Questions on “All Horse are the Same Color” Proof by Complete Induction

The name of the pictureThe name of the pictureThe name of the pictureClash Royale CLAN TAG#URR8PPP











up vote
26
down vote

favorite
20












I'm bugged by the following that's summarized on p. 109 of this PDF.




False theorem: All horses are the same color.



Proof by induction:



$fbox$P(n)$ is the statement: In every set of horses of size $n$, all $n$ horses are the same color.$

$fboxBase Case or $P(1)$:$ One horse is the same color as itself. This is true by inspection.

$fboxInduction Step:$ Assume $P(k)$ for some $k geq 1$.

$fboxProof of $P(k + 1) :$$

Since $H_1, H_2, ... , H_n$ is a set of $n$ horses, the induction hypothesis applies to this set. Thus, all the horses in this set are the same color.

Since $H_2, H_3, ... , H_n+1$ is also a set of $n$ horses, the induction step likewise holds for this set. Thus, all the horses in this set are the same color too.



Therefore, all $n +1$ horses in $H_1, H_2, H_3, ... , H_n , H_n+1$ are the same color. QED.




The issue the instructor was trying to point out is clearly valid. For the case $n = 1$, there is only $H_1$. So this case says nothing about possible overlapping elements of each set of $(n + 1)$, for instance $H_2$ in the above proof.



But it was proposed in the class discussion that this was the only problem. Had you been able to prove $P(2)$ true, then a proof of the above format would have been fine.



My interpretation is that yes, you could prove all horses are the same color, if you can prove that any set of two horses will be the same color. But this format would not work.



Why not? The problem I see is that the above proof is for the existence of at least one particular pair of sets of horses of sizes $n$ and $n + 1$, such that in each set, all horses are the same color. Particularly when the set of size $n$ is a subset of the set of size $n + 1$. In order to prove the induction step, don't you need to prove that sets of sizes $n$ and $n + 1$, do not necessarily contain the same, overlapping elements?



You could prove that any horse can be added to a set of 2 horses. Take the last two, and they must be the same color, and so on. Wwhatever color the first two happen to be, all other horses must thus be the same color.



Am I misinterpreting the example, or am I making a logical error? Thanks in advance.







share|cite|improve this question

















  • 2




    P(1) is obviously false by inspection. Many single horses are of more than one colour -- they're called piebalds or skewbalds.
    – Mike Scott
    May 15 '17 at 20:00














up vote
26
down vote

favorite
20












I'm bugged by the following that's summarized on p. 109 of this PDF.




False theorem: All horses are the same color.



Proof by induction:



$fbox$P(n)$ is the statement: In every set of horses of size $n$, all $n$ horses are the same color.$

$fboxBase Case or $P(1)$:$ One horse is the same color as itself. This is true by inspection.

$fboxInduction Step:$ Assume $P(k)$ for some $k geq 1$.

$fboxProof of $P(k + 1) :$$

Since $H_1, H_2, ... , H_n$ is a set of $n$ horses, the induction hypothesis applies to this set. Thus, all the horses in this set are the same color.

Since $H_2, H_3, ... , H_n+1$ is also a set of $n$ horses, the induction step likewise holds for this set. Thus, all the horses in this set are the same color too.



Therefore, all $n +1$ horses in $H_1, H_2, H_3, ... , H_n , H_n+1$ are the same color. QED.




The issue the instructor was trying to point out is clearly valid. For the case $n = 1$, there is only $H_1$. So this case says nothing about possible overlapping elements of each set of $(n + 1)$, for instance $H_2$ in the above proof.



But it was proposed in the class discussion that this was the only problem. Had you been able to prove $P(2)$ true, then a proof of the above format would have been fine.



My interpretation is that yes, you could prove all horses are the same color, if you can prove that any set of two horses will be the same color. But this format would not work.



Why not? The problem I see is that the above proof is for the existence of at least one particular pair of sets of horses of sizes $n$ and $n + 1$, such that in each set, all horses are the same color. Particularly when the set of size $n$ is a subset of the set of size $n + 1$. In order to prove the induction step, don't you need to prove that sets of sizes $n$ and $n + 1$, do not necessarily contain the same, overlapping elements?



You could prove that any horse can be added to a set of 2 horses. Take the last two, and they must be the same color, and so on. Wwhatever color the first two happen to be, all other horses must thus be the same color.



Am I misinterpreting the example, or am I making a logical error? Thanks in advance.







share|cite|improve this question

















  • 2




    P(1) is obviously false by inspection. Many single horses are of more than one colour -- they're called piebalds or skewbalds.
    – Mike Scott
    May 15 '17 at 20:00












up vote
26
down vote

favorite
20









up vote
26
down vote

favorite
20






20





I'm bugged by the following that's summarized on p. 109 of this PDF.




False theorem: All horses are the same color.



Proof by induction:



$fbox$P(n)$ is the statement: In every set of horses of size $n$, all $n$ horses are the same color.$

$fboxBase Case or $P(1)$:$ One horse is the same color as itself. This is true by inspection.

$fboxInduction Step:$ Assume $P(k)$ for some $k geq 1$.

$fboxProof of $P(k + 1) :$$

Since $H_1, H_2, ... , H_n$ is a set of $n$ horses, the induction hypothesis applies to this set. Thus, all the horses in this set are the same color.

Since $H_2, H_3, ... , H_n+1$ is also a set of $n$ horses, the induction step likewise holds for this set. Thus, all the horses in this set are the same color too.



Therefore, all $n +1$ horses in $H_1, H_2, H_3, ... , H_n , H_n+1$ are the same color. QED.




The issue the instructor was trying to point out is clearly valid. For the case $n = 1$, there is only $H_1$. So this case says nothing about possible overlapping elements of each set of $(n + 1)$, for instance $H_2$ in the above proof.



But it was proposed in the class discussion that this was the only problem. Had you been able to prove $P(2)$ true, then a proof of the above format would have been fine.



My interpretation is that yes, you could prove all horses are the same color, if you can prove that any set of two horses will be the same color. But this format would not work.



Why not? The problem I see is that the above proof is for the existence of at least one particular pair of sets of horses of sizes $n$ and $n + 1$, such that in each set, all horses are the same color. Particularly when the set of size $n$ is a subset of the set of size $n + 1$. In order to prove the induction step, don't you need to prove that sets of sizes $n$ and $n + 1$, do not necessarily contain the same, overlapping elements?



You could prove that any horse can be added to a set of 2 horses. Take the last two, and they must be the same color, and so on. Wwhatever color the first two happen to be, all other horses must thus be the same color.



Am I misinterpreting the example, or am I making a logical error? Thanks in advance.







share|cite|improve this question













I'm bugged by the following that's summarized on p. 109 of this PDF.




False theorem: All horses are the same color.



Proof by induction:



$fbox$P(n)$ is the statement: In every set of horses of size $n$, all $n$ horses are the same color.$

$fboxBase Case or $P(1)$:$ One horse is the same color as itself. This is true by inspection.

$fboxInduction Step:$ Assume $P(k)$ for some $k geq 1$.

$fboxProof of $P(k + 1) :$$

Since $H_1, H_2, ... , H_n$ is a set of $n$ horses, the induction hypothesis applies to this set. Thus, all the horses in this set are the same color.

Since $H_2, H_3, ... , H_n+1$ is also a set of $n$ horses, the induction step likewise holds for this set. Thus, all the horses in this set are the same color too.



