Why is the Hilbert-Bernays paradox paradoxical?

The name of the pictureThe name of the pictureThe name of the pictureClash Royale CLAN TAG#URR8PPP











up vote
4
down vote

favorite












The Hilbert-Bernays Paradox is produced by defining h as '(the referent of h) + 1'. Why is this a paradox? It seems strange to believe that we could define h in terms of itself. I suspect I'm missing some context, but I can't find anything else about this paradox online that isn't pay-walled.







share|cite|improve this question

























    up vote
    4
    down vote

    favorite












    The Hilbert-Bernays Paradox is produced by defining h as '(the referent of h) + 1'. Why is this a paradox? It seems strange to believe that we could define h in terms of itself. I suspect I'm missing some context, but I can't find anything else about this paradox online that isn't pay-walled.







    share|cite|improve this question























      up vote
      4
      down vote

      favorite









      up vote
      4
      down vote

      favorite











      The Hilbert-Bernays Paradox is produced by defining h as '(the referent of h) + 1'. Why is this a paradox? It seems strange to believe that we could define h in terms of itself. I suspect I'm missing some context, but I can't find anything else about this paradox online that isn't pay-walled.







      share|cite|improve this question













      The Hilbert-Bernays Paradox is produced by defining h as '(the referent of h) + 1'. Why is this a paradox? It seems strange to believe that we could define h in terms of itself. I suspect I'm missing some context, but I can't find anything else about this paradox online that isn't pay-walled.









      share|cite|improve this question












      share|cite|improve this question




      share|cite|improve this question








      edited Jul 20 at 8:22
























      asked Jul 18 at 0:40









      Casebash

      5,50634070




      5,50634070




















          1 Answer
          1






          active

          oldest

          votes

















          up vote
          4
          down vote



          accepted










          I find the wiki article somewhat confusing. I don't have my copy of the Grundlagen at hand at the moment, but I think the wiki article has actually botched the phrasing of the paragraph. Below I'll first re-summarize the Liar (just for completeness and clarity), give my gloss on the HBG, and end by saying a bit about how reference and truth are related.




          First, let's go back to something well-known. The classical Liar Paradox




          $(*)quad$This statement is false




          shows that we cannot sustain classical logic, consistency (= non-triviality, given$^*$ classical logic), self-reference, and a(n internal) truth definition. If we have self-reference and a definition of truth, we can formula $(*)$, and classical logic then leads us to inconsistency since we can deduce both $(*)$ and $neg(*)$. Phrased this way, the Liar isn't really a paradox, it's a theorem about the limitations of logical systems. In light of the diagonal lemma, which permits (certain kinds of) self-reference in arithmetic, the Liar yields Tarski's theorem on the undefinability of truth; with an additional twist (replacing "truth" with "provability" - fine, and then applying an additional technical trick), we get Godel's first incompleteness theorem.




          OK, now what about the Hilbert-Bernays Paradox? As far as I can tell, as phrased by the wiki article it's not actually a problem, but it can be easily modified to be nasty:




          $(sharp)quad$ $1+n$, if the referent of this expression is $n$, and $0$ if this expression has no referent.




          Note this second clause: merely saying "Oh, $(sharp)$ doesn't have a referent" doesn't save us now! What we're looking at is very reminiscent of the Liar, $(*)$, above. This time it yields the following theorem: that we cannot sustain classical logic, consistency (= non-triviality, given$^*$ classical logic), self-reference, and a(n internally) definable "referent functor" (= a way to say "the referent of ---" in the internal language).



          My own instinct - and I think I'm not too rare in this - is to be suspicious of the role of self-reference. But just like in the case of the Liar, the diagonal lemma tells us that (in arithmetic at least) we actually do have enough self-referential ability to get into hot water! So in "reasonable" logical contexts (= nontrivial classically-founded computably-axiomatizable theories strong enough to support arithmetic), we conclude that the problem lies with defining "reference" (just as the Liar, via Tarski, showed that the real problem in arithmetic is defining "truth").




          Note that truth and reference are (unsurprisingly) closely related in the context of arithmetic:



          • Given a sentence $varphi$, consider the expression "$0$ if $varphi$, $1$ if not $varphi$;" if we know the referent for this expression, then we know whether $varphi$ is true or not.


