Non-atomicity of the uniform measure space on $(0, 1]$.

The name of the pictureThe name of the pictureThe name of the pictureClash Royale CLAN TAG#URR8PPP











up vote
1
down vote

favorite












I was working on the following exercise:




Show that $((0,1], mathcalB_(0, 1], U)$ defines a non-atomic measure space.




Above, $mathcalB$ denotes the Borel $sigma$-algebra, and $U$ denotes Lebesgue measure restricted to this sub-$sigma$-algebra of $mathcalB_mathbfR$. Importantly, all I know about $U$ (for the purposes of this problem) is that (1) it is a measure, and (2) it is the unique measure such that if $A = cup_n=1^N (a_n, b_n] subset (0, 1]$, where $N in mathbfN$ and the intervals are disjoint, then $U(A) = sum_n=1^N (b_n - a_n)$. [In words, "$U$ is finitely-additive over disjoint, finite unions of half-open sub-intervals of $(0, 1]$"]



In working on the exercise, I thought it would be useful to try to prove a property about the measure on the entire $mathcalB_(0, 1]$. Suppose in fact it is true that for any measurable $A$,



$$
U(A) = supleft U(I) : I subseteq A, text$I$ is a disjoint finite union of half-open sub-intervals of $(0, 1]$right
$$



If this statement is true, then the claim follows: if I set $epsilon > 0$, then I get the following approximation result:
$$
exists A supseteq I = cup_n=1^N (a_n, b_n] text (disj.): qquad U(A) - epsilon < U(I) = sum_n=1^N (b_n - a_n).
$$
Suppose now that $U(A) > 0$. If I take $epsilon = U(A)/2$, then
this says there exists a set $C = cup_n=1^N (a_n, b_n] subset A$, such
that $U(C) > U(A)/2$. Additionally $U(C) leq U(A)$ since $C subseteq A$.
Now set $B = cup_n=1^N (a_n/2, b_n/2]$. Then $B subsetneq A$, and since everything has positive measure, the strict inequalities
$$
O < U(B) < U(A)
$$
follow.



So the questions I have are



  1. Am I on the right track here? Maybe this supremum approximation argument is overkill.

  2. If this seems like a good approach, I'm struggling a bit to show that the equality holds. In particular if we fix $A$ measurable, and let $S$ denote the RHS (the supremum), then the inequality $U(A) geq S$ is immediate, since the sup is occurring over sets $B$ all of which satisfy $U(A) geq U(B)$ as $B subseteq A$. So the real part that I could use help with is demonstrating $U(A) leq S$. Again if this seems like the right thing to look at, I just want a hint.






share|cite|improve this question















  • 1




    Unfortunately your expression for $U(A)$ is incorrect. If $A$ has no interior points the supremum will be zero.
    – Umberto P.
    Jul 16 at 18:26














up vote
1
down vote

favorite












I was working on the following exercise:




Show that $((0,1], mathcalB_(0, 1], U)$ defines a non-atomic measure space.




Above, $mathcalB$ denotes the Borel $sigma$-algebra, and $U$ denotes Lebesgue measure restricted to this sub-$sigma$-algebra of $mathcalB_mathbfR$. Importantly, all I know about $U$ (for the purposes of this problem) is that (1) it is a measure, and (2) it is the unique measure such that if $A = cup_n=1^N (a_n, b_n] subset (0, 1]$, where $N in mathbfN$ and the intervals are disjoint, then $U(A) = sum_n=1^N (b_n - a_n)$. [In words, "$U$ is finitely-additive over disjoint, finite unions of half-open sub-intervals of $(0, 1]$"]



In working on the exercise, I thought it would be useful to try to prove a property about the measure on the entire $mathcalB_(0, 1]$. Suppose in fact it is true that for any measurable $A$,



$$
U(A) = supleft U(I) : I subseteq A, text$I$ is a disjoint finite union of half-open sub-intervals of $(0, 1]$right
$$



If this statement is true, then the claim follows: if I set $epsilon > 0$, then I get the following approximation result:
$$
exists A supseteq I = cup_n=1^N (a_n, b_n] text (disj.): qquad U(A) - epsilon < U(I) = sum_n=1^N (b_n - a_n).
$$
Suppose now that $U(A) > 0$. If I take $epsilon = U(A)/2$, then
this says there exists a set $C = cup_n=1^N (a_n, b_n] subset A$, such
that $U(C) > U(A)/2$. Additionally $U(C) leq U(A)$ since $C subseteq A$.
Now set $B = cup_n=1^N (a_n/2, b_n/2]$. Then $B subsetneq A$, and since everything has positive measure, the strict inequalities
$$
O < U(B) < U(A)
$$
follow.



