split(" "), channelOptions);

StackExchange.using("externalEditor", function()
// Have to fire editor after snippets, if snippets enabled
if (StackExchange.settings.snippets.snippetsEnabled)
StackExchange.using("snippets", function()
createEditor();
);

else
createEditor();

);

function createEditor()
StackExchange.prepareEditor(
heartbeatType: 'answer',
convertImagesToLinks: true,
noModals: false,
showLowRepImageUploadWarning: true,
reputationToPostImages: 10,
bindNavPrevention: true,
postfix: "",
noCode: true, onDemand: true,
discardSelector: ".discard-answer"
,immediatelyShowMarkdownHelp:true
);



);








 

draft saved


draft discarded


















StackExchange.ready(
function ()
StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmath.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f2855753%2fwhy-is-the-root-field-premise-necessary-in-this-theorem-about-field-extensions%23new-answer', 'question_page');

);

Post as a guest






























2 Answers
2






active

oldest

votes








2 Answers
2






active

oldest

votes









active

oldest

votes






active

oldest

votes








up vote
2
down vote













This answer refers to the theorem as written in the 2nd. edition of Pinter's book:



"Root field" seems to be the same of what many of us call "splitting field": $;K;$ is a root field of some polynomial $;f(x)in I[x];$ means $;K=I(a_1,...,a_n);,;a_1,...,a_n;$ all the roots of $;f(x);$ (in some algebraic closure of $;I;$) and any subfield $;Ile Llneq K;$ fulfills that there exists at least one root $;a_n;$ such that $;a_nnotin L;$.



Observe then that $;f(x)in I[x]subset E[x];$ . Either $;E=K;$ and there's nothing to prove, or else $;Elneq K;$ and thus there is some root of $;f(x);$ whic is not in $;E;implies$ $;K;$ is the splitting field (root filed) of $;f(x);$ as polynomial in $;E[x];$ as $;K;$ contains all the roots of $;f;$ ...






share|cite|improve this answer























  • Doesn't the condition $K=I(a_1,...,a_n)$ already guarantee that any strict subfield of K lacks at least one of the $a_i$? My understanding was that $I(a_1,...,a_n)$ is the smallest field containing $I$ and $a_1, ..., a_n$, so that certainly if $L subsetneq I(a_1,...,a_n)$ then there exists an $a_i$ such that $a_i notin L$.
    – WillG
    Jul 18 at 18:08










  • @WillG Yes, of course...and that's the proof! Almost trivial.
    – DonAntonio
    Jul 18 at 19:34










  • I'm still confused then, as to what exactly goes wrong when we try to assert the same "theorem" but without the root field premise, i.e. "Suppose $I subseteq E subseteq K$, where $E$ is a finite extension of $I$ and $K$ is a finite extension of $E$. Then $K$ is the root field of some polynomial over $I$." Is this also true? If not, maybe a counterexample would help me understand what goes wrong...
    – WillG
    Jul 18 at 20:08










  • By all means: take for example $;I=E=Bbb Q;,;;K:=Bbb Q(sqrt[4]2);$ , and $; K;$ is not a splitting field of any irreducible rational polynomial.
    – DonAntonio
    Jul 18 at 21:09











  • Aha. That just blew my mind. I think my confusion was assuming all field extensions of a field $F$ had to be root fields of something over $F$, which clearly is not the case with $mathbbQ(sqrt[4]2)$. But there's one thing I'm still confused about: if $p(x)$ is the minimum polynomial of $a$ over $I$, then yes, its coefficients are in $E$ and it has a root in $K$. But is $p(x)$ necessarily irreducible in $E$? This seems to be required by Theorem 7 (in my comment above).
    – WillG
    Jul 19 at 18:55














up vote
2
down vote













This answer refers to the theorem as written in the 2nd. edition of Pinter's book:



"Root field" seems to be the same of what many of us call "splitting field": $;K;$ is a root field of some polynomial $;f(x)in I[x];$ means $;K=I(a_1,...,a_n);,;a_1,...,a_n;$ all the roots of $;f(x);$ (in some algebraic closure of $;I;$) and any subfield $;Ile Llneq K;$ fulfills that there exists at least one root $;a_n;$ such that $;a_nnotin L;$.