          • Given a formula $p(x)$, consider the sentences $p(0)$, $p(1)$, $p(2)$, $p(3)$, ... Exactly one of these is true, and if we know which is true then we know the referent of the expression "the unique $x$ satisfying $p$."


          In general, reference is more powerful than truth, however, since the domain we live in may not consist only of definable elements (so we won't be able to "search through it" for the referent as we did in the second bulletpoint above). Given this, we can actually say that in a sense $(sharp)$ is "more basic" than $(*)$.




          $^*$It's worth observing that in weaker logical systems, a single inconsistency doesn't necessarily lead to explosion. If we don't insist on classical logic, we can have nontrivial logical systems which have inconsistencies. The relevant term here is paraconsistency, and one response to the various semantic paradoxes like the Liar is to work with them, inside a paraconsistent system.






          share|cite|improve this answer























            Your Answer




            StackExchange.ifUsing("editor", function ()
            return StackExchange.using("mathjaxEditing", function ()
            StackExchange.MarkdownEditor.creationCallbacks.add(function (editor, postfix)
            StackExchange.mathjaxEditing.prepareWmdForMathJax(editor, postfix, [["$", "$"], ["\\(","\\)"]]);
            );
            );
            , "mathjax-editing");

            StackExchange.ready(function()
            var channelOptions =
            tags: "".split(" "),
            id: "69"
            ;
            initTagRenderer("".split(" "), "".split(" "), channelOptions);

            StackExchange.using("externalEditor", function()
            // Have to fire editor after snippets, if snippets enabled
            if (StackExchange.settings.snippets.snippetsEnabled)
            StackExchange.using("snippets", function()
            createEditor();
            );

            else
            createEditor();

            );

            function createEditor()
            StackExchange.prepareEditor(
            heartbeatType: 'answer',
            convertImagesToLinks: true,
            noModals: false,
            showLowRepImageUploadWarning: true,
            reputationToPostImages: 10,
            bindNavPrevention: true,
            postfix: "",
            noCode: true, onDemand: true,
            discardSelector: ".discard-answer"
            ,immediatelyShowMarkdownHelp:true
            );



            );








             

            draft saved


            draft discarded


















            StackExchange.ready(
            function ()
            StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmath.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f2855061%2fwhy-is-the-hilbert-bernays-paradox-paradoxical%23new-answer', 'question_page');

            );

            Post as a guest






























            1 Answer
            1






            active

            oldest

            votes








            1 Answer
            1






            active

            oldest

            votes









            active

            oldest

            votes






            active

            oldest

            votes








            up vote
            4
            down vote



            accepted










            I find the wiki article somewhat confusing. I don't have my copy of the Grundlagen at hand at the moment, but I think the wiki article has actually botched the phrasing of the paragraph. Below I'll first re-summarize the Liar (just for completeness and clarity), give my gloss on the HBG, and end by saying a bit about how reference and truth are related.




            First, let's go back to something well-known. The classical Liar Paradox




            $(*)quad$This statement is false




            shows that we cannot sustain classical logic, consistency (= non-triviality, given$^*$ classical logic), self-reference, and a(n internal) truth definition. If we have self-reference and a definition of truth, we can formula $(*)$, and classical logic then leads us to inconsistency since we can deduce both $(*)$ and $neg(*)$. Phrased this way, the Liar isn't really a paradox, it's a theorem about the limitations of logical systems. In light of the diagonal lemma, which permits (certain kinds of) self-reference in arithmetic, the Liar yields Tarski's theorem on the undefinability of truth; with an additional twist (replacing "truth" with "provability" - fine, and then applying an additional technical trick), we get Godel's first incompleteness theorem.




            OK, now what about the Hilbert-Bernays Paradox? As far as I can tell, as phrased by the wiki article it's not actually a problem, but it can be easily modified to be nasty:




            $(sharp)quad$ $1+n$, if the referent of this expression is $n$, and $0$ if this expression has no referent.




            Note this second clause: merely saying "Oh, $(sharp)$ doesn't have a referent" doesn't save us now! What we're looking at is very reminiscent of the Liar, $(*)$, above. This time it yields the following theorem: that we cannot sustain classical logic, consistency (= non-triviality, given$^*$ classical logic), self-reference, and a(n internally) definable "referent functor" (= a way to say "the referent of ---" in the internal language).