Therefore, all $n +1$ horses in $H_1, H_2, H_3, ... , H_n , H_n+1$ are the same color. QED.




The issue the instructor was trying to point out is clearly valid. For the case $n = 1$, there is only $H_1$. So this case says nothing about possible overlapping elements of each set of $(n + 1)$, for instance $H_2$ in the above proof.



But it was proposed in the class discussion that this was the only problem. Had you been able to prove $P(2)$ true, then a proof of the above format would have been fine.



My interpretation is that yes, you could prove all horses are the same color, if you can prove that any set of two horses will be the same color. But this format would not work.



Why not? The problem I see is that the above proof is for the existence of at least one particular pair of sets of horses of sizes $n$ and $n + 1$, such that in each set, all horses are the same color. Particularly when the set of size $n$ is a subset of the set of size $n + 1$. In order to prove the induction step, don't you need to prove that sets of sizes $n$ and $n + 1$, do not necessarily contain the same, overlapping elements?



You could prove that any horse can be added to a set of 2 horses. Take the last two, and they must be the same color, and so on. Wwhatever color the first two happen to be, all other horses must thus be the same color.



Am I misinterpreting the example, or am I making a logical error? Thanks in advance.









share|cite|improve this question












share|cite|improve this question




share|cite|improve this question








edited Dec 25 '17 at 2:07









Greek - Area 51 Proposal

2,98346697




2,98346697









asked Jun 24 '13 at 8:53









MVTC

2671310




2671310







  • 2




    P(1) is obviously false by inspection. Many single horses are of more than one colour -- they're called piebalds or skewbalds.
    – Mike Scott
    May 15 '17 at 20:00












  • 2




    P(1) is obviously false by inspection. Many single horses are of more than one colour -- they're called piebalds or skewbalds.
    – Mike Scott
    May 15 '17 at 20:00







2




2




P(1) is obviously false by inspection. Many single horses are of more than one colour -- they're called piebalds or skewbalds.
– Mike Scott
May 15 '17 at 20:00




P(1) is obviously false by inspection. Many single horses are of more than one colour -- they're called piebalds or skewbalds.
– Mike Scott
May 15 '17 at 20:00










6 Answers
6






active

oldest

votes

















up vote
50
down vote



accepted










It’s clear from the question and from your discussion with @DonAntonio that you don’t actually understand the induction step of the argument. You seem to think that it involves comparing some previously chosen set of $n$ horses with some new set of $n+1$ horses, but it does not. Let me see if I can explain more clearly just how it does work.



We assume as our induction hypothesis that if $H$ is any set whatsoever of $n$ horses, then the horses in $H$ are all the same color. Now let $H=h_1,h_2,dots,h_n+1$ be any set of $n+1$ horses; our goal is to show that all of the horses in $H$ are the same color. To do this, we look at the subsets



$$H_0=h_1,dots,h_nquadtextandquad H_1=h_2,dots,h_n+1;.$$



Each of these subsets contains $n$ horses, so by hypothesis all of the horses in $H_0$ are the same color, and all of the horses in $H_1$ are the same color.




Note: The two $n$-horse sets that we’re looking at here were not given to us ahead of time: they are just two different $n$-horse subsets of $H$. And in fact any two different $n$-horse subsets of $H$ will work equally well for the argument.




Now if $nge 2$, the horse that I’ve called $h_2$ is in both $H_0$ and $H_1$. (In fact every horse except $h_1$ and $h_n+1$ is in both $H_0$ and $H_1$.) Since $h_2$ is in $H_0$, and we already know from the induction hypothesis that all of the horses in $H_0$ are the same color, it follows that every horse in $H_0$ is the same color as $h_2$. But $h_2$ is in $H_1$ as well, so by exactly the same reasoning we conclude that every horse in $H_1$ is the same color as $h_2$. But every horse in $H$ is in $H_0$ or $H_1$ (or both), so every horse in $H$ is the same color as $h_2$, and therefore the horses in $H$ are all the same color. This completes the induction step.




There is absolutely nothing wrong with that argument — provided that $nge 2$. In particular, it does not involve starting with some particular set of $n$ horses known to be the same color and trying to use that set to show that the horses in some arbitrary set of $n+1$ horses are all the same color. The argument starts with a set of $n+1$ horses and proceeds by looking at two $n$-horse subsets of the given set. It’s important here to realize that the induction hypothesis does not say that there is some particular set of $n$ horses that are all the same color: it says that in any set of of $n$ horses, all of the horses are the same color.



The argument fails only when $n=1$. In that case it fails because the sets $H_0=h_1$ and $H_1=h_2$ no longer overlap: there is no horse in both sets. Thus, while it’s true that all of the horses in $H_0$ are the same color and that all of the horses in $H_1$ are the same color, we can no longer infer that those two colors must be the same. But if we could somehow show that in every set of two horses, both horses were the same color, the induction argument as given would work just fine: we’d always be considering some $nge 2$, so the sets $H_0$ and $H_1$ would overlap.






share|cite|improve this answer

















  • 2




    Very clear explanation of the part that was confusing to the OP -- good work understanding what the OP's confusion was!
    – ShreevatsaR
    Jun 25 '13 at 6:12










  • Excellent explanation. I think this must have cleared up completely any doubt the OP could have had. +1
    – DonAntonio
    Jun 25 '13 at 6:15










  • @DonAntonio: Thanks, and to ShreevatsaR as well.
    – Brian M. Scott
    Jun 25 '13 at 6:18

















up vote
10
down vote













I'm not sure I understand fully your doubt, but the actual problem with that, and many other examples of bogus inductive proofs out there, is that when you take the two sets



$$h_1,...,h_n;,;;h_2,...,h_n,h_n+1$$



each of size $,n,$ and thus, by the Ind. Hypothesis, formed of horses of the same color, the leap to deduce all the horses altogether have the same color requires that the intersection of both sets above is not empty, something you can't prove (because it is false!) if $,n=2,$



Thus, if we had the claim "every two horse whatsoever are of the same color", then we could prove "all the horses are of the same color"






share|cite|improve this answer





















  • $n=1$, maybe, since otherwise they share $h_2$.
    – Arthur
    Jun 24 '13 at 9:16










  • No, for $,n=1,$ it works trivially. For $,n=2,$ we have the huge problem: each of the sets $,h_1;,;h_2;$ have all the horses of the same color, then (this is the bogus part) also $,h_1,h_2,$ has horses of the same color. From this impasse the whole thing crumbles down in this case.
    – DonAntonio
    Jun 24 '13 at 9:30










  • @DonAntonio, what is meant is that it works if you have P(2) as a base case. Then, you have the same setup where you prove that for an arb. n >= 2, p(n) -> p(n+1). Then for the first n, n = 2, P(n) gives h1, h2 p(n+1) gives h1, h2, h3, and they share h2... My issue was that p(n+1) could also be h4, h5, h6, of which this proof doesn't address, but I guess after more thinking, it is obvious, that you add any element whatsoever to a set of 2, and it must be the same color, so all must be the same color. I just don't know how acceptable it would be without something more to it.
    – MVTC
    Jun 24 '13 at 10:10







  • 1




    But the above is assuming you could use and prove P(2) as a base case, which you can't.
    – MVTC
    Jun 24 '13 at 10:17











  • @DonAntonio I mean where you say "the intersection of both sets above is not empty, something you can't prove (because it is false!) if $n=2$." Here $n$ should be equal to $1$, otherwise the intersection contains $h_2$. That is what I meant. In the case $n=1$, you have two sets of uniform horses with empty intersection, thus you cannot go through with the induction step.
    – Arthur
    Jun 24 '13 at 10:24


















up vote
0
down vote













There is a more basic problem here : induction is irrelevant to the proof.