Observe then that $;f(x)in I[x]subset E[x];$ . Either $;E=K;$ and there's nothing to prove, or else $;Elneq K;$ and thus there is some root of $;f(x);$ whic is not in $;E;implies$ $;K;$ is the splitting field (root filed) of $;f(x);$ as polynomial in $;E[x];$ as $;K;$ contains all the roots of $;f;$ ...






share|cite|improve this answer























  • Doesn't the condition $K=I(a_1,...,a_n)$ already guarantee that any strict subfield of K lacks at least one of the $a_i$? My understanding was that $I(a_1,...,a_n)$ is the smallest field containing $I$ and $a_1, ..., a_n$, so that certainly if $L subsetneq I(a_1,...,a_n)$ then there exists an $a_i$ such that $a_i notin L$.
    – WillG
    Jul 18 at 18:08










  • @WillG Yes, of course...and that's the proof! Almost trivial.
    – DonAntonio
    Jul 18 at 19:34










  • I'm still confused then, as to what exactly goes wrong when we try to assert the same "theorem" but without the root field premise, i.e. "Suppose $I subseteq E subseteq K$, where $E$ is a finite extension of $I$ and $K$ is a finite extension of $E$. Then $K$ is the root field of some polynomial over $I$." Is this also true? If not, maybe a counterexample would help me understand what goes wrong...
    – WillG
    Jul 18 at 20:08










  • By all means: take for example $;I=E=Bbb Q;,;;K:=Bbb Q(sqrt[4]2);$ , and $; K;$ is not a splitting field of any irreducible rational polynomial.
    – DonAntonio
    Jul 18 at 21:09











  • Aha. That just blew my mind. I think my confusion was assuming all field extensions of a field $F$ had to be root fields of something over $F$, which clearly is not the case with $mathbbQ(sqrt[4]2)$. But there's one thing I'm still confused about: if $p(x)$ is the minimum polynomial of $a$ over $I$, then yes, its coefficients are in $E$ and it has a root in $K$. But is $p(x)$ necessarily irreducible in $E$? This seems to be required by Theorem 7 (in my comment above).
    – WillG
    Jul 19 at 18:55












up vote
2
down vote










up vote
2
down vote









This answer refers to the theorem as written in the 2nd. edition of Pinter's book:



"Root field" seems to be the same of what many of us call "splitting field": $;K;$ is a root field of some polynomial $;f(x)in I[x];$ means $;K=I(a_1,...,a_n);,;a_1,...,a_n;$ all the roots of $;f(x);$ (in some algebraic closure of $;I;$) and any subfield $;Ile Llneq K;$ fulfills that there exists at least one root $;a_n;$ such that $;a_nnotin L;$.



Observe then that $;f(x)in I[x]subset E[x];$ . Either $;E=K;$ and there's nothing to prove, or else $;Elneq K;$ and thus there is some root of $;f(x);$ whic is not in $;E;implies$ $;K;$ is the splitting field (root filed) of $;f(x);$ as polynomial in $;E[x];$ as $;K;$ contains all the roots of $;f;$ ...






share|cite|improve this answer















This answer refers to the theorem as written in the 2nd. edition of Pinter's book:



"Root field" seems to be the same of what many of us call "splitting field": $;K;$ is a root field of some polynomial $;f(x)in I[x];$ means $;K=I(a_1,...,a_n);,;a_1,...,a_n;$ all the roots of $;f(x);$ (in some algebraic closure of $;I;$) and any subfield $;Ile Llneq K;$ fulfills that there exists at least one root $;a_n;$ such that $;a_nnotin L;$.