            My own instinct - and I think I'm not too rare in this - is to be suspicious of the role of self-reference. But just like in the case of the Liar, the diagonal lemma tells us that (in arithmetic at least) we actually do have enough self-referential ability to get into hot water! So in "reasonable" logical contexts (= nontrivial classically-founded computably-axiomatizable theories strong enough to support arithmetic), we conclude that the problem lies with defining "reference" (just as the Liar, via Tarski, showed that the real problem in arithmetic is defining "truth").




            Note that truth and reference are (unsurprisingly) closely related in the context of arithmetic:



            • Given a sentence $varphi$, consider the expression "$0$ if $varphi$, $1$ if not $varphi$;" if we know the referent for this expression, then we know whether $varphi$ is true or not.


            • Given a formula $p(x)$, consider the sentences $p(0)$, $p(1)$, $p(2)$, $p(3)$, ... Exactly one of these is true, and if we know which is true then we know the referent of the expression "the unique $x$ satisfying $p$."


            In general, reference is more powerful than truth, however, since the domain we live in may not consist only of definable elements (so we won't be able to "search through it" for the referent as we did in the second bulletpoint above). Given this, we can actually say that in a sense $(sharp)$ is "more basic" than $(*)$.




            $^*$It's worth observing that in weaker logical systems, a single inconsistency doesn't necessarily lead to explosion. If we don't insist on classical logic, we can have nontrivial logical systems which have inconsistencies. The relevant term here is paraconsistency, and one response to the various semantic paradoxes like the Liar is to work with them, inside a paraconsistent system.






            share|cite|improve this answer



























              up vote
              4
              down vote



              accepted










              I find the wiki article somewhat confusing. I don't have my copy of the Grundlagen at hand at the moment, but I think the wiki article has actually botched the phrasing of the paragraph. Below I'll first re-summarize the Liar (just for completeness and clarity), give my gloss on the HBG, and end by saying a bit about how reference and truth are related.




              First, let's go back to something well-known. The classical Liar Paradox




              $(*)quad$This statement is false




              shows that we cannot sustain classical logic, consistency (= non-triviality, given$^*$ classical logic), self-reference, and a(n internal) truth definition. If we have self-reference and a definition of truth, we can formula $(*)$, and classical logic then leads us to inconsistency since we can deduce both $(*)$ and $neg(*)$. Phrased this way, the Liar isn't really a paradox, it's a theorem about the limitations of logical systems. In light of the diagonal lemma, which permits (certain kinds of) self-reference in arithmetic, the Liar yields Tarski's theorem on the undefinability of truth; with an additional twist (replacing "truth" with "provability" - fine, and then applying an additional technical trick), we get Godel's first incompleteness theorem.




              OK, now what about the Hilbert-Bernays Paradox? As far as I can tell, as phrased by the wiki article it's not actually a problem, but it can be easily modified to be nasty:




              $(sharp)quad$ $1+n$, if the referent of this expression is $n$, and $0$ if this expression has no referent.




              Note this second clause: merely saying "Oh, $(sharp)$ doesn't have a referent" doesn't save us now! What we're looking at is very reminiscent of the Liar, $(*)$, above. This time it yields the following theorem: that we cannot sustain classical logic, consistency (= non-triviality, given$^*$ classical logic), self-reference, and a(n internally) definable "referent functor" (= a way to say "the referent of ---" in the internal language).



              My own instinct - and I think I'm not too rare in this - is to be suspicious of the role of self-reference. But just like in the case of the Liar, the diagonal lemma tells us that (in arithmetic at least) we actually do have enough self-referential ability to get into hot water! So in "reasonable" logical contexts (= nontrivial classically-founded computably-axiomatizable theories strong enough to support arithmetic), we conclude that the problem lies with defining "reference" (just as the Liar, via Tarski, showed that the real problem in arithmetic is defining "truth").




              Note that truth and reference are (unsurprisingly) closely related in the context of arithmetic:



              • Given a sentence $varphi$, consider the expression "$0$ if $varphi$, $1$ if not $varphi$;" if we know the referent for this expression, then we know whether $varphi$ is true or not.


