Does a downward chain of models of ZFC violate the axiom of foundation?
Clash Royale CLAN TAG#URR8PPP
up vote
2
down vote
favorite
Here's an issue I ran into on this MathOverflow thread: https://mathoverflow.net/questions/18787/montagues-reflection-principle-and-compactness-theorem/18804#18804
Likewise, see Joel David Hamkins's answer here: https://mathoverflow.net/questions/15685/is-it-necessary-that-model-of-theory-is-a-set/15713#15713
A final subtle point, which I hesitate to mention because it can be confusing even to experts, is that it is a theorem that every model M of ZFC has an object m inside it which M believes to be a first order structure in the language of set theory, and if we look at m from outside M, and view it as a structure of its own, then m is a model of full ZFC.
In short: we can prove using Levy Reflection that for any model M of ZFC, some element of M satisfies ZFC (although the model may not believe that the structure does). But this seems like a problem for the axiom of foundation: can't we construct a downward chain of membership composed of the first model, the model which is an element of that model, and so on?
The only idea I've come up with is that somehow the descending chain of these submodels is not an element of the starting model M. But it's not clear to me why we couldn't guarantee that it is, by taking some sufficiently expansive initial model like the Von Neumann Universe. Is there a principle reason that the downward chain would not be a member of the universe? Or is there another way of resolving the issue that I've missed?
logic set-theory model-theory
add a comment |Â
up vote
2
down vote
favorite
Here's an issue I ran into on this MathOverflow thread: https://mathoverflow.net/questions/18787/montagues-reflection-principle-and-compactness-theorem/18804#18804
Likewise, see Joel David Hamkins's answer here: https://mathoverflow.net/questions/15685/is-it-necessary-that-model-of-theory-is-a-set/15713#15713
A final subtle point, which I hesitate to mention because it can be confusing even to experts, is that it is a theorem that every model M of ZFC has an object m inside it which M believes to be a first order structure in the language of set theory, and if we look at m from outside M, and view it as a structure of its own, then m is a model of full ZFC.
In short: we can prove using Levy Reflection that for any model M of ZFC, some element of M satisfies ZFC (although the model may not believe that the structure does). But this seems like a problem for the axiom of foundation: can't we construct a downward chain of membership composed of the first model, the model which is an element of that model, and so on?
The only idea I've come up with is that somehow the descending chain of these submodels is not an element of the starting model M. But it's not clear to me why we couldn't guarantee that it is, by taking some sufficiently expansive initial model like the Von Neumann Universe. Is there a principle reason that the downward chain would not be a member of the universe? Or is there another way of resolving the issue that I've missed?
logic set-theory model-theory
7
The model has its own notion of membership, which need not agree with the outer membership. So you are looking at a "chain" $M_1ni M_2ni'M_3ni''dots$ where the membership relation keeps changing, which does not contradict anything.
– Mario Carneiro
Jul 17 at 20:40
@MarioCarneiro can you explain how the membership relation would differ? If $M_1 ni M_2 ni' M_3$ but $neg M_2 ni M_3$, then how is the "membership" relation $in '$ represented in the model $M_1$?
– Spencer
Jul 17 at 20:45
$M_1$ thinks that $(M_2,in')$ is a model of ZFC, so $in'$ is a binary relation on $M_2$ (or at least $M_1$ thinks it is). It is quite possible that $M_1$ also thinks $M_3notin M_2$ but $M_3in' M_2$.
– Mario Carneiro
Jul 17 at 20:49
I think the reflection principle proves something stronger than that, though. Because Levy reflection demonstrates every finite set of axioms has a model with membership interpreted in the same way.
– Spencer
Jul 17 at 20:52
2
True, but any compactness type argument to get a full model will destroy that property.
– Mario Carneiro
Jul 17 at 20:55
add a comment |Â
up vote
2
down vote
favorite
up vote
2
down vote
favorite
Here's an issue I ran into on this MathOverflow thread: https://mathoverflow.net/questions/18787/montagues-reflection-principle-and-compactness-theorem/18804#18804
Likewise, see Joel David Hamkins's answer here: https://mathoverflow.net/questions/15685/is-it-necessary-that-model-of-theory-is-a-set/15713#15713
A final subtle point, which I hesitate to mention because it can be confusing even to experts, is that it is a theorem that every model M of ZFC has an object m inside it which M believes to be a first order structure in the language of set theory, and if we look at m from outside M, and view it as a structure of its own, then m is a model of full ZFC.