$P(2)$ is, by itself, a formalization of the statement that all horses are the same color. There is no reason to prove $P(2)$ to prove $P(3)$ to prove ... $P(n)$ and conclude from this chain of implications that all horses are the same color; one would try to prove $P(2)$ and in case of success, summarize that as "all horses have the same color".



If proving $P(n)$ were of interest for some reason, it can be derived in one step from $P(2)$, with no need for an induction.



The size of the set of horses is usually ignored in presentations of this argument and ones like it. But if there are $n$ horses in the universe, $P(k)$ is an empty statement for $k>n$, and is true regardless of the truth value $P(n)$. This shows that $P(n)$ is logically stronger than $P(n+1)$, and that the inductive step from $P(n) $ to $P(n+1)$ is vacuous for large $n$.






share|cite|improve this answer




























    up vote
    0
    down vote













    As you pointed out, $P(1)$ is trivially true. And you are trying to prove $$P(n)implies P(n+1)$$ to finish the proof. But It's clear that $P(1)$ does NOT implies $P(2)$. Thus the statement $$P(n)implies P(n+1)$$ is not true. And this is where your proof falls.






    share|cite|improve this answer




























      up vote
      -1
      down vote













      I just had a student come to me with this problem. I am not a mathematician by trade, so this was the first I'd heard of it. (It's a very good problem that forces the student to understand the method!)



      My natural inclination was to negate that which was supposedly proven ("all horses are the same color"), and take the "contrapositive" of the entire inductive chain, and see if we do necessarily contradict the base case. (In other words, the inductive argument supposedly gives $P(1) Rightarrow P(2) Rightarrow cdotsRightarrow P$; I wanted to see if $neg P Rightarrow cdots Rightarrow neg P(2) Rightarrow neg P(1) $.)



      So, right off the bat, the negation of "all horses are the same color" is "there exists horse A and horse B such that A is a different color than B". From that, you immediately see that $P(1)$ is unsuitable base case because $neg P(2)$ means "in a set of 2 horses, the two hoses are different colors". That does not contradict anything about $P(1)$ (which of course is logically unimpeachable).



      What also comes out in the above line of reasoning confirms what @zyx said: induction is irrelevant to the statement being proven. At every step, the condition that the statement be false hinges on the existence of two different horses having different colors. So, if you had somehow shown $P(2)$ to be true, game over.






      share|cite|improve this answer






























        up vote
        -2
        down vote













        Just want to add a quick summary.



        The proof is "almost" perfect. It simply fails on n=1.



        Yes obviously any set with 1 horse will have the same color. However, you can't extend that to n=2.



        If you can somehow proof that any set of 2 horses have the same color then yes, you got something right, that any set with any number of horses will have the same color.






        share|cite|improve this answer





















          Your Answer




          StackExchange.ifUsing("editor", function ()
          return StackExchange.using("mathjaxEditing", function ()
          StackExchange.MarkdownEditor.creationCallbacks.add(function (editor, postfix)
          StackExchange.mathjaxEditing.prepareWmdForMathJax(editor, postfix, [["$", "$"], ["\\(","\\)"]]);
          );
          );
          , "mathjax-editing");

          StackExchange.ready(function()
          var channelOptions =
          tags: "".split(" "),
          id: "69"
          ;
          initTagRenderer("".split(" "), "".split(" "), channelOptions);

          StackExchange.using("externalEditor", function()
          // Have to fire editor after snippets, if snippets enabled
          if (StackExchange.settings.snippets.snippetsEnabled)
          StackExchange.using("snippets", function()
          createEditor();
          );

          else
          createEditor();

          );

          function createEditor()
          StackExchange.prepareEditor(
          heartbeatType: 'answer',
          convertImagesToLinks: true,
          noModals: false,
          showLowRepImageUploadWarning: true,
          reputationToPostImages: 10,
          bindNavPrevention: true,
          postfix: "",
          noCode: true, onDemand: true,
          discardSelector: ".discard-answer"
          ,immediatelyShowMarkdownHelp:true
          );



          );








           

          draft saved


          draft discarded


















          StackExchange.ready(
          function ()
          StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmath.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f428151%2fquestions-on-all-horse-are-the-same-color-proof-by-complete-induction%23new-answer', 'question_page');

          );

          Post as a guest






























          6 Answers
          6






          active

          oldest

          votes








          6 Answers
          6






          active

          oldest

          votes









          active

          oldest

          votes






          active

          oldest

          votes








          up vote
          50
          down vote



          accepted










          It’s clear from the question and from your discussion with @DonAntonio that you don’t actually understand the induction step of the argument. You seem to think that it involves comparing some previously chosen set of $n$ horses with some new set of $n+1$ horses, but it does not. Let me see if I can explain more clearly just how it does work.



          We assume as our induction hypothesis that if $H$ is any set whatsoever of $n$ horses, then the horses in $H$ are all the same color. Now let $H=h_1,h_2,dots,h_n+1$ be any set of $n+1$ horses; our goal is to show that all of the horses in $H$ are the same color. To do this, we look at the subsets



          $$H_0=h_1,dots,h_nquadtextandquad H_1=h_2,dots,h_n+1;.$$



          Each of these subsets contains $n$ horses, so by hypothesis all of the horses in $H_0$ are the same color, and all of the horses in $H_1$ are the same color.




          Note: The two $n$-horse sets that we’re looking at here were not given to us ahead of time: they are just two different $n$-horse subsets of $H$. And in fact any two different $n$-horse subsets of $H$ will work equally well for the argument.




          Now if $nge 2$, the horse that I’ve called $h_2$ is in both $H_0$ and $H_1$. (In fact every horse except $h_1$ and $h_n+1$ is in both $H_0$ and $H_1$.) Since $h_2$ is in $H_0$, and we already know from the induction hypothesis that all of the horses in $H_0$ are the same color, it follows that every horse in $H_0$ is the same color as $h_2$. But $h_2$ is in $H_1$ as well, so by exactly the same reasoning we conclude that every horse in $H_1$ is the same color as $h_2$. But every horse in $H$ is in $H_0$ or $H_1$ (or both), so every horse in $H$ is the same color as $h_2$, and therefore the horses in $H$ are all the same color. This completes the induction step.




          There is absolutely nothing wrong with that argument — provided that $nge 2$. In particular, it does not involve starting with some particular set of $n$ horses known to be the same color and trying to use that set to show that the horses in some arbitrary set of $n+1$ horses are all the same color. The argument starts with a set of $n+1$ horses and proceeds by looking at two $n$-horse subsets of the given set. It’s important here to realize that the induction hypothesis does not say that there is some particular set of $n$ horses that are all the same color: it says that in any set of of $n$ horses, all of the horses are the same color.



