Question about Fraïssé's theorem

The name of the pictureThe name of the pictureThe name of the pictureClash Royale CLAN TAG#URR8PPP











up vote
1
down vote

favorite
1












In Bruno Poizat's book "A course in model theory" pages 35,36, he says :




"we have no difficulty proving the first part of Fraïssé's theorem, that two $p$-equivalent tuples satisfy the same formulas of quantifier rank less than or equal to $p$".




He continues, "As the for converse, which depends on Lemma 2.3 ("there are only finitely many p-equivalence classes"), it is correct only if the signature can be reduced to a finite number of relations and and constants. In fact, one $single$ $function$ of nonzero arity allows the formation of infinitely many terms, and consequently infinltely many atomic formulas.



"Therefore, if we want to reduce elementary equivalence completely to finite back-and-forth criteria, we need to reduce it to finite signatures, and to replace each $n$-ary function by its graph, which is an $(n+1)$-ary relation. Doing this would preserve elementary equivalence, but change the notions of atomic formula, formula of quantifier rank $p$, $p-isomorphism$, etc."



I don't really understand what he says about functions here, about replacing them with their graphs. Can someone please explain why this is necessary? Am I missing something?







share|cite|improve this question





















  • What is $p$-equivalence for tuples?
    – Berci
    Jul 30 at 8:23










  • In the first chapter, the theorem is stated for a relation. He says two tuples in the universes of $R$ and $R'$ are $p-equivalent$ if they correspond via a $p-$isomorphism from $R$ to $R'$. This is an equivalence relation, and he writes $(overrightarrowa,R)sim_p (overrightarrowb,R')$
    – Stonecipher
    Jul 30 at 9:10














up vote
1
down vote

favorite
1












In Bruno Poizat's book "A course in model theory" pages 35,36, he says :




"we have no difficulty proving the first part of Fraïssé's theorem, that two $p$-equivalent tuples satisfy the same formulas of quantifier rank less than or equal to $p$".




He continues, "As the for converse, which depends on Lemma 2.3 ("there are only finitely many p-equivalence classes"), it is correct only if the signature can be reduced to a finite number of relations and and constants. In fact, one $single$ $function$ of nonzero arity allows the formation of infinitely many terms, and consequently infinltely many atomic formulas.



"Therefore, if we want to reduce elementary equivalence completely to finite back-and-forth criteria, we need to reduce it to finite signatures, and to replace each $n$-ary function by its graph, which is an $(n+1)$-ary relation. Doing this would preserve elementary equivalence, but change the notions of atomic formula, formula of quantifier rank $p$, $p-isomorphism$, etc."



I don't really understand what he says about functions here, about replacing them with their graphs. Can someone please explain why this is necessary? Am I missing something?







share|cite|improve this question





















  • What is $p$-equivalence for tuples?
    – Berci
    Jul 30 at 8:23










  • In the first chapter, the theorem is stated for a relation. He says two tuples in the universes of $R$ and $R'$ are $p-equivalent$ if they correspond via a $p-$isomorphism from $R$ to $R'$. This is an equivalence relation, and he writes $(overrightarrowa,R)sim_p (overrightarrowb,R')$
    – Stonecipher
    Jul 30 at 9:10












up vote
1
down vote

favorite
1









up vote
1
down vote

favorite
1






1





In Bruno Poizat's book "A course in model theory" pages 35,36, he says :




"we have no difficulty proving the first part of Fraïssé's theorem, that two $p$-equivalent tuples satisfy the same formulas of quantifier rank less than or equal to $p$".




He continues, "As the for converse, which depends on Lemma 2.3 ("there are only finitely many p-equivalence classes"), it is correct only if the signature can be reduced to a finite number of relations and and constants. In fact, one $single$ $function$ of nonzero arity allows the formation of infinitely many terms, and consequently infinltely many atomic formulas.



"Therefore, if we want to reduce elementary equivalence completely to finite back-and-forth criteria, we need to reduce it to finite signatures, and to replace each $n$-ary function by its graph, which is an $(n+1)$-ary relation. Doing this would preserve elementary equivalence, but change the notions of atomic formula, formula of quantifier rank $p$, $p-isomorphism$, etc."