In short: we can prove using Levy Reflection that for any model M of ZFC, some element of M satisfies ZFC (although the model may not believe that the structure does). But this seems like a problem for the axiom of foundation: can't we construct a downward chain of membership composed of the first model, the model which is an element of that model, and so on?
The only idea I've come up with is that somehow the descending chain of these submodels is not an element of the starting model M. But it's not clear to me why we couldn't guarantee that it is, by taking some sufficiently expansive initial model like the Von Neumann Universe. Is there a principle reason that the downward chain would not be a member of the universe? Or is there another way of resolving the issue that I've missed?
logic set-theory model-theory
Here's an issue I ran into on this MathOverflow thread: https://mathoverflow.net/questions/18787/montagues-reflection-principle-and-compactness-theorem/18804#18804
Likewise, see Joel David Hamkins's answer here: https://mathoverflow.net/questions/15685/is-it-necessary-that-model-of-theory-is-a-set/15713#15713
A final subtle point, which I hesitate to mention because it can be confusing even to experts, is that it is a theorem that every model M of ZFC has an object m inside it which M believes to be a first order structure in the language of set theory, and if we look at m from outside M, and view it as a structure of its own, then m is a model of full ZFC.
In short: we can prove using Levy Reflection that for any model M of ZFC, some element of M satisfies ZFC (although the model may not believe that the structure does). But this seems like a problem for the axiom of foundation: can't we construct a downward chain of membership composed of the first model, the model which is an element of that model, and so on?
The only idea I've come up with is that somehow the descending chain of these submodels is not an element of the starting model M. But it's not clear to me why we couldn't guarantee that it is, by taking some sufficiently expansive initial model like the Von Neumann Universe. Is there a principle reason that the downward chain would not be a member of the universe? Or is there another way of resolving the issue that I've missed?
logic set-theory model-theory
asked Jul 17 at 20:38
Spencer
1678
1678
7
The model has its own notion of membership, which need not agree with the outer membership. So you are looking at a "chain" $M_1ni M_2ni'M_3ni''dots$ where the membership relation keeps changing, which does not contradict anything.
– Mario Carneiro
Jul 17 at 20:40
@MarioCarneiro can you explain how the membership relation would differ? If $M_1 ni M_2 ni' M_3$ but $neg M_2 ni M_3$, then how is the "membership" relation $in '$ represented in the model $M_1$?
– Spencer
Jul 17 at 20:45
$M_1$ thinks that $(M_2,in')$ is a model of ZFC, so $in'$ is a binary relation on $M_2$ (or at least $M_1$ thinks it is). It is quite possible that $M_1$ also thinks $M_3notin M_2$ but $M_3in' M_2$.
– Mario Carneiro
Jul 17 at 20:49
I think the reflection principle proves something stronger than that, though. Because Levy reflection demonstrates every finite set of axioms has a model with membership interpreted in the same way.
– Spencer
Jul 17 at 20:52
2
True, but any compactness type argument to get a full model will destroy that property.
– Mario Carneiro
Jul 17 at 20:55
add a comment |Â
7
The model has its own notion of membership, which need not agree with the outer membership. So you are looking at a "chain" $M_1ni M_2ni'M_3ni''dots$ where the membership relation keeps changing, which does not contradict anything.
– Mario Carneiro
Jul 17 at 20:40
@MarioCarneiro can you explain how the membership relation would differ? If $M_1 ni M_2 ni' M_3$ but $neg M_2 ni M_3$, then how is the "membership" relation $in '$ represented in the model $M_1$?
– Spencer
Jul 17 at 20:45
$M_1$ thinks that $(M_2,in')$ is a model of ZFC, so $in'$ is a binary relation on $M_2$ (or at least $M_1$ thinks it is). It is quite possible that $M_1$ also thinks $M_3notin M_2$ but $M_3in' M_2$.
– Mario Carneiro
Jul 17 at 20:49
I think the reflection principle proves something stronger than that, though. Because Levy reflection demonstrates every finite set of axioms has a model with membership interpreted in the same way.
– Spencer
Jul 17 at 20:52
2
True, but any compactness type argument to get a full model will destroy that property.