          The argument fails only when $n=1$. In that case it fails because the sets $H_0=h_1$ and $H_1=h_2$ no longer overlap: there is no horse in both sets. Thus, while it’s true that all of the horses in $H_0$ are the same color and that all of the horses in $H_1$ are the same color, we can no longer infer that those two colors must be the same. But if we could somehow show that in every set of two horses, both horses were the same color, the induction argument as given would work just fine: we’d always be considering some $nge 2$, so the sets $H_0$ and $H_1$ would overlap.






          share|cite|improve this answer

















          • 2




            Very clear explanation of the part that was confusing to the OP -- good work understanding what the OP's confusion was!
            – ShreevatsaR
            Jun 25 '13 at 6:12










          • Excellent explanation. I think this must have cleared up completely any doubt the OP could have had. +1
            – DonAntonio
            Jun 25 '13 at 6:15










          • @DonAntonio: Thanks, and to ShreevatsaR as well.
            – Brian M. Scott
            Jun 25 '13 at 6:18














          up vote
          50
          down vote



          accepted










          It’s clear from the question and from your discussion with @DonAntonio that you don’t actually understand the induction step of the argument. You seem to think that it involves comparing some previously chosen set of $n$ horses with some new set of $n+1$ horses, but it does not. Let me see if I can explain more clearly just how it does work.



          We assume as our induction hypothesis that if $H$ is any set whatsoever of $n$ horses, then the horses in $H$ are all the same color. Now let $H=h_1,h_2,dots,h_n+1$ be any set of $n+1$ horses; our goal is to show that all of the horses in $H$ are the same color. To do this, we look at the subsets



          $$H_0=h_1,dots,h_nquadtextandquad H_1=h_2,dots,h_n+1;.$$



          Each of these subsets contains $n$ horses, so by hypothesis all of the horses in $H_0$ are the same color, and all of the horses in $H_1$ are the same color.




          Note: The two $n$-horse sets that we’re looking at here were not given to us ahead of time: they are just two different $n$-horse subsets of $H$. And in fact any two different $n$-horse subsets of $H$ will work equally well for the argument.




          Now if $nge 2$, the horse that I’ve called $h_2$ is in both $H_0$ and $H_1$. (In fact every horse except $h_1$ and $h_n+1$ is in both $H_0$ and $H_1$.) Since $h_2$ is in $H_0$, and we already know from the induction hypothesis that all of the horses in $H_0$ are the same color, it follows that every horse in $H_0$ is the same color as $h_2$. But $h_2$ is in $H_1$ as well, so by exactly the same reasoning we conclude that every horse in $H_1$ is the same color as $h_2$. But every horse in $H$ is in $H_0$ or $H_1$ (or both), so every horse in $H$ is the same color as $h_2$, and therefore the horses in $H$ are all the same color. This completes the induction step.




          There is absolutely nothing wrong with that argument — provided that $nge 2$. In particular, it does not involve starting with some particular set of $n$ horses known to be the same color and trying to use that set to show that the horses in some arbitrary set of $n+1$ horses are all the same color. The argument starts with a set of $n+1$ horses and proceeds by looking at two $n$-horse subsets of the given set. It’s important here to realize that the induction hypothesis does not say that there is some particular set of $n$ horses that are all the same color: it says that in any set of of $n$ horses, all of the horses are the same color.



          The argument fails only when $n=1$. In that case it fails because the sets $H_0=h_1$ and $H_1=h_2$ no longer overlap: there is no horse in both sets. Thus, while it’s true that all of the horses in $H_0$ are the same color and that all of the horses in $H_1$ are the same color, we can no longer infer that those two colors must be the same. But if we could somehow show that in every set of two horses, both horses were the same color, the induction argument as given would work just fine: we’d always be considering some $nge 2$, so the sets $H_0$ and $H_1$ would overlap.






          share|cite|improve this answer

















          • 2




            Very clear explanation of the part that was confusing to the OP -- good work understanding what the OP's confusion was!
            – ShreevatsaR
            Jun 25 '13 at 6:12










          • Excellent explanation. I think this must have cleared up completely any doubt the OP could have had. +1
            – DonAntonio
            Jun 25 '13 at 6:15










          • @DonAntonio: Thanks, and to ShreevatsaR as well.
            – Brian M. Scott
            Jun 25 '13 at 6:18












          up vote
          50
          down vote



          accepted







          up vote
          50
          down vote



          accepted






          It’s clear from the question and from your discussion with @DonAntonio that you don’t actually understand the induction step of the argument. You seem to think that it involves comparing some previously chosen set of $n$ horses with some new set of $n+1$ horses, but it does not. Let me see if I can explain more clearly just how it does work.



          We assume as our induction hypothesis that if $H$ is any set whatsoever of $n$ horses, then the horses in $H$ are all the same color. Now let $H=h_1,h_2,dots,h_n+1$ be any set of $n+1$ horses; our goal is to show that all of the horses in $H$ are the same color. To do this, we look at the subsets



          $$H_0=h_1,dots,h_nquadtextandquad H_1=h_2,dots,h_n+1;.$$



          Each of these subsets contains $n$ horses, so by hypothesis all of the horses in $H_0$ are the same color, and all of the horses in $H_1$ are the same color.




          Note: The two $n$-horse sets that we’re looking at here were not given to us ahead of time: they are just two different $n$-horse subsets of $H$. And in fact any two different $n$-horse subsets of $H$ will work equally well for the argument.




          Now if $nge 2$, the horse that I’ve called $h_2$ is in both $H_0$ and $H_1$. (In fact every horse except $h_1$ and $h_n+1$ is in both $H_0$ and $H_1$.) Since $h_2$ is in $H_0$, and we already know from the induction hypothesis that all of the horses in $H_0$ are the same color, it follows that every horse in $H_0$ is the same color as $h_2$. But $h_2$ is in $H_1$ as well, so by exactly the same reasoning we conclude that every horse in $H_1$ is the same color as $h_2$. But every horse in $H$ is in $H_0$ or $H_1$ (or both), so every horse in $H$ is the same color as $h_2$, and therefore the horses in $H$ are all the same color. This completes the induction step.




          There is absolutely nothing wrong with that argument — provided that $nge 2$. In particular, it does not involve starting with some particular set of $n$ horses known to be the same color and trying to use that set to show that the horses in some arbitrary set of $n+1$ horses are all the same color. The argument starts with a set of $n+1$ horses and proceeds by looking at two $n$-horse subsets of the given set. It’s important here to realize that the induction hypothesis does not say that there is some particular set of $n$ horses that are all the same color: it says that in any set of of $n$ horses, all of the horses are the same color.



          The argument fails only when $n=1$. In that case it fails because the sets $H_0=h_1$ and $H_1=h_2$ no longer overlap: there is no horse in both sets. Thus, while it’s true that all of the horses in $H_0$ are the same color and that all of the horses in $H_1$ are the same color, we can no longer infer that those two colors must be the same. But if we could somehow show that in every set of two horses, both horses were the same color, the induction argument as given would work just fine: we’d always be considering some $nge 2$, so the sets $H_0$ and $H_1$ would overlap.






          share|cite|improve this answer













          It’s clear from the question and from your discussion with @DonAntonio that you don’t actually understand the induction step of the argument. You seem to think that it involves comparing some previously chosen set of $n$ horses with some new set of $n+1$ horses, but it does not. Let me see if I can explain more clearly just how it does work.