              • Given a formula $p(x)$, consider the sentences $p(0)$, $p(1)$, $p(2)$, $p(3)$, ... Exactly one of these is true, and if we know which is true then we know the referent of the expression "the unique $x$ satisfying $p$."


              In general, reference is more powerful than truth, however, since the domain we live in may not consist only of definable elements (so we won't be able to "search through it" for the referent as we did in the second bulletpoint above). Given this, we can actually say that in a sense $(sharp)$ is "more basic" than $(*)$.




              $^*$It's worth observing that in weaker logical systems, a single inconsistency doesn't necessarily lead to explosion. If we don't insist on classical logic, we can have nontrivial logical systems which have inconsistencies. The relevant term here is paraconsistency, and one response to the various semantic paradoxes like the Liar is to work with them, inside a paraconsistent system.






              share|cite|improve this answer

























                up vote
                4
                down vote



                accepted







                up vote
                4
                down vote



                accepted






                I find the wiki article somewhat confusing. I don't have my copy of the Grundlagen at hand at the moment, but I think the wiki article has actually botched the phrasing of the paragraph. Below I'll first re-summarize the Liar (just for completeness and clarity), give my gloss on the HBG, and end by saying a bit about how reference and truth are related.




                First, let's go back to something well-known. The classical Liar Paradox




                $(*)quad$This statement is false




                shows that we cannot sustain classical logic, consistency (= non-triviality, given$^*$ classical logic), self-reference, and a(n internal) truth definition. If we have self-reference and a definition of truth, we can formula $(*)$, and classical logic then leads us to inconsistency since we can deduce both $(*)$ and $neg(*)$. Phrased this way, the Liar isn't really a paradox, it's a theorem about the limitations of logical systems. In light of the diagonal lemma, which permits (certain kinds of) self-reference in arithmetic, the Liar yields Tarski's theorem on the undefinability of truth; with an additional twist (replacing "truth" with "provability" - fine, and then applying an additional technical trick), we get Godel's first incompleteness theorem.




                OK, now what about the Hilbert-Bernays Paradox? As far as I can tell, as phrased by the wiki article it's not actually a problem, but it can be easily modified to be nasty:




                $(sharp)quad$ $1+n$, if the referent of this expression is $n$, and $0$ if this expression has no referent.




                Note this second clause: merely saying "Oh, $(sharp)$ doesn't have a referent" doesn't save us now! What we're looking at is very reminiscent of the Liar, $(*)$, above. This time it yields the following theorem: that we cannot sustain classical logic, consistency (= non-triviality, given$^*$ classical logic), self-reference, and a(n internally) definable "referent functor" (= a way to say "the referent of ---" in the internal language).



                My own instinct - and I think I'm not too rare in this - is to be suspicious of the role of self-reference. But just like in the case of the Liar, the diagonal lemma tells us that (in arithmetic at least) we actually do have enough self-referential ability to get into hot water! So in "reasonable" logical contexts (= nontrivial classically-founded computably-axiomatizable theories strong enough to support arithmetic), we conclude that the problem lies with defining "reference" (just as the Liar, via Tarski, showed that the real problem in arithmetic is defining "truth").




                Note that truth and reference are (unsurprisingly) closely related in the context of arithmetic:



                • Given a sentence $varphi$, consider the expression "$0$ if $varphi$, $1$ if not $varphi$;" if we know the referent for this expression, then we know whether $varphi$ is true or not.


                • Given a formula $p(x)$, consider the sentences $p(0)$, $p(1)$, $p(2)$, $p(3)$, ... Exactly one of these is true, and if we know which is true then we know the referent of the expression "the unique $x$ satisfying $p$."


                In general, reference is more powerful than truth, however, since the domain we live in may not consist only of definable elements (so we won't be able to "search through it" for the referent as we did in the second bulletpoint above). Given this, we can actually say that in a sense $(sharp)$ is "more basic" than $(*)$.