– Mario Carneiro
Jul 17 at 20:55
7
7
The model has its own notion of membership, which need not agree with the outer membership. So you are looking at a "chain" $M_1ni M_2ni'M_3ni''dots$ where the membership relation keeps changing, which does not contradict anything.
– Mario Carneiro
Jul 17 at 20:40
The model has its own notion of membership, which need not agree with the outer membership. So you are looking at a "chain" $M_1ni M_2ni'M_3ni''dots$ where the membership relation keeps changing, which does not contradict anything.
– Mario Carneiro
Jul 17 at 20:40
@MarioCarneiro can you explain how the membership relation would differ? If $M_1 ni M_2 ni' M_3$ but $neg M_2 ni M_3$, then how is the "membership" relation $in '$ represented in the model $M_1$?
– Spencer
Jul 17 at 20:45
@MarioCarneiro can you explain how the membership relation would differ? If $M_1 ni M_2 ni' M_3$ but $neg M_2 ni M_3$, then how is the "membership" relation $in '$ represented in the model $M_1$?
– Spencer
Jul 17 at 20:45
$M_1$ thinks that $(M_2,in')$ is a model of ZFC, so $in'$ is a binary relation on $M_2$ (or at least $M_1$ thinks it is). It is quite possible that $M_1$ also thinks $M_3notin M_2$ but $M_3in' M_2$.
– Mario Carneiro
Jul 17 at 20:49
$M_1$ thinks that $(M_2,in')$ is a model of ZFC, so $in'$ is a binary relation on $M_2$ (or at least $M_1$ thinks it is). It is quite possible that $M_1$ also thinks $M_3notin M_2$ but $M_3in' M_2$.
– Mario Carneiro
Jul 17 at 20:49
I think the reflection principle proves something stronger than that, though. Because Levy reflection demonstrates every finite set of axioms has a model with membership interpreted in the same way.
– Spencer
Jul 17 at 20:52
I think the reflection principle proves something stronger than that, though. Because Levy reflection demonstrates every finite set of axioms has a model with membership interpreted in the same way.
– Spencer
Jul 17 at 20:52
2
2
True, but any compactness type argument to get a full model will destroy that property.
– Mario Carneiro
Jul 17 at 20:55
True, but any compactness type argument to get a full model will destroy that property.
– Mario Carneiro
Jul 17 at 20:55
add a comment |Â
1 Answer
1
active
oldest
votes
up vote
6
down vote
accepted
No, it doesn't. The quick slogan is "tables, chairs, and beer mugs" - when we speak of a model of set theory (within an ambeint model $M$), the membership relation of that model need have nothing to do with actual membership (in the sense of $M$), so "$ain^b bin^MM$" doesn't let us conclude anything about whether $ain^Mb$ or not.
More explicitly: when we say that $M$ contains an $in$-structure (a model of set theory or otherwise) such that [stuff], all we mean is that there is some $ain M$ such that $M$ thinks "$a$ is an ordered pair $(x, e)$, where $e$ is a binary relation on $x$ and $x$ is nonempty" (nonemptiness is only an issue since the semantics of first-order logic rules out empty structures) such that [stuff].$^*$ Now $a$, as a structure, may itself "contain a structure" in the sense that there may be some $bin^M x$ such that according to $a$, $b$ is an ordered pair $(y, f)$ where $f$ is a binary relation on $y$ and $ynot=emptyset$. But note that since $a$'s membership relation is $e$, from the perspective of $M$ (and $in^M$) $b$ might not look anything like what $a$ thinks $b$ looks like.
For example, take $M$ to be $V$ for simplicity; then for any countably infinite $in$-structure $mathfrakS$ and any countably infinite set $A$, there is a binary relation $Esubseteq A^2$ such that $(A, E)congmathfrakS$. But of course $E$ need look nothing at all like $in$.
For a more concrete example - again, working in $V$ for simplicity - let $x=emptyset$ and $e=emptyset$. Then:
In $V$, $x$ is nonempty and $e$ is a set of ordered pairs of elements of $x$ (specifically, $e=langle emptyset,emptysetrangle$).
This means that $a:=(x,e)$ is an $in$-structure.
In the sense of $a$, we have that $emptyset$ (by which I mean, and will continue to mean, $emptyset^V$) is an ordered pair whose left coordinate, $emptyset$, is nonempty (it has precisely one element, namely itself) and whose right coordinate, $emptyset$, is a set of ordered pairs of elements of the left coordinate (it consists of a single ordered pair, saying that $emptyset$ is related to $emptyset$).