          We assume as our induction hypothesis that if $H$ is any set whatsoever of $n$ horses, then the horses in $H$ are all the same color. Now let $H=h_1,h_2,dots,h_n+1$ be any set of $n+1$ horses; our goal is to show that all of the horses in $H$ are the same color. To do this, we look at the subsets



          $$H_0=h_1,dots,h_nquadtextandquad H_1=h_2,dots,h_n+1;.$$



          Each of these subsets contains $n$ horses, so by hypothesis all of the horses in $H_0$ are the same color, and all of the horses in $H_1$ are the same color.




          Note: The two $n$-horse sets that we’re looking at here were not given to us ahead of time: they are just two different $n$-horse subsets of $H$. And in fact any two different $n$-horse subsets of $H$ will work equally well for the argument.




          Now if $nge 2$, the horse that I’ve called $h_2$ is in both $H_0$ and $H_1$. (In fact every horse except $h_1$ and $h_n+1$ is in both $H_0$ and $H_1$.) Since $h_2$ is in $H_0$, and we already know from the induction hypothesis that all of the horses in $H_0$ are the same color, it follows that every horse in $H_0$ is the same color as $h_2$. But $h_2$ is in $H_1$ as well, so by exactly the same reasoning we conclude that every horse in $H_1$ is the same color as $h_2$. But every horse in $H$ is in $H_0$ or $H_1$ (or both), so every horse in $H$ is the same color as $h_2$, and therefore the horses in $H$ are all the same color. This completes the induction step.




          There is absolutely nothing wrong with that argument — provided that $nge 2$. In particular, it does not involve starting with some particular set of $n$ horses known to be the same color and trying to use that set to show that the horses in some arbitrary set of $n+1$ horses are all the same color. The argument starts with a set of $n+1$ horses and proceeds by looking at two $n$-horse subsets of the given set. It’s important here to realize that the induction hypothesis does not say that there is some particular set of $n$ horses that are all the same color: it says that in any set of of $n$ horses, all of the horses are the same color.



          The argument fails only when $n=1$. In that case it fails because the sets $H_0=h_1$ and $H_1=h_2$ no longer overlap: there is no horse in both sets. Thus, while it’s true that all of the horses in $H_0$ are the same color and that all of the horses in $H_1$ are the same color, we can no longer infer that those two colors must be the same. But if we could somehow show that in every set of two horses, both horses were the same color, the induction argument as given would work just fine: we’d always be considering some $nge 2$, so the sets $H_0$ and $H_1$ would overlap.







          share|cite|improve this answer













          share|cite|improve this answer



          share|cite|improve this answer











          answered Jun 24 '13 at 20:41









          Brian M. Scott

          448k39492879




          448k39492879







          • 2




            Very clear explanation of the part that was confusing to the OP -- good work understanding what the OP's confusion was!
            – ShreevatsaR
            Jun 25 '13 at 6:12










          • Excellent explanation. I think this must have cleared up completely any doubt the OP could have had. +1
            – DonAntonio
            Jun 25 '13 at 6:15










          • @DonAntonio: Thanks, and to ShreevatsaR as well.
            – Brian M. Scott
            Jun 25 '13 at 6:18












          • 2




            Very clear explanation of the part that was confusing to the OP -- good work understanding what the OP's confusion was!
            – ShreevatsaR
            Jun 25 '13 at 6:12










          • Excellent explanation. I think this must have cleared up completely any doubt the OP could have had. +1
            – DonAntonio
            Jun 25 '13 at 6:15










          • @DonAntonio: Thanks, and to ShreevatsaR as well.
            – Brian M. Scott
            Jun 25 '13 at 6:18







          2




          2




          Very clear explanation of the part that was confusing to the OP -- good work understanding what the OP's confusion was!
          – ShreevatsaR
          Jun 25 '13 at 6:12




          Very clear explanation of the part that was confusing to the OP -- good work understanding what the OP's confusion was!
          – ShreevatsaR
          Jun 25 '13 at 6:12












          Excellent explanation. I think this must have cleared up completely any doubt the OP could have had. +1
          – DonAntonio
          Jun 25 '13 at 6:15




          Excellent explanation. I think this must have cleared up completely any doubt the OP could have had. +1
          – DonAntonio
          Jun 25 '13 at 6:15












          @DonAntonio: Thanks, and to ShreevatsaR as well.
          – Brian M. Scott
          Jun 25 '13 at 6:18




          @DonAntonio: Thanks, and to ShreevatsaR as well.
          – Brian M. Scott
          Jun 25 '13 at 6:18










          up vote
          10
          down vote













          I'm not sure I understand fully your doubt, but the actual problem with that, and many other examples of bogus inductive proofs out there, is that when you take the two sets



          $$h_1,...,h_n;,;;h_2,...,h_n,h_n+1$$



          each of size $,n,$ and thus, by the Ind. Hypothesis, formed of horses of the same color, the leap to deduce all the horses altogether have the same color requires that the intersection of both sets above is not empty, something you can't prove (because it is false!) if $,n=2,$



          Thus, if we had the claim "every two horse whatsoever are of the same color", then we could prove "all the horses are of the same color"






          share|cite|improve this answer





















          • $n=1$, maybe, since otherwise they share $h_2$.
            – Arthur
            Jun 24 '13 at 9:16










          • No, for $,n=1,$ it works trivially. For $,n=2,$ we have the huge problem: each of the sets $,h_1;,;h_2;$ have all the horses of the same color, then (this is the bogus part) also $,h_1,h_2,$ has horses of the same color. From this impasse the whole thing crumbles down in this case.
            – DonAntonio
            Jun 24 '13 at 9:30










          • @DonAntonio, what is meant is that it works if you have P(2) as a base case. Then, you have the same setup where you prove that for an arb. n >= 2, p(n) -> p(n+1). Then for the first n, n = 2, P(n) gives h1, h2 p(n+1) gives h1, h2, h3, and they share h2... My issue was that p(n+1) could also be h4, h5, h6, of which this proof doesn't address, but I guess after more thinking, it is obvious, that you add any element whatsoever to a set of 2, and it must be the same color, so all must be the same color. I just don't know how acceptable it would be without something more to it.
            – MVTC
            Jun 24 '13 at 10:10







          • 1




            But the above is assuming you could use and prove P(2) as a base case, which you can't.
            – MVTC
            Jun 24 '13 at 10:17











          • @DonAntonio I mean where you say "the intersection of both sets above is not empty, something you can't prove (because it is false!) if $n=2$." Here $n$ should be equal to $1$, otherwise the intersection contains $h_2$. That is what I meant. In the case $n=1$, you have two sets of uniform horses with empty intersection, thus you cannot go through with the induction step.
            – Arthur
            Jun 24 '13 at 10:24















          up vote
          10
          down vote













          I'm not sure I understand fully your doubt, but the actual problem with that, and many other examples of bogus inductive proofs out there, is that when you take the two sets



          $$h_1,...,h_n;,;;h_2,...,h_n,h_n+1$$



          each of size $,n,$ and thus, by the Ind. Hypothesis, formed of horses of the same color, the leap to deduce all the horses altogether have the same color requires that the intersection of both sets above is not empty, something you can't prove (because it is false!) if $,n=2,$



          Thus, if we had the claim "every two horse whatsoever are of the same color", then we could prove "all the horses are of the same color"






          share|cite|improve this answer





















          • $n=1$, maybe, since otherwise they share $h_2$.
            – Arthur
            Jun 24 '13 at 9:16