I don't really understand what he says about functions here, about replacing them with their graphs. Can someone please explain why this is necessary? Am I missing something?







share|cite|improve this question













In Bruno Poizat's book "A course in model theory" pages 35,36, he says :




"we have no difficulty proving the first part of Fraïssé's theorem, that two $p$-equivalent tuples satisfy the same formulas of quantifier rank less than or equal to $p$".




He continues, "As the for converse, which depends on Lemma 2.3 ("there are only finitely many p-equivalence classes"), it is correct only if the signature can be reduced to a finite number of relations and and constants. In fact, one $single$ $function$ of nonzero arity allows the formation of infinitely many terms, and consequently infinltely many atomic formulas.



"Therefore, if we want to reduce elementary equivalence completely to finite back-and-forth criteria, we need to reduce it to finite signatures, and to replace each $n$-ary function by its graph, which is an $(n+1)$-ary relation. Doing this would preserve elementary equivalence, but change the notions of atomic formula, formula of quantifier rank $p$, $p-isomorphism$, etc."



I don't really understand what he says about functions here, about replacing them with their graphs. Can someone please explain why this is necessary? Am I missing something?









share|cite|improve this question












share|cite|improve this question




share|cite|improve this question








edited Jul 30 at 8:48
























asked Jul 30 at 8:08









Stonecipher

335




335











  • What is $p$-equivalence for tuples?
    – Berci
    Jul 30 at 8:23










  • In the first chapter, the theorem is stated for a relation. He says two tuples in the universes of $R$ and $R'$ are $p-equivalent$ if they correspond via a $p-$isomorphism from $R$ to $R'$. This is an equivalence relation, and he writes $(overrightarrowa,R)sim_p (overrightarrowb,R')$
    – Stonecipher
    Jul 30 at 9:10
















  • What is $p$-equivalence for tuples?
    – Berci
    Jul 30 at 8:23










  • In the first chapter, the theorem is stated for a relation. He says two tuples in the universes of $R$ and $R'$ are $p-equivalent$ if they correspond via a $p-$isomorphism from $R$ to $R'$. This is an equivalence relation, and he writes $(overrightarrowa,R)sim_p (overrightarrowb,R')$
    – Stonecipher
    Jul 30 at 9:10















What is $p$-equivalence for tuples?
– Berci
Jul 30 at 8:23




What is $p$-equivalence for tuples?
– Berci
Jul 30 at 8:23












In the first chapter, the theorem is stated for a relation. He says two tuples in the universes of $R$ and $R'$ are $p-equivalent$ if they correspond via a $p-$isomorphism from $R$ to $R'$. This is an equivalence relation, and he writes $(overrightarrowa,R)sim_p (overrightarrowb,R')$
– Stonecipher
Jul 30 at 9:10




In the first chapter, the theorem is stated for a relation. He says two tuples in the universes of $R$ and $R'$ are $p-equivalent$ if they correspond via a $p-$isomorphism from $R$ to $R'$. This is an equivalence relation, and he writes $(overrightarrowa,R)sim_p (overrightarrowb,R')$
– Stonecipher
Jul 30 at 9:10










1 Answer
1






active

oldest

votes

















up vote
1
down vote



accepted










Long comment



Theorem 2.2, page 24 (Fraïssé's theorem) is stated for a relation $R$.



Ch.3.2 Functions (page 33-on) consider a language with also function symbols $f_j$.



The "trick" is to replace an $n$-ary function symbol $f$ with an $(n+1)$-ary relation symbol $R$.



Consider the simple example of arithmetic; the sum operation is a binary function : $+ : mathbb N to mathbb N$.



Thus, we need a binary function symbol : $+(x,y)=z$.



We may replace it with a ternary relation symbol $+^*(x,y,z)$ defined as follows :




$+^*(x,y,z)$ holds iff $z=+(x,y)$.





Compare with : Graph of a function :




in mathematics, the graph of a function $f$ is, formally, the set of all ordered pairs $(x, f(x))$, and, in practice, the graphical representation of this set.