So the questions I have are



  1. Am I on the right track here? Maybe this supremum approximation argument is overkill.

  2. If this seems like a good approach, I'm struggling a bit to show that the equality holds. In particular if we fix $A$ measurable, and let $S$ denote the RHS (the supremum), then the inequality $U(A) geq S$ is immediate, since the sup is occurring over sets $B$ all of which satisfy $U(A) geq U(B)$ as $B subseteq A$. So the real part that I could use help with is demonstrating $U(A) leq S$. Again if this seems like the right thing to look at, I just want a hint.






share|cite|improve this question















  • 1




    Unfortunately your expression for $U(A)$ is incorrect. If $A$ has no interior points the supremum will be zero.
    – Umberto P.
    Jul 16 at 18:26












up vote
1
down vote

favorite









up vote
1
down vote

favorite











I was working on the following exercise:




Show that $((0,1], mathcalB_(0, 1], U)$ defines a non-atomic measure space.




Above, $mathcalB$ denotes the Borel $sigma$-algebra, and $U$ denotes Lebesgue measure restricted to this sub-$sigma$-algebra of $mathcalB_mathbfR$. Importantly, all I know about $U$ (for the purposes of this problem) is that (1) it is a measure, and (2) it is the unique measure such that if $A = cup_n=1^N (a_n, b_n] subset (0, 1]$, where $N in mathbfN$ and the intervals are disjoint, then $U(A) = sum_n=1^N (b_n - a_n)$. [In words, "$U$ is finitely-additive over disjoint, finite unions of half-open sub-intervals of $(0, 1]$"]



In working on the exercise, I thought it would be useful to try to prove a property about the measure on the entire $mathcalB_(0, 1]$. Suppose in fact it is true that for any measurable $A$,



$$
U(A) = supleft U(I) : I subseteq A, text$I$ is a disjoint finite union of half-open sub-intervals of $(0, 1]$right
$$



If this statement is true, then the claim follows: if I set $epsilon > 0$, then I get the following approximation result:
$$
exists A supseteq I = cup_n=1^N (a_n, b_n] text (disj.): qquad U(A) - epsilon < U(I) = sum_n=1^N (b_n - a_n).
$$
Suppose now that $U(A) > 0$. If I take $epsilon = U(A)/2$, then
this says there exists a set $C = cup_n=1^N (a_n, b_n] subset A$, such
that $U(C) > U(A)/2$. Additionally $U(C) leq U(A)$ since $C subseteq A$.
Now set $B = cup_n=1^N (a_n/2, b_n/2]$. Then $B subsetneq A$, and since everything has positive measure, the strict inequalities
$$
O < U(B) < U(A)
$$
follow.



So the questions I have are



  1. Am I on the right track here? Maybe this supremum approximation argument is overkill.

  2. If this seems like a good approach, I'm struggling a bit to show that the equality holds. In particular if we fix $A$ measurable, and let $S$ denote the RHS (the supremum), then the inequality $U(A) geq S$ is immediate, since the sup is occurring over sets $B$ all of which satisfy $U(A) geq U(B)$ as $B subseteq A$. So the real part that I could use help with is demonstrating $U(A) leq S$. Again if this seems like the right thing to look at, I just want a hint.






share|cite|improve this question











I was working on the following exercise:




Show that $((0,1], mathcalB_(0, 1], U)$ defines a non-atomic measure space.