We can repeat this analysis, and show that in the sense of $a$ it is the case that in the sense of $emptyset$ it is the case that $emptyset$ is an $in$-structure. Note that in the sense of $a$, $emptyset$ is an element of $emptyset$.
However, in the sense of $V$ the set $emptyset$ is certainly not an $in$-structure at all, let alone one that contains a further $in$-structure, let alone one which contains itself as a further $in$-structure.
$^*$This isn't quite the right general approach, since we will usually want the ability to distinguish between different binary relation symbols, but this restrictive approach is sufficient for the current question and is easier to think about.
Sorry, one confusion on this: what is happening when some element is a model of ZFC under the "canonical" ordering: i.e. if we consider $V_kappa$ for some inaccessible $kappa$, how does this fit into the idea that models of set theory are ordered pairs $(M,in)$? Can we somehow infer that the membership relation on $V_kappa$ (understood as a set) is also in the model?
– Spencer
Jul 20 at 3:40
A reader not familiar with David Hilbert's famous lecture could be puzzled by your "tables, chairs, and beer mugs". Perhaps you could add a sentence or a phrase to elucidate it.
– DanielWainfleet
Jul 24 at 18:18
To the proposer. Re: Your comment to this A: "The idea that models of set theory are ordered pairs $(M,in) $". What idea? A model is $(M,in^*),$ and $in^*$ may fail to be well-founded. Assuming that ZFC has a well-founded model is a stronger assumption than that there is a model... If $k$ is the least inaccessible then $(V_k,in)$ is a well-founded model but a model $(M,in^*)$ of ZFC that belongs to $V_k$ need not be well-founded.
– DanielWainfleet
Jul 24 at 18:38
add a comment |Â
1 Answer
1
active
oldest
votes
1 Answer
1
active
oldest
votes
active
oldest
votes
active
oldest
votes
up vote
6
down vote
accepted
No, it doesn't. The quick slogan is "tables, chairs, and beer mugs" - when we speak of a model of set theory (within an ambeint model $M$), the membership relation of that model need have nothing to do with actual membership (in the sense of $M$), so "$ain^b bin^MM$" doesn't let us conclude anything about whether $ain^Mb$ or not.
More explicitly: when we say that $M$ contains an $in$-structure (a model of set theory or otherwise) such that [stuff], all we mean is that there is some $ain M$ such that $M$ thinks "$a$ is an ordered pair $(x, e)$, where $e$ is a binary relation on $x$ and $x$ is nonempty" (nonemptiness is only an issue since the semantics of first-order logic rules out empty structures) such that [stuff].$^*$ Now $a$, as a structure, may itself "contain a structure" in the sense that there may be some $bin^M x$ such that according to $a$, $b$ is an ordered pair $(y, f)$ where $f$ is a binary relation on $y$ and $ynot=emptyset$. But note that since $a$'s membership relation is $e$, from the perspective of $M$ (and $in^M$) $b$ might not look anything like what $a$ thinks $b$ looks like.
For example, take $M$ to be $V$ for simplicity; then for any countably infinite $in$-structure $mathfrakS$ and any countably infinite set $A$, there is a binary relation $Esubseteq A^2$ such that $(A, E)congmathfrakS$. But of course $E$ need look nothing at all like $in$.
For a more concrete example - again, working in $V$ for simplicity - let $x=emptyset$ and $e=emptyset$. Then:
In $V$, $x$ is nonempty and $e$ is a set of ordered pairs of elements of $x$ (specifically, $e=langle emptyset,emptysetrangle$).
This means that $a:=(x,e)$ is an $in$-structure.
In the sense of $a$, we have that $emptyset$ (by which I mean, and will continue to mean, $emptyset^V$) is an ordered pair whose left coordinate, $emptyset$, is nonempty (it has precisely one element, namely itself) and whose right coordinate, $emptyset$, is a set of ordered pairs of elements of the left coordinate (it consists of a single ordered pair, saying that $emptyset$ is related to $emptyset$).
We can repeat this analysis, and show that in the sense of $a$ it is the case that in the sense of $emptyset$ it is the case that $emptyset$ is an $in$-structure. Note that in the sense of $a$, $emptyset$ is an element of $emptyset$.
However, in the sense of $V$ the set $emptyset$ is certainly not an $in$-structure at all, let alone one that contains a further $in$-structure, let alone one which contains itself as a further $in$-structure.