Observe then that $;f(x)in I[x]subset E[x];$ . Either $;E=K;$ and there's nothing to prove, or else $;Elneq K;$ and thus there is some root of $;f(x);$ whic is not in $;E;implies$ $;K;$ is the splitting field (root filed) of $;f(x);$ as polynomial in $;E[x];$ as $;K;$ contains all the roots of $;f;$ ...







share|cite|improve this answer















share|cite|improve this answer



share|cite|improve this answer








edited Jul 20 at 9:02


























answered Jul 18 at 17:41









DonAntonio

173k1484218




173k1484218











  • Doesn't the condition $K=I(a_1,...,a_n)$ already guarantee that any strict subfield of K lacks at least one of the $a_i$? My understanding was that $I(a_1,...,a_n)$ is the smallest field containing $I$ and $a_1, ..., a_n$, so that certainly if $L subsetneq I(a_1,...,a_n)$ then there exists an $a_i$ such that $a_i notin L$.
    – WillG
    Jul 18 at 18:08










  • @WillG Yes, of course...and that's the proof! Almost trivial.
    – DonAntonio
    Jul 18 at 19:34










  • I'm still confused then, as to what exactly goes wrong when we try to assert the same "theorem" but without the root field premise, i.e. "Suppose $I subseteq E subseteq K$, where $E$ is a finite extension of $I$ and $K$ is a finite extension of $E$. Then $K$ is the root field of some polynomial over $I$." Is this also true? If not, maybe a counterexample would help me understand what goes wrong...
    – WillG
    Jul 18 at 20:08










  • By all means: take for example $;I=E=Bbb Q;,;;K:=Bbb Q(sqrt[4]2);$ , and $; K;$ is not a splitting field of any irreducible rational polynomial.
    – DonAntonio
    Jul 18 at 21:09











  • Aha. That just blew my mind. I think my confusion was assuming all field extensions of a field $F$ had to be root fields of something over $F$, which clearly is not the case with $mathbbQ(sqrt[4]2)$. But there's one thing I'm still confused about: if $p(x)$ is the minimum polynomial of $a$ over $I$, then yes, its coefficients are in $E$ and it has a root in $K$. But is $p(x)$ necessarily irreducible in $E$? This seems to be required by Theorem 7 (in my comment above).
    – WillG
    Jul 19 at 18:55
















  • Doesn't the condition $K=I(a_1,...,a_n)$ already guarantee that any strict subfield of K lacks at least one of the $a_i$? My understanding was that $I(a_1,...,a_n)$ is the smallest field containing $I$ and $a_1, ..., a_n$, so that certainly if $L subsetneq I(a_1,...,a_n)$ then there exists an $a_i$ such that $a_i notin L$.
    – WillG
    Jul 18 at 18:08










  • @WillG Yes, of course...and that's the proof! Almost trivial.
    – DonAntonio
    Jul 18 at 19:34










  • I'm still confused then, as to what exactly goes wrong when we try to assert the same "theorem" but without the root field premise, i.e. "Suppose $I subseteq E subseteq K$, where $E$ is a finite extension of $I$ and $K$ is a finite extension of $E$. Then $K$ is the root field of some polynomial over $I$." Is this also true? If not, maybe a counterexample would help me understand what goes wrong...
    – WillG
    Jul 18 at 20:08










  • By all means: take for example $;I=E=Bbb Q;,;;K:=Bbb Q(sqrt[4]2);$ , and $; K;$ is not a splitting field of any irreducible rational polynomial.
    – DonAntonio
    Jul 18 at 21:09











  • Aha. That just blew my mind. I think my confusion was assuming all field extensions of a field $F$ had to be root fields of something over $F$, which clearly is not the case with $mathbbQ(sqrt[4]2)$. But there's one thing I'm still confused about: if $p(x)$ is the minimum polynomial of $a$ over $I$, then yes, its coefficients are in $E$ and it has a root in $K$. But is $p(x)$ necessarily irreducible in $E$? This seems to be required by Theorem 7 (in my comment above).
    – WillG
    Jul 19 at 18:55