Above, $mathcalB$ denotes the Borel $sigma$-algebra, and $U$ denotes Lebesgue measure restricted to this sub-$sigma$-algebra of $mathcalB_mathbfR$. Importantly, all I know about $U$ (for the purposes of this problem) is that (1) it is a measure, and (2) it is the unique measure such that if $A = cup_n=1^N (a_n, b_n] subset (0, 1]$, where $N in mathbfN$ and the intervals are disjoint, then $U(A) = sum_n=1^N (b_n - a_n)$. [In words, "$U$ is finitely-additive over disjoint, finite unions of half-open sub-intervals of $(0, 1]$"]



In working on the exercise, I thought it would be useful to try to prove a property about the measure on the entire $mathcalB_(0, 1]$. Suppose in fact it is true that for any measurable $A$,



$$
U(A) = supleft U(I) : I subseteq A, text$I$ is a disjoint finite union of half-open sub-intervals of $(0, 1]$right
$$



If this statement is true, then the claim follows: if I set $epsilon > 0$, then I get the following approximation result:
$$
exists A supseteq I = cup_n=1^N (a_n, b_n] text (disj.): qquad U(A) - epsilon < U(I) = sum_n=1^N (b_n - a_n).
$$
Suppose now that $U(A) > 0$. If I take $epsilon = U(A)/2$, then
this says there exists a set $C = cup_n=1^N (a_n, b_n] subset A$, such
that $U(C) > U(A)/2$. Additionally $U(C) leq U(A)$ since $C subseteq A$.
Now set $B = cup_n=1^N (a_n/2, b_n/2]$. Then $B subsetneq A$, and since everything has positive measure, the strict inequalities
$$
O < U(B) < U(A)
$$
follow.



So the questions I have are



  1. Am I on the right track here? Maybe this supremum approximation argument is overkill.

  2. If this seems like a good approach, I'm struggling a bit to show that the equality holds. In particular if we fix $A$ measurable, and let $S$ denote the RHS (the supremum), then the inequality $U(A) geq S$ is immediate, since the sup is occurring over sets $B$ all of which satisfy $U(A) geq U(B)$ as $B subseteq A$. So the real part that I could use help with is demonstrating $U(A) leq S$. Again if this seems like the right thing to look at, I just want a hint.








share|cite|improve this question










share|cite|improve this question




share|cite|improve this question









asked Jul 16 at 18:21









Drew Brady

410112




410112







  • 1




    Unfortunately your expression for $U(A)$ is incorrect. If $A$ has no interior points the supremum will be zero.
    – Umberto P.
    Jul 16 at 18:26












  • 1




    Unfortunately your expression for $U(A)$ is incorrect. If $A$ has no interior points the supremum will be zero.
    – Umberto P.
    Jul 16 at 18:26







1




1




Unfortunately your expression for $U(A)$ is incorrect. If $A$ has no interior points the supremum will be zero.
– Umberto P.
Jul 16 at 18:26




Unfortunately your expression for $U(A)$ is incorrect. If $A$ has no interior points the supremum will be zero.
– Umberto P.
Jul 16 at 18:26










2 Answers
2






active

oldest

votes

















up vote
1
down vote













You are not on the right track.



For instance observe that the supremum takes value $0$ on a sets like $(0,1]-mathbb Q$ and also on sets like $mathbb Q$.



For $uin(0,1]$ and $epsilon>0$ small enough we have $uin(u-epsilon,u]subseteq(0,1]$ implying that: $$U(u)leq U((u-epsilon,u])=epsilon$$



Since we can take $epsilon>0$ as small as we like this can only be true if:$$U(u)=0$$






share|cite|improve this answer






























    up vote
    0
    down vote













    Suppose for a contradiction that the set $A$ would be an atom. We may partition $(0,1]$ into intervals



    $$
    B_k,n := [(k-1)/n,k/n] ~~~(1 le k le n)
    $$



    for $n = 1, 2, ldots$. Suppose that $mu(A) = epsilon$. Then choose $n$ sufficiently small so that $1/n < epsilon$ (Achimedean axiom) and observe that one of the sets
    $$
    B_k, n cap A
    $$
    has positive measure (otherwise $mu(A) = 0$), but also measure less than $epsilon$.