$^*$This isn't quite the right general approach, since we will usually want the ability to distinguish between different binary relation symbols, but this restrictive approach is sufficient for the current question and is easier to think about.
Sorry, one confusion on this: what is happening when some element is a model of ZFC under the "canonical" ordering: i.e. if we consider $V_kappa$ for some inaccessible $kappa$, how does this fit into the idea that models of set theory are ordered pairs $(M,in)$? Can we somehow infer that the membership relation on $V_kappa$ (understood as a set) is also in the model?
– Spencer
Jul 20 at 3:40
A reader not familiar with David Hilbert's famous lecture could be puzzled by your "tables, chairs, and beer mugs". Perhaps you could add a sentence or a phrase to elucidate it.
– DanielWainfleet
Jul 24 at 18:18
To the proposer. Re: Your comment to this A: "The idea that models of set theory are ordered pairs $(M,in) $". What idea? A model is $(M,in^*),$ and $in^*$ may fail to be well-founded. Assuming that ZFC has a well-founded model is a stronger assumption than that there is a model... If $k$ is the least inaccessible then $(V_k,in)$ is a well-founded model but a model $(M,in^*)$ of ZFC that belongs to $V_k$ need not be well-founded.
– DanielWainfleet
Jul 24 at 18:38
add a comment |Â
up vote
6
down vote
accepted
No, it doesn't. The quick slogan is "tables, chairs, and beer mugs" - when we speak of a model of set theory (within an ambeint model $M$), the membership relation of that model need have nothing to do with actual membership (in the sense of $M$), so "$ain^b bin^MM$" doesn't let us conclude anything about whether $ain^Mb$ or not.
More explicitly: when we say that $M$ contains an $in$-structure (a model of set theory or otherwise) such that [stuff], all we mean is that there is some $ain M$ such that $M$ thinks "$a$ is an ordered pair $(x, e)$, where $e$ is a binary relation on $x$ and $x$ is nonempty" (nonemptiness is only an issue since the semantics of first-order logic rules out empty structures) such that [stuff].$^*$ Now $a$, as a structure, may itself "contain a structure" in the sense that there may be some $bin^M x$ such that according to $a$, $b$ is an ordered pair $(y, f)$ where $f$ is a binary relation on $y$ and $ynot=emptyset$. But note that since $a$'s membership relation is $e$, from the perspective of $M$ (and $in^M$) $b$ might not look anything like what $a$ thinks $b$ looks like.
For example, take $M$ to be $V$ for simplicity; then for any countably infinite $in$-structure $mathfrakS$ and any countably infinite set $A$, there is a binary relation $Esubseteq A^2$ such that $(A, E)congmathfrakS$. But of course $E$ need look nothing at all like $in$.
For a more concrete example - again, working in $V$ for simplicity - let $x=emptyset$ and $e=emptyset$. Then:
In $V$, $x$ is nonempty and $e$ is a set of ordered pairs of elements of $x$ (specifically, $e=langle emptyset,emptysetrangle$).
This means that $a:=(x,e)$ is an $in$-structure.
In the sense of $a$, we have that $emptyset$ (by which I mean, and will continue to mean, $emptyset^V$) is an ordered pair whose left coordinate, $emptyset$, is nonempty (it has precisely one element, namely itself) and whose right coordinate, $emptyset$, is a set of ordered pairs of elements of the left coordinate (it consists of a single ordered pair, saying that $emptyset$ is related to $emptyset$).
We can repeat this analysis, and show that in the sense of $a$ it is the case that in the sense of $emptyset$ it is the case that $emptyset$ is an $in$-structure. Note that in the sense of $a$, $emptyset$ is an element of $emptyset$.
However, in the sense of $V$ the set $emptyset$ is certainly not an $in$-structure at all, let alone one that contains a further $in$-structure, let alone one which contains itself as a further $in$-structure.
$^*$This isn't quite the right general approach, since we will usually want the ability to distinguish between different binary relation symbols, but this restrictive approach is sufficient for the current question and is easier to think about.
Sorry, one confusion on this: what is happening when some element is a model of ZFC under the "canonical" ordering: i.e. if we consider $V_kappa$ for some inaccessible $kappa$, how does this fit into the idea that models of set theory are ordered pairs $(M,in)$? Can we somehow infer that the membership relation on $V_kappa$ (understood as a set) is also in the model?