In symbols : $text Graph(f) = (x, y) mid y=f(x) $.






share|cite|improve this answer























  • Okay, but I'm bothered when he says "single function of nonzero arity allows the formation of infinitely many terms, and consequently infinltely many atomic formulas" and whether it would affect Lemma 2.3 "there are only finitely many p-equivalence classes"?
    – Stonecipher
    Jul 30 at 8:45











  • I understood it. Thank you. Just I was confused with "infinitely many atomic formulas", where the lemma says it should be finite
    – Stonecipher
    Jul 30 at 9:02











Your Answer




StackExchange.ifUsing("editor", function ()
return StackExchange.using("mathjaxEditing", function ()
StackExchange.MarkdownEditor.creationCallbacks.add(function (editor, postfix)
StackExchange.mathjaxEditing.prepareWmdForMathJax(editor, postfix, [["$", "$"], ["\\(","\\)"]]);
);
);
, "mathjax-editing");

StackExchange.ready(function()
var channelOptions =
tags: "".split(" "),
id: "69"
;
initTagRenderer("".split(" "), "".split(" "), channelOptions);

StackExchange.using("externalEditor", function()
// Have to fire editor after snippets, if snippets enabled
if (StackExchange.settings.snippets.snippetsEnabled)
StackExchange.using("snippets", function()
createEditor();
);

else
createEditor();

);

function createEditor()
StackExchange.prepareEditor(
heartbeatType: 'answer',
convertImagesToLinks: true,
noModals: false,
showLowRepImageUploadWarning: true,
reputationToPostImages: 10,
bindNavPrevention: true,
postfix: "",
noCode: true, onDemand: true,
discardSelector: ".discard-answer"
,immediatelyShowMarkdownHelp:true
);



);








 

draft saved


draft discarded


















StackExchange.ready(
function ()
StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmath.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f2866760%2fquestion-about-fra%25c3%25afss%25c3%25a9s-theorem%23new-answer', 'question_page');

);

Post as a guest






























1 Answer
1






active

oldest

votes








1 Answer
1






active

oldest

votes









active

oldest

votes






active

oldest

votes








up vote
1
down vote



accepted










Long comment



Theorem 2.2, page 24 (Fraïssé's theorem) is stated for a relation $R$.



Ch.3.2 Functions (page 33-on) consider a language with also function symbols $f_j$.



The "trick" is to replace an $n$-ary function symbol $f$ with an $(n+1)$-ary relation symbol $R$.



Consider the simple example of arithmetic; the sum operation is a binary function : $+ : mathbb N to mathbb N$.



Thus, we need a binary function symbol : $+(x,y)=z$.



We may replace it with a ternary relation symbol $+^*(x,y,z)$ defined as follows :




$+^*(x,y,z)$ holds iff $z=+(x,y)$.





Compare with : Graph of a function :




in mathematics, the graph of a function $f$ is, formally, the set of all ordered pairs $(x, f(x))$, and, in practice, the graphical representation of this set.




In symbols : $text Graph(f) = (x, y) mid y=f(x) $.






share|cite|improve this answer























  • Okay, but I'm bothered when he says "single function of nonzero arity allows the formation of infinitely many terms, and consequently infinltely many atomic formulas" and whether it would affect Lemma 2.3 "there are only finitely many p-equivalence classes"?
    – Stonecipher
    Jul 30 at 8:45











  • I understood it. Thank you. Just I was confused with "infinitely many atomic formulas", where the lemma says it should be finite
    – Stonecipher
    Jul 30 at 9:02















up vote
1
down vote



accepted










Long comment



Theorem 2.2, page 24 (Fraïssé's theorem) is stated for a relation $R$.



Ch.3.2 Functions (page 33-on) consider a language with also function symbols $f_j$.



The "trick" is to replace an $n$-ary function symbol $f$ with an $(n+1)$-ary relation symbol $R$.



Consider the simple example of arithmetic; the sum operation is a binary function : $+ : mathbb N to mathbb N$.



Thus, we need a binary function symbol : $+(x,y)=z$.



We may replace it with a ternary relation symbol $+^*(x,y,z)$ defined as follows :




$+^*(x,y,z)$ holds iff $z=+(x,y)$.





Compare with : Graph of a function :




in mathematics, the graph of a function $f$ is, formally, the set of all ordered pairs $(x, f(x))$, and, in practice, the graphical representation of this set.




In symbols : $text Graph(f) = (x, y) mid y=f(x) $.






share|cite|improve this answer























  • Okay, but I'm bothered when he says "single function of nonzero arity allows the formation of infinitely many terms, and consequently infinltely many atomic formulas" and whether it would affect Lemma 2.3 "there are only finitely many p-equivalence classes"?
    – Stonecipher
    Jul 30 at 8:45











  • I understood it. Thank you. Just I was confused with "infinitely many atomic formulas", where the lemma says it should be finite
    – Stonecipher
    Jul 30 at 9:02













up vote
1
down vote



accepted







up vote
1
down vote



accepted






Long comment



Theorem 2.2, page 24 (Fraïssé's theorem) is stated for a relation $R$.