    share|cite|improve this answer





















    • Very clever. How'd you come up with it or is it sort of just a standard analysis argument?
      – Drew Brady
      Jul 16 at 19:16










    • (It kinda looks like the pigeonhole principle)
      – Drew Brady
      Jul 16 at 19:17










    • (The idea being that if the set A lied strictly inside any of these intervals, its mass would be too little, so it must have nontrivial intersection with at least two of these intervals).
      – Drew Brady
      Jul 16 at 19:19






    • 1




      I came up with it using intuition for the real world: If a set has measure, it must be localised somewhere (imagine it to be a weight or a density). Now an atom cannot be cut into tiny pieces, but the real line can, and the atom is a subset of the real line.
      – AlgebraicsAnonymous
      Jul 17 at 9:48










    Your Answer




    StackExchange.ifUsing("editor", function ()
    return StackExchange.using("mathjaxEditing", function ()
    StackExchange.MarkdownEditor.creationCallbacks.add(function (editor, postfix)
    StackExchange.mathjaxEditing.prepareWmdForMathJax(editor, postfix, [["$", "$"], ["\\(","\\)"]]);
    );
    );
    , "mathjax-editing");

    StackExchange.ready(function()
    var channelOptions =
    tags: "".split(" "),
    id: "69"
    ;
    initTagRenderer("".split(" "), "".split(" "), channelOptions);

    StackExchange.using("externalEditor", function()
    // Have to fire editor after snippets, if snippets enabled
    if (StackExchange.settings.snippets.snippetsEnabled)
    StackExchange.using("snippets", function()
    createEditor();
    );

    else
    createEditor();

    );

    function createEditor()
    StackExchange.prepareEditor(
    heartbeatType: 'answer',
    convertImagesToLinks: true,
    noModals: false,
    showLowRepImageUploadWarning: true,
    reputationToPostImages: 10,
    bindNavPrevention: true,
    postfix: "",
    noCode: true, onDemand: true,
    discardSelector: ".discard-answer"
    ,immediatelyShowMarkdownHelp:true
    );



    );








     

    draft saved


    draft discarded


















    StackExchange.ready(
    function ()
    StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmath.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f2853695%2fnon-atomicity-of-the-uniform-measure-space-on-0-1%23new-answer', 'question_page');

    );

    Post as a guest






























    2 Answers
    2






    active

    oldest

    votes








    2 Answers
    2






    active

    oldest

    votes









    active

    oldest

    votes






    active

    oldest

    votes








    up vote
    1
    down vote













    You are not on the right track.



    For instance observe that the supremum takes value $0$ on a sets like $(0,1]-mathbb Q$ and also on sets like $mathbb Q$.



    For $uin(0,1]$ and $epsilon>0$ small enough we have $uin(u-epsilon,u]subseteq(0,1]$ implying that: $$U(u)leq U((u-epsilon,u])=epsilon$$



    Since we can take $epsilon>0$ as small as we like this can only be true if:$$U(u)=0$$






    share|cite|improve this answer



























      up vote
      1
      down vote













      You are not on the right track.



      For instance observe that the supremum takes value $0$ on a sets like $(0,1]-mathbb Q$ and also on sets like $mathbb Q$.



      For $uin(0,1]$ and $epsilon>0$ small enough we have $uin(u-epsilon,u]subseteq(0,1]$ implying that: $$U(u)leq U((u-epsilon,u])=epsilon$$



      Since we can take $epsilon>0$ as small as we like this can only be true if:$$U(u)=0$$






      share|cite|improve this answer

























        up vote
        1
        down vote










        up vote
        1
        down vote









        You are not on the right track.



        For instance observe that the supremum takes value $0$ on a sets like $(0,1]-mathbb Q$ and also on sets like $mathbb Q$.



        For $uin(0,1]$ and $epsilon>0$ small enough we have $uin(u-epsilon,u]subseteq(0,1]$ implying that: $$U(u)leq U((u-epsilon,u])=epsilon$$



        Since we can take $epsilon>0$ as small as we like this can only be true if:$$U(u)=0$$






        share|cite|improve this answer















        You are not on the right track.