– Spencer
Jul 20 at 3:40
A reader not familiar with David Hilbert's famous lecture could be puzzled by your "tables, chairs, and beer mugs". Perhaps you could add a sentence or a phrase to elucidate it.
– DanielWainfleet
Jul 24 at 18:18
To the proposer. Re: Your comment to this A: "The idea that models of set theory are ordered pairs $(M,in) $". What idea? A model is $(M,in^*),$ and $in^*$ may fail to be well-founded. Assuming that ZFC has a well-founded model is a stronger assumption than that there is a model... If $k$ is the least inaccessible then $(V_k,in)$ is a well-founded model but a model $(M,in^*)$ of ZFC that belongs to $V_k$ need not be well-founded.
– DanielWainfleet
Jul 24 at 18:38
add a comment |Â
up vote
6
down vote
accepted
up vote
6
down vote
accepted
No, it doesn't. The quick slogan is "tables, chairs, and beer mugs" - when we speak of a model of set theory (within an ambeint model $M$), the membership relation of that model need have nothing to do with actual membership (in the sense of $M$), so "$ain^b bin^MM$" doesn't let us conclude anything about whether $ain^Mb$ or not.
More explicitly: when we say that $M$ contains an $in$-structure (a model of set theory or otherwise) such that [stuff], all we mean is that there is some $ain M$ such that $M$ thinks "$a$ is an ordered pair $(x, e)$, where $e$ is a binary relation on $x$ and $x$ is nonempty" (nonemptiness is only an issue since the semantics of first-order logic rules out empty structures) such that [stuff].$^*$ Now $a$, as a structure, may itself "contain a structure" in the sense that there may be some $bin^M x$ such that according to $a$, $b$ is an ordered pair $(y, f)$ where $f$ is a binary relation on $y$ and $ynot=emptyset$. But note that since $a$'s membership relation is $e$, from the perspective of $M$ (and $in^M$) $b$ might not look anything like what $a$ thinks $b$ looks like.
For example, take $M$ to be $V$ for simplicity; then for any countably infinite $in$-structure $mathfrakS$ and any countably infinite set $A$, there is a binary relation $Esubseteq A^2$ such that $(A, E)congmathfrakS$. But of course $E$ need look nothing at all like $in$.
For a more concrete example - again, working in $V$ for simplicity - let $x=emptyset$ and $e=emptyset$. Then:
In $V$, $x$ is nonempty and $e$ is a set of ordered pairs of elements of $x$ (specifically, $e=langle emptyset,emptysetrangle$).
This means that $a:=(x,e)$ is an $in$-structure.
In the sense of $a$, we have that $emptyset$ (by which I mean, and will continue to mean, $emptyset^V$) is an ordered pair whose left coordinate, $emptyset$, is nonempty (it has precisely one element, namely itself) and whose right coordinate, $emptyset$, is a set of ordered pairs of elements of the left coordinate (it consists of a single ordered pair, saying that $emptyset$ is related to $emptyset$).
We can repeat this analysis, and show that in the sense of $a$ it is the case that in the sense of $emptyset$ it is the case that $emptyset$ is an $in$-structure. Note that in the sense of $a$, $emptyset$ is an element of $emptyset$.
However, in the sense of $V$ the set $emptyset$ is certainly not an $in$-structure at all, let alone one that contains a further $in$-structure, let alone one which contains itself as a further $in$-structure.
$^*$This isn't quite the right general approach, since we will usually want the ability to distinguish between different binary relation symbols, but this restrictive approach is sufficient for the current question and is easier to think about.
No, it doesn't. The quick slogan is "tables, chairs, and beer mugs" - when we speak of a model of set theory (within an ambeint model $M$), the membership relation of that model need have nothing to do with actual membership (in the sense of $M$), so "$ain^b bin^MM$" doesn't let us conclude anything about whether $ain^Mb$ or not.
More explicitly: when we say that $M$ contains an $in$-structure (a model of set theory or otherwise) such that [stuff], all we mean is that there is some $ain M$ such that $M$ thinks "$a$ is an ordered pair $(x, e)$, where $e$ is a binary relation on $x$ and $x$ is nonempty" (nonemptiness is only an issue since the semantics of first-order logic rules out empty structures) such that [stuff].$^*$ Now $a$, as a structure, may itself "contain a structure" in the sense that there may be some $bin^M x$ such that according to $a$, $b$ is an ordered pair $(y, f)$ where $f$ is a binary relation on $y$ and $ynot=emptyset$. But note that since $a$'s membership relation is $e$, from the perspective of $M$ (and $in^M$) $b$ might not look anything like what $a$ thinks $b$ looks like.