Doesn't the condition $K=I(a_1,...,a_n)$ already guarantee that any strict subfield of K lacks at least one of the $a_i$? My understanding was that $I(a_1,...,a_n)$ is the smallest field containing $I$ and $a_1, ..., a_n$, so that certainly if $L subsetneq I(a_1,...,a_n)$ then there exists an $a_i$ such that $a_i notin L$.
– WillG
Jul 18 at 18:08




Doesn't the condition $K=I(a_1,...,a_n)$ already guarantee that any strict subfield of K lacks at least one of the $a_i$? My understanding was that $I(a_1,...,a_n)$ is the smallest field containing $I$ and $a_1, ..., a_n$, so that certainly if $L subsetneq I(a_1,...,a_n)$ then there exists an $a_i$ such that $a_i notin L$.
– WillG
Jul 18 at 18:08












@WillG Yes, of course...and that's the proof! Almost trivial.
– DonAntonio
Jul 18 at 19:34




@WillG Yes, of course...and that's the proof! Almost trivial.
– DonAntonio
Jul 18 at 19:34












I'm still confused then, as to what exactly goes wrong when we try to assert the same "theorem" but without the root field premise, i.e. "Suppose $I subseteq E subseteq K$, where $E$ is a finite extension of $I$ and $K$ is a finite extension of $E$. Then $K$ is the root field of some polynomial over $I$." Is this also true? If not, maybe a counterexample would help me understand what goes wrong...
– WillG
Jul 18 at 20:08




I'm still confused then, as to what exactly goes wrong when we try to assert the same "theorem" but without the root field premise, i.e. "Suppose $I subseteq E subseteq K$, where $E$ is a finite extension of $I$ and $K$ is a finite extension of $E$. Then $K$ is the root field of some polynomial over $I$." Is this also true? If not, maybe a counterexample would help me understand what goes wrong...
– WillG
Jul 18 at 20:08












By all means: take for example $;I=E=Bbb Q;,;;K:=Bbb Q(sqrt[4]2);$ , and $; K;$ is not a splitting field of any irreducible rational polynomial.
– DonAntonio
Jul 18 at 21:09





By all means: take for example $;I=E=Bbb Q;,;;K:=Bbb Q(sqrt[4]2);$ , and $; K;$ is not a splitting field of any irreducible rational polynomial.
– DonAntonio
Jul 18 at 21:09













Aha. That just blew my mind. I think my confusion was assuming all field extensions of a field $F$ had to be root fields of something over $F$, which clearly is not the case with $mathbbQ(sqrt[4]2)$. But there's one thing I'm still confused about: if $p(x)$ is the minimum polynomial of $a$ over $I$, then yes, its coefficients are in $E$ and it has a root in $K$. But is $p(x)$ necessarily irreducible in $E$? This seems to be required by Theorem 7 (in my comment above).
– WillG
Jul 19 at 18:55




Aha. That just blew my mind. I think my confusion was assuming all field extensions of a field $F$ had to be root fields of something over $F$, which clearly is not the case with $mathbbQ(sqrt[4]2)$. But there's one thing I'm still confused about: if $p(x)$ is the minimum polynomial of $a$ over $I$, then yes, its coefficients are in $E$ and it has a root in $K$. But is $p(x)$ necessarily irreducible in $E$? This seems to be required by Theorem 7 (in my comment above).
– WillG
Jul 19 at 18:55










up vote
0
down vote



accepted










After reviewing this more, I believe the actual theorem from Pinter is wrong! Counterexample: Let $I=mathbbQ$ and $E=K=mathbbQ(sqrt[4]2)$.



I found the 2nd edition of the same book and discovered the theorem is different:




Suppose $Isubseteq Esubseteq K$ where $E$ is a finite extension of $I$ and $K$ is a finite extension of $E$. If $K$ is the root field of some polynomial over $I$, then $K$ is also the root field of some polynomial over $E$.