        For instance observe that the supremum takes value $0$ on a sets like $(0,1]-mathbb Q$ and also on sets like $mathbb Q$.



        For $uin(0,1]$ and $epsilon>0$ small enough we have $uin(u-epsilon,u]subseteq(0,1]$ implying that: $$U(u)leq U((u-epsilon,u])=epsilon$$



        Since we can take $epsilon>0$ as small as we like this can only be true if:$$U(u)=0$$







        share|cite|improve this answer















        share|cite|improve this answer



        share|cite|improve this answer








        edited Jul 16 at 20:07


























        answered Jul 16 at 18:55









        drhab

        86.6k541118




        86.6k541118




















            up vote
            0
            down vote













            Suppose for a contradiction that the set $A$ would be an atom. We may partition $(0,1]$ into intervals



            $$
            B_k,n := [(k-1)/n,k/n] ~~~(1 le k le n)
            $$



            for $n = 1, 2, ldots$. Suppose that $mu(A) = epsilon$. Then choose $n$ sufficiently small so that $1/n < epsilon$ (Achimedean axiom) and observe that one of the sets
            $$
            B_k, n cap A
            $$
            has positive measure (otherwise $mu(A) = 0$), but also measure less than $epsilon$.






            share|cite|improve this answer





















            • Very clever. How'd you come up with it or is it sort of just a standard analysis argument?
              – Drew Brady
              Jul 16 at 19:16










            • (It kinda looks like the pigeonhole principle)
              – Drew Brady
              Jul 16 at 19:17










            • (The idea being that if the set A lied strictly inside any of these intervals, its mass would be too little, so it must have nontrivial intersection with at least two of these intervals).
              – Drew Brady
              Jul 16 at 19:19






            • 1




              I came up with it using intuition for the real world: If a set has measure, it must be localised somewhere (imagine it to be a weight or a density). Now an atom cannot be cut into tiny pieces, but the real line can, and the atom is a subset of the real line.
              – AlgebraicsAnonymous
              Jul 17 at 9:48














            up vote
            0
            down vote













            Suppose for a contradiction that the set $A$ would be an atom. We may partition $(0,1]$ into intervals



            $$
            B_k,n := [(k-1)/n,k/n] ~~~(1 le k le n)
            $$



            for $n = 1, 2, ldots$. Suppose that $mu(A) = epsilon$. Then choose $n$ sufficiently small so that $1/n < epsilon$ (Achimedean axiom) and observe that one of the sets
            $$
            B_k, n cap A
            $$
            has positive measure (otherwise $mu(A) = 0$), but also measure less than $epsilon$.






            share|cite|improve this answer





















            • Very clever. How'd you come up with it or is it sort of just a standard analysis argument?
              – Drew Brady
              Jul 16 at 19:16










            • (It kinda looks like the pigeonhole principle)
              – Drew Brady
              Jul 16 at 19:17










            • (The idea being that if the set A lied strictly inside any of these intervals, its mass would be too little, so it must have nontrivial intersection with at least two of these intervals).
              – Drew Brady
              Jul 16 at 19:19






            • 1




              I came up with it using intuition for the real world: If a set has measure, it must be localised somewhere (imagine it to be a weight or a density). Now an atom cannot be cut into tiny pieces, but the real line can, and the atom is a subset of the real line.
              – AlgebraicsAnonymous
              Jul 17 at 9:48












            up vote
            0
            down vote










            up vote
            0
            down vote









            Suppose for a contradiction that the set $A$ would be an atom. We may partition $(0,1]$ into intervals



            $$
            B_k,n := [(k-1)/n,k/n] ~~~(1 le k le n)
            $$



            for $n = 1, 2, ldots$. Suppose that $mu(A) = epsilon$. Then choose $n$ sufficiently small so that $1/n < epsilon$ (Achimedean axiom) and observe that one of the sets
            $$
            B_k, n cap A
            $$
            has positive measure (otherwise $mu(A) = 0$), but also measure less than $epsilon$.