Ch.3.2 Functions (page 33-on) consider a language with also function symbols $f_j$.



The "trick" is to replace an $n$-ary function symbol $f$ with an $(n+1)$-ary relation symbol $R$.



Consider the simple example of arithmetic; the sum operation is a binary function : $+ : mathbb N to mathbb N$.



Thus, we need a binary function symbol : $+(x,y)=z$.



We may replace it with a ternary relation symbol $+^*(x,y,z)$ defined as follows :




$+^*(x,y,z)$ holds iff $z=+(x,y)$.





Compare with : Graph of a function :




in mathematics, the graph of a function $f$ is, formally, the set of all ordered pairs $(x, f(x))$, and, in practice, the graphical representation of this set.




In symbols : $text Graph(f) = (x, y) mid y=f(x) $.






share|cite|improve this answer















Long comment



Theorem 2.2, page 24 (Fraïssé's theorem) is stated for a relation $R$.



Ch.3.2 Functions (page 33-on) consider a language with also function symbols $f_j$.



The "trick" is to replace an $n$-ary function symbol $f$ with an $(n+1)$-ary relation symbol $R$.



Consider the simple example of arithmetic; the sum operation is a binary function : $+ : mathbb N to mathbb N$.



Thus, we need a binary function symbol : $+(x,y)=z$.



We may replace it with a ternary relation symbol $+^*(x,y,z)$ defined as follows :




$+^*(x,y,z)$ holds iff $z=+(x,y)$.





Compare with : Graph of a function :




in mathematics, the graph of a function $f$ is, formally, the set of all ordered pairs $(x, f(x))$, and, in practice, the graphical representation of this set.




In symbols : $text Graph(f) = (x, y) mid y=f(x) $.







share|cite|improve this answer















share|cite|improve this answer



share|cite|improve this answer








edited Jul 30 at 8:41


























answered Jul 30 at 8:32









Mauro ALLEGRANZA

60.6k346105




60.6k346105











  • Okay, but I'm bothered when he says "single function of nonzero arity allows the formation of infinitely many terms, and consequently infinltely many atomic formulas" and whether it would affect Lemma 2.3 "there are only finitely many p-equivalence classes"?
    – Stonecipher
    Jul 30 at 8:45











  • I understood it. Thank you. Just I was confused with "infinitely many atomic formulas", where the lemma says it should be finite
    – Stonecipher
    Jul 30 at 9:02

















  • Okay, but I'm bothered when he says "single function of nonzero arity allows the formation of infinitely many terms, and consequently infinltely many atomic formulas" and whether it would affect Lemma 2.3 "there are only finitely many p-equivalence classes"?
    – Stonecipher
    Jul 30 at 8:45











  • I understood it. Thank you. Just I was confused with "infinitely many atomic formulas", where the lemma says it should be finite
    – Stonecipher
    Jul 30 at 9:02
















Okay, but I'm bothered when he says "single function of nonzero arity allows the formation of infinitely many terms, and consequently infinltely many atomic formulas" and whether it would affect Lemma 2.3 "there are only finitely many p-equivalence classes"?
– Stonecipher
Jul 30 at 8:45





Okay, but I'm bothered when he says "single function of nonzero arity allows the formation of infinitely many terms, and consequently infinltely many atomic formulas" and whether it would affect Lemma 2.3 "there are only finitely many p-equivalence classes"?
– Stonecipher
Jul 30 at 8:45













I understood it. Thank you. Just I was confused with "infinitely many atomic formulas", where the lemma says it should be finite
– Stonecipher
Jul 30 at 9:02





I understood it. Thank you. Just I was confused with "infinitely many atomic formulas", where the lemma says it should be finite
– Stonecipher
Jul 30 at 9:02













 

draft saved


draft discarded


























 


draft saved


draft discarded














StackExchange.ready(
function ()
StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmath.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f2866760%2fquestion-about-fra%25c3%25afss%25c3%25a9s-theorem%23new-answer', 'question_page');

);

Post as a guest













































































Comments

Popular posts from this blog

What is the equation of a 3D cone with generalised tilt?

Color the edges and diagonals of a regular polygon

Relationship between determinant of matrix and determinant of adjoint?