For example, take $M$ to be $V$ for simplicity; then for any countably infinite $in$-structure $mathfrakS$ and any countably infinite set $A$, there is a binary relation $Esubseteq A^2$ such that $(A, E)congmathfrakS$. But of course $E$ need look nothing at all like $in$.
For a more concrete example - again, working in $V$ for simplicity - let $x=emptyset$ and $e=emptyset$. Then:
In $V$, $x$ is nonempty and $e$ is a set of ordered pairs of elements of $x$ (specifically, $e=langle emptyset,emptysetrangle$).
This means that $a:=(x,e)$ is an $in$-structure.
In the sense of $a$, we have that $emptyset$ (by which I mean, and will continue to mean, $emptyset^V$) is an ordered pair whose left coordinate, $emptyset$, is nonempty (it has precisely one element, namely itself) and whose right coordinate, $emptyset$, is a set of ordered pairs of elements of the left coordinate (it consists of a single ordered pair, saying that $emptyset$ is related to $emptyset$).
We can repeat this analysis, and show that in the sense of $a$ it is the case that in the sense of $emptyset$ it is the case that $emptyset$ is an $in$-structure. Note that in the sense of $a$, $emptyset$ is an element of $emptyset$.
However, in the sense of $V$ the set $emptyset$ is certainly not an $in$-structure at all, let alone one that contains a further $in$-structure, let alone one which contains itself as a further $in$-structure.
$^*$This isn't quite the right general approach, since we will usually want the ability to distinguish between different binary relation symbols, but this restrictive approach is sufficient for the current question and is easier to think about.
answered Jul 19 at 18:46
Noah Schweber
111k9140263
111k9140263
Sorry, one confusion on this: what is happening when some element is a model of ZFC under the "canonical" ordering: i.e. if we consider $V_kappa$ for some inaccessible $kappa$, how does this fit into the idea that models of set theory are ordered pairs $(M,in)$? Can we somehow infer that the membership relation on $V_kappa$ (understood as a set) is also in the model?
– Spencer
Jul 20 at 3:40
A reader not familiar with David Hilbert's famous lecture could be puzzled by your "tables, chairs, and beer mugs". Perhaps you could add a sentence or a phrase to elucidate it.
– DanielWainfleet
Jul 24 at 18:18
To the proposer. Re: Your comment to this A: "The idea that models of set theory are ordered pairs $(M,in) $". What idea? A model is $(M,in^*),$ and $in^*$ may fail to be well-founded. Assuming that ZFC has a well-founded model is a stronger assumption than that there is a model... If $k$ is the least inaccessible then $(V_k,in)$ is a well-founded model but a model $(M,in^*)$ of ZFC that belongs to $V_k$ need not be well-founded.
– DanielWainfleet
Jul 24 at 18:38
add a comment |Â
Sorry, one confusion on this: what is happening when some element is a model of ZFC under the "canonical" ordering: i.e. if we consider $V_kappa$ for some inaccessible $kappa$, how does this fit into the idea that models of set theory are ordered pairs $(M,in)$? Can we somehow infer that the membership relation on $V_kappa$ (understood as a set) is also in the model?
– Spencer
Jul 20 at 3:40
A reader not familiar with David Hilbert's famous lecture could be puzzled by your "tables, chairs, and beer mugs". Perhaps you could add a sentence or a phrase to elucidate it.
– DanielWainfleet
Jul 24 at 18:18
To the proposer. Re: Your comment to this A: "The idea that models of set theory are ordered pairs $(M,in) $". What idea? A model is $(M,in^*),$ and $in^*$ may fail to be well-founded. Assuming that ZFC has a well-founded model is a stronger assumption than that there is a model... If $k$ is the least inaccessible then $(V_k,in)$ is a well-founded model but a model $(M,in^*)$ of ZFC that belongs to $V_k$ need not be well-founded.