This makes much more sense now.






share|cite|improve this answer





















  • I honestly didn't even read your whole question. I simply went to Pinter's book and read from there the theorem, which is the one you mention here (2nd. Edition) and whose proof is pretty trivial. Indeed, the 1st. edition has this theorem wrongly written and, of course, it is false as it appears there.
    – DonAntonio
    Jul 20 at 9:01














up vote
0
down vote



accepted










After reviewing this more, I believe the actual theorem from Pinter is wrong! Counterexample: Let $I=mathbbQ$ and $E=K=mathbbQ(sqrt[4]2)$.



I found the 2nd edition of the same book and discovered the theorem is different:




Suppose $Isubseteq Esubseteq K$ where $E$ is a finite extension of $I$ and $K$ is a finite extension of $E$. If $K$ is the root field of some polynomial over $I$, then $K$ is also the root field of some polynomial over $E$.




This makes much more sense now.






share|cite|improve this answer





















  • I honestly didn't even read your whole question. I simply went to Pinter's book and read from there the theorem, which is the one you mention here (2nd. Edition) and whose proof is pretty trivial. Indeed, the 1st. edition has this theorem wrongly written and, of course, it is false as it appears there.
    – DonAntonio
    Jul 20 at 9:01












up vote
0
down vote



accepted







up vote
0
down vote



accepted






After reviewing this more, I believe the actual theorem from Pinter is wrong! Counterexample: Let $I=mathbbQ$ and $E=K=mathbbQ(sqrt[4]2)$.



I found the 2nd edition of the same book and discovered the theorem is different:




Suppose $Isubseteq Esubseteq K$ where $E$ is a finite extension of $I$ and $K$ is a finite extension of $E$. If $K$ is the root field of some polynomial over $I$, then $K$ is also the root field of some polynomial over $E$.




This makes much more sense now.






share|cite|improve this answer













After reviewing this more, I believe the actual theorem from Pinter is wrong! Counterexample: Let $I=mathbbQ$ and $E=K=mathbbQ(sqrt[4]2)$.



I found the 2nd edition of the same book and discovered the theorem is different:




Suppose $Isubseteq Esubseteq K$ where $E$ is a finite extension of $I$ and $K$ is a finite extension of $E$. If $K$ is the root field of some polynomial over $I$, then $K$ is also the root field of some polynomial over $E$.




This makes much more sense now.







share|cite|improve this answer













share|cite|improve this answer



share|cite|improve this answer











answered Jul 20 at 5:03









WillG

40128




40128











  • I honestly didn't even read your whole question. I simply went to Pinter's book and read from there the theorem, which is the one you mention here (2nd. Edition) and whose proof is pretty trivial. Indeed, the 1st. edition has this theorem wrongly written and, of course, it is false as it appears there.
    – DonAntonio
    Jul 20 at 9:01
















  • I honestly didn't even read your whole question. I simply went to Pinter's book and read from there the theorem, which is the one you mention here (2nd. Edition) and whose proof is pretty trivial. Indeed, the 1st. edition has this theorem wrongly written and, of course, it is false as it appears there.
    – DonAntonio
    Jul 20 at 9:01















I honestly didn't even read your whole question. I simply went to Pinter's book and read from there the theorem, which is the one you mention here (2nd. Edition) and whose proof is pretty trivial. Indeed, the 1st. edition has this theorem wrongly written and, of course, it is false as it appears there.
– DonAntonio
Jul 20 at 9:01




I honestly didn't even read your whole question. I simply went to Pinter's book and read from there the theorem, which is the one you mention here (2nd. Edition) and whose proof is pretty trivial. Indeed, the 1st. edition has this theorem wrongly written and, of course, it is false as it appears there.
– DonAntonio
Jul 20 at 9:01












 

draft saved


draft discarded


























 


draft saved


draft discarded














StackExchange.ready(
function ()
StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmath.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f2855753%2fwhy-is-the-root-field-premise-necessary-in-this-theorem-about-field-extensions%23new-answer', 'question_page');

);

Post as a guest













































































Comments

Popular posts from this blog

What is the equation of a 3D cone with generalised tilt?

Relationship between determinant of matrix and determinant of adjoint?

Color the edges and diagonals of a regular polygon