          • No, for $,n=1,$ it works trivially. For $,n=2,$ we have the huge problem: each of the sets $,h_1;,;h_2;$ have all the horses of the same color, then (this is the bogus part) also $,h_1,h_2,$ has horses of the same color. From this impasse the whole thing crumbles down in this case.
            – DonAntonio
            Jun 24 '13 at 9:30










          • @DonAntonio, what is meant is that it works if you have P(2) as a base case. Then, you have the same setup where you prove that for an arb. n >= 2, p(n) -> p(n+1). Then for the first n, n = 2, P(n) gives h1, h2 p(n+1) gives h1, h2, h3, and they share h2... My issue was that p(n+1) could also be h4, h5, h6, of which this proof doesn't address, but I guess after more thinking, it is obvious, that you add any element whatsoever to a set of 2, and it must be the same color, so all must be the same color. I just don't know how acceptable it would be without something more to it.
            – MVTC
            Jun 24 '13 at 10:10







          • 1




            But the above is assuming you could use and prove P(2) as a base case, which you can't.
            – MVTC
            Jun 24 '13 at 10:17











          • @DonAntonio I mean where you say "the intersection of both sets above is not empty, something you can't prove (because it is false!) if $n=2$." Here $n$ should be equal to $1$, otherwise the intersection contains $h_2$. That is what I meant. In the case $n=1$, you have two sets of uniform horses with empty intersection, thus you cannot go through with the induction step.
            – Arthur
            Jun 24 '13 at 10:24













          up vote
          10
          down vote










          up vote
          10
          down vote









          I'm not sure I understand fully your doubt, but the actual problem with that, and many other examples of bogus inductive proofs out there, is that when you take the two sets



          $$h_1,...,h_n;,;;h_2,...,h_n,h_n+1$$



          each of size $,n,$ and thus, by the Ind. Hypothesis, formed of horses of the same color, the leap to deduce all the horses altogether have the same color requires that the intersection of both sets above is not empty, something you can't prove (because it is false!) if $,n=2,$



          Thus, if we had the claim "every two horse whatsoever are of the same color", then we could prove "all the horses are of the same color"






          share|cite|improve this answer













          I'm not sure I understand fully your doubt, but the actual problem with that, and many other examples of bogus inductive proofs out there, is that when you take the two sets



          $$h_1,...,h_n;,;;h_2,...,h_n,h_n+1$$



          each of size $,n,$ and thus, by the Ind. Hypothesis, formed of horses of the same color, the leap to deduce all the horses altogether have the same color requires that the intersection of both sets above is not empty, something you can't prove (because it is false!) if $,n=2,$



          Thus, if we had the claim "every two horse whatsoever are of the same color", then we could prove "all the horses are of the same color"







          share|cite|improve this answer













          share|cite|improve this answer



          share|cite|improve this answer











          answered Jun 24 '13 at 9:06









          DonAntonio

          172k1483217




          172k1483217











          • $n=1$, maybe, since otherwise they share $h_2$.
            – Arthur
            Jun 24 '13 at 9:16










          • No, for $,n=1,$ it works trivially. For $,n=2,$ we have the huge problem: each of the sets $,h_1;,;h_2;$ have all the horses of the same color, then (this is the bogus part) also $,h_1,h_2,$ has horses of the same color. From this impasse the whole thing crumbles down in this case.
            – DonAntonio
            Jun 24 '13 at 9:30










          • @DonAntonio, what is meant is that it works if you have P(2) as a base case. Then, you have the same setup where you prove that for an arb. n >= 2, p(n) -> p(n+1). Then for the first n, n = 2, P(n) gives h1, h2 p(n+1) gives h1, h2, h3, and they share h2... My issue was that p(n+1) could also be h4, h5, h6, of which this proof doesn't address, but I guess after more thinking, it is obvious, that you add any element whatsoever to a set of 2, and it must be the same color, so all must be the same color. I just don't know how acceptable it would be without something more to it.
            – MVTC
            Jun 24 '13 at 10:10







          • 1




            But the above is assuming you could use and prove P(2) as a base case, which you can't.
            – MVTC
            Jun 24 '13 at 10:17











          • @DonAntonio I mean where you say "the intersection of both sets above is not empty, something you can't prove (because it is false!) if $n=2$." Here $n$ should be equal to $1$, otherwise the intersection contains $h_2$. That is what I meant. In the case $n=1$, you have two sets of uniform horses with empty intersection, thus you cannot go through with the induction step.
            – Arthur
            Jun 24 '13 at 10:24

















          • $n=1$, maybe, since otherwise they share $h_2$.
            – Arthur
            Jun 24 '13 at 9:16










          • No, for $,n=1,$ it works trivially. For $,n=2,$ we have the huge problem: each of the sets $,h_1;,;h_2;$ have all the horses of the same color, then (this is the bogus part) also $,h_1,h_2,$ has horses of the same color. From this impasse the whole thing crumbles down in this case.
            – DonAntonio
            Jun 24 '13 at 9:30










          • @DonAntonio, what is meant is that it works if you have P(2) as a base case. Then, you have the same setup where you prove that for an arb. n >= 2, p(n) -> p(n+1). Then for the first n, n = 2, P(n) gives h1, h2 p(n+1) gives h1, h2, h3, and they share h2... My issue was that p(n+1) could also be h4, h5, h6, of which this proof doesn't address, but I guess after more thinking, it is obvious, that you add any element whatsoever to a set of 2, and it must be the same color, so all must be the same color. I just don't know how acceptable it would be without something more to it.
            – MVTC
            Jun 24 '13 at 10:10







          • 1




            But the above is assuming you could use and prove P(2) as a base case, which you can't.
            – MVTC
            Jun 24 '13 at 10:17











          • @DonAntonio I mean where you say "the intersection of both sets above is not empty, something you can't prove (because it is false!) if $n=2$." Here $n$ should be equal to $1$, otherwise the intersection contains $h_2$. That is what I meant. In the case $n=1$, you have two sets of uniform horses with empty intersection, thus you cannot go through with the induction step.
            – Arthur
            Jun 24 '13 at 10:24
















          $n=1$, maybe, since otherwise they share $h_2$.
          – Arthur
          Jun 24 '13 at 9:16




          $n=1$, maybe, since otherwise they share $h_2$.
          – Arthur
          Jun 24 '13 at 9:16












          No, for $,n=1,$ it works trivially. For $,n=2,$ we have the huge problem: each of the sets $,h_1;,;h_2;$ have all the horses of the same color, then (this is the bogus part) also $,h_1,h_2,$ has horses of the same color. From this impasse the whole thing crumbles down in this case.
          – DonAntonio
          Jun 24 '13 at 9:30




          No, for $,n=1,$ it works trivially. For $,n=2,$ we have the huge problem: each of the sets $,h_1;,;h_2;$ have all the horses of the same color, then (this is the bogus part) also $,h_1,h_2,$ has horses of the same color. From this impasse the whole thing crumbles down in this case.
          – DonAntonio
          Jun 24 '13 at 9:30












          @DonAntonio, what is meant is that it works if you have P(2) as a base case. Then, you have the same setup where you prove that for an arb. n >= 2, p(n) -> p(n+1). Then for the first n, n = 2, P(n) gives h1, h2 p(n+1) gives h1, h2, h3, and they share h2... My issue was that p(n+1) could also be h4, h5, h6, of which this proof doesn't address, but I guess after more thinking, it is obvious, that you add any element whatsoever to a set of 2, and it must be the same color, so all must be the same color. I just don't know how acceptable it would be without something more to it.
          – MVTC
          Jun 24 '13 at 10:10