– DanielWainfleet
Jul 24 at 18:38
Sorry, one confusion on this: what is happening when some element is a model of ZFC under the "canonical" ordering: i.e. if we consider $V_kappa$ for some inaccessible $kappa$, how does this fit into the idea that models of set theory are ordered pairs $(M,in)$? Can we somehow infer that the membership relation on $V_kappa$ (understood as a set) is also in the model?
– Spencer
Jul 20 at 3:40
Sorry, one confusion on this: what is happening when some element is a model of ZFC under the "canonical" ordering: i.e. if we consider $V_kappa$ for some inaccessible $kappa$, how does this fit into the idea that models of set theory are ordered pairs $(M,in)$? Can we somehow infer that the membership relation on $V_kappa$ (understood as a set) is also in the model?
– Spencer
Jul 20 at 3:40
A reader not familiar with David Hilbert's famous lecture could be puzzled by your "tables, chairs, and beer mugs". Perhaps you could add a sentence or a phrase to elucidate it.
– DanielWainfleet
Jul 24 at 18:18
A reader not familiar with David Hilbert's famous lecture could be puzzled by your "tables, chairs, and beer mugs". Perhaps you could add a sentence or a phrase to elucidate it.
– DanielWainfleet
Jul 24 at 18:18
To the proposer. Re: Your comment to this A: "The idea that models of set theory are ordered pairs $(M,in) $". What idea? A model is $(M,in^*),$ and $in^*$ may fail to be well-founded. Assuming that ZFC has a well-founded model is a stronger assumption than that there is a model... If $k$ is the least inaccessible then $(V_k,in)$ is a well-founded model but a model $(M,in^*)$ of ZFC that belongs to $V_k$ need not be well-founded.
– DanielWainfleet
Jul 24 at 18:38
To the proposer. Re: Your comment to this A: "The idea that models of set theory are ordered pairs $(M,in) $". What idea? A model is $(M,in^*),$ and $in^*$ may fail to be well-founded. Assuming that ZFC has a well-founded model is a stronger assumption than that there is a model... If $k$ is the least inaccessible then $(V_k,in)$ is a well-founded model but a model $(M,in^*)$ of ZFC that belongs to $V_k$ need not be well-founded.
– DanielWainfleet
Jul 24 at 18:38
add a comment |Â
Sign up or log in
StackExchange.ready(function ()
StackExchange.helpers.onClickDraftSave('#login-link');
);
Sign up using Google
Sign up using Facebook
Sign up using Email and Password
Post as a guest
StackExchange.ready(
function ()
StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmath.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f2854898%2fdoes-a-downward-chain-of-models-of-zfc-violate-the-axiom-of-foundation%23new-answer', 'question_page');
);
Post as a guest
Sign up or log in
StackExchange.ready(function ()
StackExchange.helpers.onClickDraftSave('#login-link');
);
Sign up using Google
Sign up using Facebook
Sign up using Email and Password
Post as a guest
Sign up or log in
StackExchange.ready(function ()
StackExchange.helpers.onClickDraftSave('#login-link');
);
Sign up using Google
Sign up using Facebook
Sign up using Email and Password
Post as a guest
Sign up or log in
StackExchange.ready(function ()
StackExchange.helpers.onClickDraftSave('#login-link');
);
Sign up using Google
Sign up using Facebook
Sign up using Email and Password
Sign up using Google
Sign up using Facebook
Sign up using Email and Password
7
The model has its own notion of membership, which need not agree with the outer membership. So you are looking at a "chain" $M_1ni M_2ni'M_3ni''dots$ where the membership relation keeps changing, which does not contradict anything.
– Mario Carneiro
Jul 17 at 20:40
@MarioCarneiro can you explain how the membership relation would differ? If $M_1 ni M_2 ni' M_3$ but $neg M_2 ni M_3$, then how is the "membership" relation $in '$ represented in the model $M_1$?
– Spencer
Jul 17 at 20:45
$M_1$ thinks that $(M_2,in')$ is a model of ZFC, so $in'$ is a binary relation on $M_2$ (or at least $M_1$ thinks it is). It is quite possible that $M_1$ also thinks $M_3notin M_2$ but $M_3in' M_2$.
– Mario Carneiro
Jul 17 at 20:49
I think the reflection principle proves something stronger than that, though. Because Levy reflection demonstrates every finite set of axioms has a model with membership interpreted in the same way.
– Spencer
Jul 17 at 20:52
2
True, but any compactness type argument to get a full model will destroy that property.
– Mario Carneiro
Jul 17 at 20:55