                $^*$It's worth observing that in weaker logical systems, a single inconsistency doesn't necessarily lead to explosion. If we don't insist on classical logic, we can have nontrivial logical systems which have inconsistencies. The relevant term here is paraconsistency, and one response to the various semantic paradoxes like the Liar is to work with them, inside a paraconsistent system.






                share|cite|improve this answer















                I find the wiki article somewhat confusing. I don't have my copy of the Grundlagen at hand at the moment, but I think the wiki article has actually botched the phrasing of the paragraph. Below I'll first re-summarize the Liar (just for completeness and clarity), give my gloss on the HBG, and end by saying a bit about how reference and truth are related.




                First, let's go back to something well-known. The classical Liar Paradox




                $(*)quad$This statement is false




                shows that we cannot sustain classical logic, consistency (= non-triviality, given$^*$ classical logic), self-reference, and a(n internal) truth definition. If we have self-reference and a definition of truth, we can formula $(*)$, and classical logic then leads us to inconsistency since we can deduce both $(*)$ and $neg(*)$. Phrased this way, the Liar isn't really a paradox, it's a theorem about the limitations of logical systems. In light of the diagonal lemma, which permits (certain kinds of) self-reference in arithmetic, the Liar yields Tarski's theorem on the undefinability of truth; with an additional twist (replacing "truth" with "provability" - fine, and then applying an additional technical trick), we get Godel's first incompleteness theorem.




                OK, now what about the Hilbert-Bernays Paradox? As far as I can tell, as phrased by the wiki article it's not actually a problem, but it can be easily modified to be nasty:




                $(sharp)quad$ $1+n$, if the referent of this expression is $n$, and $0$ if this expression has no referent.




                Note this second clause: merely saying "Oh, $(sharp)$ doesn't have a referent" doesn't save us now! What we're looking at is very reminiscent of the Liar, $(*)$, above. This time it yields the following theorem: that we cannot sustain classical logic, consistency (= non-triviality, given$^*$ classical logic), self-reference, and a(n internally) definable "referent functor" (= a way to say "the referent of ---" in the internal language).



                My own instinct - and I think I'm not too rare in this - is to be suspicious of the role of self-reference. But just like in the case of the Liar, the diagonal lemma tells us that (in arithmetic at least) we actually do have enough self-referential ability to get into hot water! So in "reasonable" logical contexts (= nontrivial classically-founded computably-axiomatizable theories strong enough to support arithmetic), we conclude that the problem lies with defining "reference" (just as the Liar, via Tarski, showed that the real problem in arithmetic is defining "truth").




                Note that truth and reference are (unsurprisingly) closely related in the context of arithmetic:



                • Given a sentence $varphi$, consider the expression "$0$ if $varphi$, $1$ if not $varphi$;" if we know the referent for this expression, then we know whether $varphi$ is true or not.


                • Given a formula $p(x)$, consider the sentences $p(0)$, $p(1)$, $p(2)$, $p(3)$, ... Exactly one of these is true, and if we know which is true then we know the referent of the expression "the unique $x$ satisfying $p$."


                In general, reference is more powerful than truth, however, since the domain we live in may not consist only of definable elements (so we won't be able to "search through it" for the referent as we did in the second bulletpoint above). Given this, we can actually say that in a sense $(sharp)$ is "more basic" than $(*)$.




                $^*$It's worth observing that in weaker logical systems, a single inconsistency doesn't necessarily lead to explosion. If we don't insist on classical logic, we can have nontrivial logical systems which have inconsistencies. The relevant term here is paraconsistency, and one response to the various semantic paradoxes like the Liar is to work with them, inside a paraconsistent system.







                share|cite|improve this answer















                share|cite|improve this answer



                share|cite|improve this answer








                edited Jul 18 at 2:00


























                answered Jul 18 at 1:50









                Noah Schweber

                111k9140262




                111k9140262






















                     

                    draft saved


                    draft discarded


























                     


                    draft saved


                    draft discarded














                    StackExchange.ready(
                    function ()
                    StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmath.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f2855061%2fwhy-is-the-hilbert-bernays-paradox-paradoxical%23new-answer', 'question_page');

                    );

                    Post as a guest













































































                    Comments

                    Popular posts from this blog

                    What is the equation of a 3D cone with generalised tilt?

                    Color the edges and diagonals of a regular polygon

                    Relationship between determinant of matrix and determinant of adjoint?