          @DonAntonio, what is meant is that it works if you have P(2) as a base case. Then, you have the same setup where you prove that for an arb. n >= 2, p(n) -> p(n+1). Then for the first n, n = 2, P(n) gives h1, h2 p(n+1) gives h1, h2, h3, and they share h2... My issue was that p(n+1) could also be h4, h5, h6, of which this proof doesn't address, but I guess after more thinking, it is obvious, that you add any element whatsoever to a set of 2, and it must be the same color, so all must be the same color. I just don't know how acceptable it would be without something more to it.
          – MVTC
          Jun 24 '13 at 10:10





          1




          1




          But the above is assuming you could use and prove P(2) as a base case, which you can't.
          – MVTC
          Jun 24 '13 at 10:17





          But the above is assuming you could use and prove P(2) as a base case, which you can't.
          – MVTC
          Jun 24 '13 at 10:17













          @DonAntonio I mean where you say "the intersection of both sets above is not empty, something you can't prove (because it is false!) if $n=2$." Here $n$ should be equal to $1$, otherwise the intersection contains $h_2$. That is what I meant. In the case $n=1$, you have two sets of uniform horses with empty intersection, thus you cannot go through with the induction step.
          – Arthur
          Jun 24 '13 at 10:24





          @DonAntonio I mean where you say "the intersection of both sets above is not empty, something you can't prove (because it is false!) if $n=2$." Here $n$ should be equal to $1$, otherwise the intersection contains $h_2$. That is what I meant. In the case $n=1$, you have two sets of uniform horses with empty intersection, thus you cannot go through with the induction step.
          – Arthur
          Jun 24 '13 at 10:24











          up vote
          0
          down vote













          There is a more basic problem here : induction is irrelevant to the proof.



          $P(2)$ is, by itself, a formalization of the statement that all horses are the same color. There is no reason to prove $P(2)$ to prove $P(3)$ to prove ... $P(n)$ and conclude from this chain of implications that all horses are the same color; one would try to prove $P(2)$ and in case of success, summarize that as "all horses have the same color".



          If proving $P(n)$ were of interest for some reason, it can be derived in one step from $P(2)$, with no need for an induction.



          The size of the set of horses is usually ignored in presentations of this argument and ones like it. But if there are $n$ horses in the universe, $P(k)$ is an empty statement for $k>n$, and is true regardless of the truth value $P(n)$. This shows that $P(n)$ is logically stronger than $P(n+1)$, and that the inductive step from $P(n) $ to $P(n+1)$ is vacuous for large $n$.






          share|cite|improve this answer

























            up vote
            0
            down vote













            There is a more basic problem here : induction is irrelevant to the proof.



            $P(2)$ is, by itself, a formalization of the statement that all horses are the same color. There is no reason to prove $P(2)$ to prove $P(3)$ to prove ... $P(n)$ and conclude from this chain of implications that all horses are the same color; one would try to prove $P(2)$ and in case of success, summarize that as "all horses have the same color".



            If proving $P(n)$ were of interest for some reason, it can be derived in one step from $P(2)$, with no need for an induction.



            The size of the set of horses is usually ignored in presentations of this argument and ones like it. But if there are $n$ horses in the universe, $P(k)$ is an empty statement for $k>n$, and is true regardless of the truth value $P(n)$. This shows that $P(n)$ is logically stronger than $P(n+1)$, and that the inductive step from $P(n) $ to $P(n+1)$ is vacuous for large $n$.






            share|cite|improve this answer























              up vote
              0
              down vote










              up vote
              0
              down vote









              There is a more basic problem here : induction is irrelevant to the proof.



              $P(2)$ is, by itself, a formalization of the statement that all horses are the same color. There is no reason to prove $P(2)$ to prove $P(3)$ to prove ... $P(n)$ and conclude from this chain of implications that all horses are the same color; one would try to prove $P(2)$ and in case of success, summarize that as "all horses have the same color".



              If proving $P(n)$ were of interest for some reason, it can be derived in one step from $P(2)$, with no need for an induction.



              The size of the set of horses is usually ignored in presentations of this argument and ones like it. But if there are $n$ horses in the universe, $P(k)$ is an empty statement for $k>n$, and is true regardless of the truth value $P(n)$. This shows that $P(n)$ is logically stronger than $P(n+1)$, and that the inductive step from $P(n) $ to $P(n+1)$ is vacuous for large $n$.






              share|cite|improve this answer













              There is a more basic problem here : induction is irrelevant to the proof.



              $P(2)$ is, by itself, a formalization of the statement that all horses are the same color. There is no reason to prove $P(2)$ to prove $P(3)$ to prove ... $P(n)$ and conclude from this chain of implications that all horses are the same color; one would try to prove $P(2)$ and in case of success, summarize that as "all horses have the same color".



              If proving $P(n)$ were of interest for some reason, it can be derived in one step from $P(2)$, with no need for an induction.



              The size of the set of horses is usually ignored in presentations of this argument and ones like it. But if there are $n$ horses in the universe, $P(k)$ is an empty statement for $k>n$, and is true regardless of the truth value $P(n)$. This shows that $P(n)$ is logically stronger than $P(n+1)$, and that the inductive step from $P(n) $ to $P(n+1)$ is vacuous for large $n$.







              share|cite|improve this answer













              share|cite|improve this answer



              share|cite|improve this answer











              answered Jun 25 '13 at 5:21









              zyx

              31k33697




              31k33697




















                  up vote
                  0
                  down vote













                  As you pointed out, $P(1)$ is trivially true. And you are trying to prove $$P(n)implies P(n+1)$$ to finish the proof. But It's clear that $P(1)$ does NOT implies $P(2)$. Thus the statement $$P(n)implies P(n+1)$$ is not true. And this is where your proof falls.






                  share|cite|improve this answer

























                    up vote
                    0
                    down vote













                    As you pointed out, $P(1)$ is trivially true. And you are trying to prove $$P(n)implies P(n+1)$$ to finish the proof. But It's clear that $P(1)$ does NOT implies $P(2)$. Thus the statement $$P(n)implies P(n+1)$$ is not true. And this is where your proof falls.






                    share|cite|improve this answer























                      up vote
                      0
                      down vote










                      up vote
                      0
                      down vote









                      As you pointed out, $P(1)$ is trivially true. And you are trying to prove $$P(n)implies P(n+1)$$ to finish the proof. But It's clear that $P(1)$ does NOT implies $P(2)$. Thus the statement $$P(n)implies P(n+1)$$ is not true. And this is where your proof falls.






                      share|cite|improve this answer













                      As you pointed out, $P(1)$ is trivially true. And you are trying to prove $$P(n)implies P(n+1)$$ to finish the proof. But It's clear that $P(1)$ does NOT implies $P(2)$. Thus the statement $$P(n)implies P(n+1)$$ is not true. And this is where your proof falls.







                      share|cite|improve this answer













                      share|cite|improve this answer



                      share|cite|improve this answer











                      answered Jul 31 at 5:49









                      Le Anh Dung

                      740317




                      740317




















                          up vote
                          -1
                          down vote













                          I just had a student come to me with this problem. I am not a mathematician by trade, so this was the first I'd heard of it. (It's a very good problem that forces the student to understand the method!)