            share|cite|improve this answer













            Suppose for a contradiction that the set $A$ would be an atom. We may partition $(0,1]$ into intervals



            $$
            B_k,n := [(k-1)/n,k/n] ~~~(1 le k le n)
            $$



            for $n = 1, 2, ldots$. Suppose that $mu(A) = epsilon$. Then choose $n$ sufficiently small so that $1/n < epsilon$ (Achimedean axiom) and observe that one of the sets
            $$
            B_k, n cap A
            $$
            has positive measure (otherwise $mu(A) = 0$), but also measure less than $epsilon$.







            share|cite|improve this answer













            share|cite|improve this answer



            share|cite|improve this answer











            answered Jul 16 at 18:31









            AlgebraicsAnonymous

            69111




            69111











            • Very clever. How'd you come up with it or is it sort of just a standard analysis argument?
              – Drew Brady
              Jul 16 at 19:16










            • (It kinda looks like the pigeonhole principle)
              – Drew Brady
              Jul 16 at 19:17










            • (The idea being that if the set A lied strictly inside any of these intervals, its mass would be too little, so it must have nontrivial intersection with at least two of these intervals).
              – Drew Brady
              Jul 16 at 19:19






            • 1




              I came up with it using intuition for the real world: If a set has measure, it must be localised somewhere (imagine it to be a weight or a density). Now an atom cannot be cut into tiny pieces, but the real line can, and the atom is a subset of the real line.
              – AlgebraicsAnonymous
              Jul 17 at 9:48
















            • Very clever. How'd you come up with it or is it sort of just a standard analysis argument?
              – Drew Brady
              Jul 16 at 19:16










            • (It kinda looks like the pigeonhole principle)
              – Drew Brady
              Jul 16 at 19:17










            • (The idea being that if the set A lied strictly inside any of these intervals, its mass would be too little, so it must have nontrivial intersection with at least two of these intervals).
              – Drew Brady
              Jul 16 at 19:19






            • 1




              I came up with it using intuition for the real world: If a set has measure, it must be localised somewhere (imagine it to be a weight or a density). Now an atom cannot be cut into tiny pieces, but the real line can, and the atom is a subset of the real line.
              – AlgebraicsAnonymous
              Jul 17 at 9:48















            Very clever. How'd you come up with it or is it sort of just a standard analysis argument?
            – Drew Brady
            Jul 16 at 19:16




            Very clever. How'd you come up with it or is it sort of just a standard analysis argument?
            – Drew Brady
            Jul 16 at 19:16












            (It kinda looks like the pigeonhole principle)
            – Drew Brady
            Jul 16 at 19:17




            (It kinda looks like the pigeonhole principle)
            – Drew Brady
            Jul 16 at 19:17












            (The idea being that if the set A lied strictly inside any of these intervals, its mass would be too little, so it must have nontrivial intersection with at least two of these intervals).
            – Drew Brady
            Jul 16 at 19:19




            (The idea being that if the set A lied strictly inside any of these intervals, its mass would be too little, so it must have nontrivial intersection with at least two of these intervals).
            – Drew Brady
            Jul 16 at 19:19




            1




            1




            I came up with it using intuition for the real world: If a set has measure, it must be localised somewhere (imagine it to be a weight or a density). Now an atom cannot be cut into tiny pieces, but the real line can, and the atom is a subset of the real line.
            – AlgebraicsAnonymous
            Jul 17 at 9:48




            I came up with it using intuition for the real world: If a set has measure, it must be localised somewhere (imagine it to be a weight or a density). Now an atom cannot be cut into tiny pieces, but the real line can, and the atom is a subset of the real line.
            – AlgebraicsAnonymous
            Jul 17 at 9:48












             

            draft saved


            draft discarded


























             


            draft saved


            draft discarded














            StackExchange.ready(
            function ()
            StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmath.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f2853695%2fnon-atomicity-of-the-uniform-measure-space-on-0-1%23new-answer', 'question_page');

            );

            Post as a guest













































































            Comments

            Popular posts from this blog

            What is the equation of a 3D cone with generalised tilt?

            Color the edges and diagonals of a regular polygon

            Relationship between determinant of matrix and determinant of adjoint?