                          My natural inclination was to negate that which was supposedly proven ("all horses are the same color"), and take the "contrapositive" of the entire inductive chain, and see if we do necessarily contradict the base case. (In other words, the inductive argument supposedly gives $P(1) Rightarrow P(2) Rightarrow cdotsRightarrow P$; I wanted to see if $neg P Rightarrow cdots Rightarrow neg P(2) Rightarrow neg P(1) $.)



                          So, right off the bat, the negation of "all horses are the same color" is "there exists horse A and horse B such that A is a different color than B". From that, you immediately see that $P(1)$ is unsuitable base case because $neg P(2)$ means "in a set of 2 horses, the two hoses are different colors". That does not contradict anything about $P(1)$ (which of course is logically unimpeachable).



                          What also comes out in the above line of reasoning confirms what @zyx said: induction is irrelevant to the statement being proven. At every step, the condition that the statement be false hinges on the existence of two different horses having different colors. So, if you had somehow shown $P(2)$ to be true, game over.






                          share|cite|improve this answer



























                            up vote
                            -1
                            down vote













                            I just had a student come to me with this problem. I am not a mathematician by trade, so this was the first I'd heard of it. (It's a very good problem that forces the student to understand the method!)



                            My natural inclination was to negate that which was supposedly proven ("all horses are the same color"), and take the "contrapositive" of the entire inductive chain, and see if we do necessarily contradict the base case. (In other words, the inductive argument supposedly gives $P(1) Rightarrow P(2) Rightarrow cdotsRightarrow P$; I wanted to see if $neg P Rightarrow cdots Rightarrow neg P(2) Rightarrow neg P(1) $.)



                            So, right off the bat, the negation of "all horses are the same color" is "there exists horse A and horse B such that A is a different color than B". From that, you immediately see that $P(1)$ is unsuitable base case because $neg P(2)$ means "in a set of 2 horses, the two hoses are different colors". That does not contradict anything about $P(1)$ (which of course is logically unimpeachable).



                            What also comes out in the above line of reasoning confirms what @zyx said: induction is irrelevant to the statement being proven. At every step, the condition that the statement be false hinges on the existence of two different horses having different colors. So, if you had somehow shown $P(2)$ to be true, game over.






                            share|cite|improve this answer

























                              up vote
                              -1
                              down vote










                              up vote
                              -1
                              down vote









                              I just had a student come to me with this problem. I am not a mathematician by trade, so this was the first I'd heard of it. (It's a very good problem that forces the student to understand the method!)



                              My natural inclination was to negate that which was supposedly proven ("all horses are the same color"), and take the "contrapositive" of the entire inductive chain, and see if we do necessarily contradict the base case. (In other words, the inductive argument supposedly gives $P(1) Rightarrow P(2) Rightarrow cdotsRightarrow P$; I wanted to see if $neg P Rightarrow cdots Rightarrow neg P(2) Rightarrow neg P(1) $.)



                              So, right off the bat, the negation of "all horses are the same color" is "there exists horse A and horse B such that A is a different color than B". From that, you immediately see that $P(1)$ is unsuitable base case because $neg P(2)$ means "in a set of 2 horses, the two hoses are different colors". That does not contradict anything about $P(1)$ (which of course is logically unimpeachable).



                              What also comes out in the above line of reasoning confirms what @zyx said: induction is irrelevant to the statement being proven. At every step, the condition that the statement be false hinges on the existence of two different horses having different colors. So, if you had somehow shown $P(2)$ to be true, game over.






                              share|cite|improve this answer















                              I just had a student come to me with this problem. I am not a mathematician by trade, so this was the first I'd heard of it. (It's a very good problem that forces the student to understand the method!)



                              My natural inclination was to negate that which was supposedly proven ("all horses are the same color"), and take the "contrapositive" of the entire inductive chain, and see if we do necessarily contradict the base case. (In other words, the inductive argument supposedly gives $P(1) Rightarrow P(2) Rightarrow cdotsRightarrow P$; I wanted to see if $neg P Rightarrow cdots Rightarrow neg P(2) Rightarrow neg P(1) $.)



                              So, right off the bat, the negation of "all horses are the same color" is "there exists horse A and horse B such that A is a different color than B". From that, you immediately see that $P(1)$ is unsuitable base case because $neg P(2)$ means "in a set of 2 horses, the two hoses are different colors". That does not contradict anything about $P(1)$ (which of course is logically unimpeachable).



                              What also comes out in the above line of reasoning confirms what @zyx said: induction is irrelevant to the statement being proven. At every step, the condition that the statement be false hinges on the existence of two different horses having different colors. So, if you had somehow shown $P(2)$ to be true, game over.







                              share|cite|improve this answer















                              share|cite|improve this answer



                              share|cite|improve this answer








                              edited Jul 1 '16 at 22:18


























                              answered Jul 1 '16 at 22:03









                              user3337629

                              592




                              592




















                                  up vote
                                  -2
                                  down vote













                                  Just want to add a quick summary.



                                  The proof is "almost" perfect. It simply fails on n=1.



                                  Yes obviously any set with 1 horse will have the same color. However, you can't extend that to n=2.



                                  If you can somehow proof that any set of 2 horses have the same color then yes, you got something right, that any set with any number of horses will have the same color.






                                  share|cite|improve this answer

























                                    up vote
                                    -2
                                    down vote













                                    Just want to add a quick summary.



                                    The proof is "almost" perfect. It simply fails on n=1.



                                    Yes obviously any set with 1 horse will have the same color. However, you can't extend that to n=2.



                                    If you can somehow proof that any set of 2 horses have the same color then yes, you got something right, that any set with any number of horses will have the same color.






                                    share|cite|improve this answer























                                      up vote
                                      -2
                                      down vote










                                      up vote
                                      -2
                                      down vote









                                      Just want to add a quick summary.



                                      The proof is "almost" perfect. It simply fails on n=1.



                                      Yes obviously any set with 1 horse will have the same color. However, you can't extend that to n=2.



                                      If you can somehow proof that any set of 2 horses have the same color then yes, you got something right, that any set with any number of horses will have the same color.






                                      share|cite|improve this answer













                                      Just want to add a quick summary.



                                      The proof is "almost" perfect. It simply fails on n=1.



                                      Yes obviously any set with 1 horse will have the same color. However, you can't extend that to n=2.



                                      If you can somehow proof that any set of 2 horses have the same color then yes, you got something right, that any set with any number of horses will have the same color.







                                      share|cite|improve this answer













                                      share|cite|improve this answer



                                      share|cite|improve this answer











                                      answered Aug 15 '16 at 9:49









                                      J. Chang

                                      7701614




                                      7701614






















                                           

                                          draft saved


                                          draft discarded


























                                           


                                          draft saved


                                          draft discarded














                                          StackExchange.ready(
                                          function ()
                                          StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmath.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f428151%2fquestions-on-all-horse-are-the-same-color-proof-by-complete-induction%23new-answer', 'question_page');

                                          );

                                          Post as a guest













































































                                          Comments

                                          Popular posts from this blog

                                          What is the equation of a 3D cone with generalised tilt?

                                          Color the edges and diagonals of a regular polygon

                                          Relationship between determinant of matrix and determinant of adjoint?